Lovers of Sophia

Home > Other > Lovers of Sophia > Page 18
Lovers of Sophia Page 18

by Jason Reza Jorjani


  dimension would in any way invalidate the Quran’s ‘exoteric’ sharia.

  This is clear enough from the passage’s own exhortation to follow

  all of the foundational ‘clear verses’ rather than being perversely

  driven to obscure interpretation based on the mysterious ones. In

  conclusion, we see that there is no “true and limitless meaning of the Quran” to be fathomed by Muslims, as Ayoub describes the Shiite

  batin.17 If there is an ‘essence’ of Islam at al , it is concerned with a profound inner faith characterized by holy dread of Judgment and

  perpetual remembrance of God, one that does not challenge the

  exoteric dogmas or laws of the Quran but underlies their sincere observance. There is no evidence for any other kind of esoteric

  understanding of Islam in the Quran revealed through Muhammad.

  Now let us lay to rest the belief that Muhammad secretly

  initiated his cousin and son-in-law Ali ibn Abu Talib (4th Caliph)

  into a gnostic wisdom that is passed on in a silsila or “chain” from Imam to Imam and down onto the Sufi masters and founders of

  orders. The only way, if any, that this belief would be verified is if the vast corpus of sermons of Ali testified to his mystical understanding.

  Quite to the contrary Ali’s Nahjul Balagha shows just how literal y he subscribes to all of the most ridiculous and barbaric dogmas of

  the Quran.

  In Sermon 1 Ali describes how Al ah kneaded and molded

  Adam from different kinds of clay, dried him and blew into him to

  animate his mind and limbs. He then describes how all of the angels

  bowed to Adam at Al ah’s command, except for Iblis (Satan) – at

  17 Ayoub, “The Speaking Qur’an and the Silent Qur’an”, 182.

  141

  lovers of sophia

  which point he explicitly quotes the Quran. Ali then continues to describe Adam’s temptation by Iblis and his fall from Paradise, in

  which Al ah “sent him down to the place of trial and procreation of

  progeny” and promised him an ultimate return to the garden by way

  of pious action. There is nothing mystical about this at al . Neither

  is there anything mystical about Ali’s literal belief in the Quranic

  vision of Judgment Day and the resurrection. In Sermon 82 he says that “Al ah would bring them [people] out from the corners of the

  graves”, whereupon the resurrected will “run towards the place fixed

  for their final return, group by group, quiet, standing and arrayed

  in rows.” Final y, their “…ears would resound with the thundering

  voice of the announcer calling towards the final judgment, award of

  recompense, striking of punishment and paying of reward.” Later in

  the same sermon Ali emphasizes perpetual fear of God (rather than

  divine love) as the proper state of the true believer: “O’ creatures of Al ah, fear Al ah, like the fearing of the wise man whom the thought

  (of the next world) has turned away from other matters, fear (of

  Al ah) has afflicted his body with trouble and pain, his engagement

  in the night prayer has turned even his short sleep into awakening,

  hope of eternal recompense keeps him thirsty in the day…” Ali adds:

  “Certainly paradise is the best reward and achievement, and hell is

  appropriate punishment and suffering.”

  Hope of paradise and detailed descriptions of it that seduce the

  believer into earthly piety are just as much part and parcel of Ali’s

  teaching as of Muhammad’s. In Sermon 164 Ali says in light of the beauty of paradise this world and its desires and pleasures should

  seem cheap to the believer, whereupon he describes in detail “the

  rustling of the trees whose roots lie hidden in the mounds of musk

  on the banks of the rivers in Paradise and in the attraction of the

  bunches of fresh pearls in the twigs and branches of those trees, and

  in the appearance of different fruits from under the cover of their

  leaves. These fruits can be picked without difficulty as they come

  down at the desire of their pickers. Pure honey and fermented wine

  will be handed round to those who settle down in the courtyards of

  its palaces.”

  142

  jason reza jorjani

  Ali concludes with a statement that betrays the basis of Muslim

  piety is striving for the above described delights of paradise, a desire so intense that it makes one long to leave this world and go straight

  to the next: “O’ listener! If you busy yourself in advancing towards

  these wonderful scenes which will rush towards you, then your heart

  will certainly die due to eagerness for them, and you will be prepared to seek the company of those in the graves straight away from my

  audience here and hasten towards them.” In reading such passages

  we can easily understand the psychology of Muslim martyrdom, it

  being the only means to in fact go straight from this cheap world

  into the delights of the heavenly garden.

  Ali’s views on half of humanity are most un-mystical and in line

  with the barbarity of the Quran’s dark Surah on women. In Sermon 152 Ali speaks contemptuously of beasts, carnivores and women in the same breath when he says:

  “Beasts are concerned with their bellies. Carnivores are

  concerned with assaulting others. Women are concerned with

  the adornments of this ignoble life and the creation of mischief

  herein. On the other hand, believers are humble, believers are

  admonishers and believers are afraid of Al ah.”

  The last part of this statement takes the degradation of women even

  further than the Quran by shockingly suggesting that only men

  are spiritual y and intellectual y fit to be ‘believers’. Like a beast, a woman is also incapable of true faith. In Sermon 79 Ali employs a ridiculously circular argument that condemns women for the very

  strictures that the Quran binds them with in the first place:

  “O’ ye peoples! Women are deficient in Faith, deficient in shares

  and deficient in intelligence. As regards the deficiency in their

  Faith, it is their abstention from prayers and fasting during their

  menstrual period. As regards deficiency in their intelligence, it is

  because the evidence of two women is equal to that of one man.

  As for the deficiency of their shares that is because of their share

  in inheritance being half of men.”

  143

  lovers of sophia

  Ali concludes this statement with a warning to believers never to

  listen to a woman or heed to her wishes, even if it seems that she

  is right. This verse offers the perfect compliment to the Quran’s

  infamous verse (quoted above) concerning women’s duty to obey

  men because of the latter’s superiority:

  “So beware of the evils of women. Be on your guard even from

  those of them who are (reportedly) good. Do not obey them

  even in good things so that they may not attract you to evils.”

  Not only does Ali literal y reiterate and uphold every major dogma

  of the Quran, he also believes that the Quran is such a perfect and complete guide that any and every bit of “innovation” outside of its

  sharia is heresy and blasphemy. In Sermon 175 he writes:

  …know that this Quran is an adviser who never deceives, a

  leader who never misleads and a narrator who never speaks a

  lie…You should also know that no one will need anything after

  (gu
idance from) the Quran… Know, O’ creatures of Al ah, that a believer should regard lawful this year what he regarded lawful

  in the previous year and should consider unlawful this year what

  he considered unlawful in the previous year. Certainly people’s

  innovation cannot make lawful for you what has been declared

  unlawful; rather, lawful is that which Al ah has made lawful and

  unlawful is that which Al ah has made unlawful…People are of

  two categories – the follower of the shariah (religious laws), and the follower of the innovations to whom Al ah has not given any

  testimony by way of sunnah or the light of any plea.

  Therefore the notion that the Quran was an exoteric message of discipline for the ignorant rabble and that there is an esoteric

  mystical Islam for a spiritual elite, would have been considered

  total y heretical by Ali himself – never mind the preposterous and

  total y unsubstantiated claim that he himself was the first initiate of this mystical tradition! After thoroughly examining the sermons of

  Ali we see that beyond a shadow of a doubt he was no mystic at al .

  144

  jason reza jorjani

  Not only did he subscribe completely to the dogma of Muhammad’s

  Quranic revelation, he also fervently reaffirmed the eternal validity

  of all its decrees. Thus the silsilat al-Irfan (chain of gnosis) breaks at its very first link, and the tradition of ‘Islamic Mysticism’ is severed from Muhammad and his Quran, in other words, from Islam itself.

  145

  SPINOZA, THE UNTIMELY ONE

  More than any other philosopher before him, Friedrich

  Nietzsche considered himself a visionary and

  revolutionary thinker, a man born outside of time, an

  “untimely one.” In the last half-century, much scholarship

  has questioned this Promethean image of Nietzsche. His debts

  to Schopenhauer were well known even in his own time, and the

  influence of such figures as Dostoyevsky and Emerson have since

  been discerned. By comparison, the affinity of Nietzsche’s thought

  with the much earlier work of Baruch Spinoza has been neglected.

  This despite a number of strong indications, in Nietzsche’s published

  works and private notebooks,1 that Spinoza is the one figure who by

  far holds the greatest title to being Nietzsche’s predecessor.

  In section 475 of Human, All-too-Human, Nietzsche is arguing

  against anti-Semitism.2 He claims that it is the Jews “to whom we

  owe the noblest human being (Christ), the purest philosopher

  (Spinoza), the mightiest book, and the most effective moral code in

  the world.” This is all the more remarkable because the Jews are “a

  people which, not without guilt on all our parts, has had the most

  sorrowful history of all people,” persecuted by all nations on account of their being perceived as threatening because of “their energy and

  higher intelligence, their capital of spirit and wil .”

  1 Friedrich Nietzsche, Writings from the Late Notebooks (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003).

  2 Friedrich Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human (University of Nebraska Press, 1984).

  146

  jason reza jorjani

  In section 408 of Mixed Opinions and Maxims, Nietzsche lists

  Spinoza as one of eight thinkers in terms of which his own thinking

  unfolds and who have the right to judge his work from beyond the

  grave. He writes:

  “With these I must come to terms when I have long wandered

  alone; they may call me right and wrong; to them will I listen

  when in the process they call each other right and wrong.

  Whatsoever I say, resolve, or think up for myself and others – on

  these eight I fix my eyes and see their eyes fixed on me. May the

  living forgive me that occasional y they appear to me as shades, so pale and somber, so restless and, alas, so lusting for life – while those men then seem so alive to me…”

  In a later notebook entry Nietzsche revises the list, writing: “My

  ancestors: Heraclitus, Empedocles, Spinoza, Goethe”.3 Heraclitus and

  Schopenhauer are usual y cited as the two philosophers who had

  the greatest impact on Nietzsche, and who might be considered his

  predecessors. Interestingly, Heraclitus fails to appear on the first list, while Schopenhauer, who does appear on the first list, is dropped

  in the second. Nietzsche never seriously engages with Epicurus,

  Montaigne or Pascal (from the first list), nor with Empedocles (from

  the second), and his extensive comments about Plato and Rousseau

  (cited in the first list) are almost completely critical and negative.

  The only two thinkers present in both lists are Spinoza and Goethe.

  Goethe is not a philosopher in the strictest sense, so this leaves us

  with Nietzsche suggesting that, of all philosophers, Spinoza is the

  most intimately related to him.

  In a third list of greatest thinkers and kindred spirits, which

  appears in Nietzsche’s notebooks from the period of the Gay

  Science, Spinoza alone appears of the figures from the first and second lists and is now equated with the likes of the founders of the

  world-religions (and of Nietzsche himself!): “In that which moved

  3 Walter Kaufmann, Basic Works of Friedrich Nietzsche (New York: The Modern Library, 1992), 159.

  147

  lovers of sophia

  Zarathustra, Moses, Mohammed, Jesus, Plato, Brutus, Spinoza,

  Mirabeau – I live too.”4

  A letter of July 30, 1881, written by Nietzsche to Franz Overbeck,

  may be the clearest single piece of evidence for his debt to Spinoza,

  or at least proof of a strong affinity with this predecessor. Here

  Nietzsche clearly states that he and Spinoza are in agreement on five

  main points, the denial of: 1) free-will; 2) purpose; 3) the moral world order; 4); the un-egoistic; and 5) the existence of evil. Nietzsche

  writes:

  I am real y amazed, real y delighted! I have a precursor! I hardly

  knew Spinoza: what brought me to him now was the guidance

  of instinct. Not only is his whole tendency like my own…in five

  main points of his doctrine I find myself; this most abnormal

  and lonely thinker is the closest to me in these points precisely:

  he denies free wil , purposes, the moral world order, the

  nonegoistical, evil; of course the differences are enormous, but

  they are differences more of period, culture, field of knowledge.

  As we shall see, this is no exaggeration. Spinoza anticipates nearly

  every major aspect of Nietzsche’s thought. There are more than

  25 significant references to Spinoza in the course of Nietzsche’s

  published works and private notes. I will focus on those of them that

  underline the affinity of Nietzsche and Spinoza, as the majority of

  critical remarks on Spinoza antedate Nietzsche’s own claim (in 1881)

  that the differences between the two thinkers are superficial and are

  far outweighed by the fundamental similarities.

  Let us begin with a comparison of the respective views of

  Spinoza and Nietzsche on the relationship between the Mind and

  Body. Spinoza believes that the Mind is an idea of the Body.5 It is not a simple idea representing a coherently unified body, but a complex

  4 Walter Kaufmann, The Gay Science (New York: Random House, 1974), 151.

  5 Benedict de Spinoza, A Spinoza Reader: The Ethics
and Other Works (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press), Ethics 2:13.

  148

  jason reza jorjani

  of ideas whose ‘objects’ ( ideatum) are diverse bodily processes.6

  Thus the relationship between Mind and Body is more intimate

  than a mere causality, wherein either the movements of the Body

  would depend on the ideas of the Mind, or bodily processes would

  determine these mental ideas. Instead, forging beyond both idealist

  and materialist reductionism, while at the same time avoiding

  Cartesian dualism, Spinoza holds that: “the mind and the body are

  one and the same thing, which is conceived now under the attribute

  of thought, now under the attribute of extension.”7

  This is essential y the same way that Nietzsche conceives of

  the relationship between mind and body, though in very different

  language. It is often assumed that Nietzsche reduced the Mind to

  an effect of bodily drives. This is the sense that we get from passages like the following, from sections 489 and 491 of the Will to Power:

  “Thinking is for us a means not of ‘knowing’ but of describing an

  event, ordering it, making it available for our use… [and] belief in the body is more fundamental than belief in the soul… the body is the richer, clearer, more comprehensible phenomenon: to be

  placed first methodological y.”8 Such passages can be very deceptive,

  because Nietzsche’s use of the language of the body is polemical and

  is not indicative of biological reductionism. This becomes clear in

  the following passage from section 552 in the Will to Power:

  There are no opposites: only from those of logic do we derive

  the concept of opposites – and falsely transfer it to things… If

  we give up the concept “subject” and “object”, then also the

  concept “substance” – and as a consequence also the various

  modifications of it, e.g., “matter”, “spirit”, and other hypothetical

  entities, “the eternity and immutability of matter,” etc. We have

  got rid of materiality.”

  Here we see Nietzsche reject both a spiritual and a materialistic

  interpretation of the world, going beyond both idealism and

  6 Ibid.,

  Ethics 2:15.

  7 Ibid.,

  Ethics 2:21, Scholium.

 

‹ Prev