Lovers of Sophia

Home > Other > Lovers of Sophia > Page 40
Lovers of Sophia Page 40

by Jason Reza Jorjani


  presented in the spectacle of the three prematurely debauched girls:

  “As for the girls, he turned them off, he would not admit one of

  them, eagerly as they implored and hard as they tried to enter

  by force if not by permission. The hunchback alone managed to

  slip in under his outstretched arm, but he rushed after her, seized

  her by the skirts, whirled her once round his head, and then set

  her down before the door among the other girls, who had not

  dared meanwhile, although he had quitted his post, to cross the

  threshold. K. did not know what to make of all this, for they

  seemed to be on the friendliest terms together.”232

  This seems to be an intentional foreshadowing of the man from the

  country debating whether or not to enter the doorway into the Law

  without permission, especial y as Titorelli is a man in the confidence of the Court, with a higher unofficial position than many of the

  Court officials. It has been suggested that the three girls who storm

  his studio by force, like the three women who offer K. help, are

  symbolic references to the Goddess Hecate. Titorelli is, of course,

  the painter of the image of the War Goddess of Justice who is also

  the Goddess of the Hunt.

  The Law maintains the firm ground of ‘the country’, even if

  those who live there are free from having to deal with the law. The

  Priest explains that the man from the country was not compelled to

  remain at the side of the doorway into the Law. He could have gone

  back into the country and lived his life as he wished. Nevertheless,

  he lives because there is a Law. The man from the country, for whom

  alone this entryway to the Law has been forged, is a man who is

  called before the Law – as into the primordial understanding that 232 Ibid., 143.

  315

  lovers of sophia

  precedes principles of limited relevance. He is called to a wisdom before the scriptures, a wisdom that surpasses the deception of the

  Law, in a word, to Witchcraft. The parable is clear enough that unlike the doorkeeper, it is his destiny to enter, but he may choose the time of this destiny’s fulfillment. If he were to storm through its entrance without permission, the Law would not be destroyed. Rather, he

  would be ecstatical y annihilated by the understanding that the

  scriptures are a lie and the essence of the Law is the unknowable

  Oneness of Being.

  The same is true of Joseph K. The very first line of The Trial is

  “someone must have been telling lies about Joseph K., for without

  having done anything wrong he was arrested one fine morning.”233

  The passages above suggest that this view, implicitly attributed by

  Kafka to the perspective of Joseph K., is a naïve presumption. No one

  has been telling lies about Joseph K., rather the wrong that Joseph K.

  has done is that he has believed himself to exist at al . Joseph K. is a lie, he exists a lie. There is some aspect of him that suspects this, and his arrest is not so much a condemnation (of his possessiveness and

  desire to gain advantage) as it is an invitation into the devastating

  revelation of the triune goddess that is already seducing him from

  within. Yet it remains true of Joseph K. that, as Kafka writes in

  his Blue Octavo Notebooks: “His answer to the assertion that he did perhaps possess, but that he was not, was only trembling and palpitations.”234

  233 Ibid., 1.

  234 Brod,

  The Blue Octavo Notebooks, 90.

  316

  WITTGENSTEIN’S INCOHERENT

  ETHICS

  The most highly reputed philosophers in Western history,

  from Plato and Aristotle to Locke, Kant, and Hegel, did

  not confine their work to epistemology or metaphysics.

  Ever since conservative mobs set fire to the Pythagorean

  schools and condemned Socrates to death for confronting the likes

  of Euthyphro and Thrasymachus, the quest to justify some universal

  standard of ethical conduct has been central to philosophy’s defining

  struggle against religious dogma and the blind rule of force.

  While Ludwig Wittgenstein is hailed by some as the preeminent

  philosopher of the 20th century, or even as the greatest thinker since Immanuel Kant, he never developed a coherent ethics. Perhaps

  this could be overlooked if Wittgenstein were simply uninterested

  in ethics, but the fact is that he always believed there to be nothing more important. The theory of meaning in the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus1 rejects the ethical as nonsensical. Yet the young Wittgenstein attempts, both in that work itself and in his early

  wartime notebooks,2 to stow away and protect ethics on a mystical y

  transcendent plane.

  In the first section of this paper, I argue that this attempt

  is ineffectual and incoherent from both an ontological and an

  epistemological perspective. So far as his latter work, as best

  1 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (New York: Barnes and Noble, 2003).

  2 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Notebooks 1914–1916 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979).

  317

  lovers of sophia

  exemplified by Philosophical Investigations 3 and On Certainty,4

  Wittgenstein’s views on the rational incommensurability of diverse

  “language games” precludes any understanding of Justice that

  transcends cultural conditioning or coercion. I hope to make clear why that is so in the second section of this paper. I conclude, in the paper’s third section, by considering the late Wittgenstein’s often passionate remarks on religion. These remarks accord religious beliefs a unique

  linguistic, cultural, and psychological status that cannot be accounted for within the framework of the Investigations or On Certainty. They may have been the attempt of a person with deep moral sentiments to

  emotional y compensate for, or even to momentarily escape from, the

  amoral character of his rigorous philosophical work.

  1. The Incoherent ‘Ethics’ of the Tractatus

  In his “Letter to Ficker”, a potential publisher of the Tractatus, the young Wittgenstein claims that the work’s main point is ethical,

  but that it addresses the Ethical by delimiting it from within, which

  “strictly speaking”, is the only way that he believes it could be

  delimited. The letter reads in part:

  I once wanted to give a few words in the foreword [to the

  Tractatus] which now actual y are not in it, which, however, I’ll write to you now because they might be a key for you: I wanted

  to write that my work consists of two parts: of the one which is

  here, and of everything which I have not written. And precisely this second part is the important one. For the Ethical is delimited

  from within, as it were, by my book; and I’m convinced that,

  strictly speaking, it can ONLY be delimited in this way. In brief, I think: All of that which many are babbling today, I have defined in my book by remaining silent about it.5

  3 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations: The German text, with a revised English translation (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2001).

  4 Ludwig Wittgenstein, On Certainty (New York: Harper & Row, 1972).

  5 Brian R. Clack, An Introduction to Wittgenstein’s Philosophy of Religion (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1999), 33.

  318

  jason reza jorjani

  However, despite Wittgenstein’s claim in this letter, the so-called

  “ethics” of the Tractatus is b
oth ineffectual and incoherent, especial y when one traces its origins to remarks within Wittgenstein’s wartime

  Notebooks of 1914-1916.

  At the core of the ethical problem of the Tractatus is its model of an isomorphic, or one-to-one, relationship between linguistic

  propositions and worldly facts. The correspondence between any

  statement and the facts that it intends to represent is reducible to

  one between elementary propositions and states of affairs, and

  these are in turn respectively reducible to simple names and simple

  objects. “Meaning” in the sense of “sense” is a function of the way

  that simple names intend or point to certain simple objects that

  are elementary constituents of states of affairs. The names out

  of which all propositions are ultimately constituted function as

  proxies for objects. We use them in lieu of having to find and point

  to something every time we want to make reference to it. It is in

  this sense that a name is supposed to (proximal y) mean an object.

  The early Wittgenstein says that “we feel that the world must consist

  of elements” that are its non-composite “substance”, all change

  being precisely describable in terms of the “configuration” of these

  “unalterable and subsistent” objects.6

  The tractarian Wittgenstein rejects any nexus of necessary

  connections outside of those constitutive of logic. Like Hume, he

  views the relationship between empirical ‘causes’ and their apparent

  ‘effects’ as a contingent one. “Causation” is no more than a useful

  concept employed under a given paradigm of representation, not an

  absolute ontological reality true of the world in itself.7 This means

  that there is no logical y necessary connection between my willing

  p and the fact that p actual y does come about as an empirical event.

  According to Wittgenstein, this is true at a level more fundamental

  than that which differentiates the movements of voluntary and

  involuntary muscles.8 My body is a mere phenomenon that cannot

  6 Wittgenstein,

  Tractatus, 2.02, 2.021, 2.0271; Notebooks, 62.

  7 Wittgenstein,

  Tractatus, 6.33-6.341, 6.36f., 6.362.

  8 Ibid., 5.631.

  319

  lovers of sophia

  be ontological y separated from the rest of the phenomenal world

  over which I have no control.9

  If Wittgenstein had not gone on to make any explicit references

  to ethics, the straightforward ethical implications of such a

  worldview would clearly be that propositions concerning rape,

  pil age, and genocide have the same status as those referring to an

  avalanche. To talk of such ‘terrible’ incidents in ethical terms cannot even be “false”, because the statements involved are not reducible

  to simple names of elementary particulars that stand in precise

  relations to other such simples in order to constitute a certain state of affairs that either obtains in fact or is found not to be the case, by means of scientifical y precise empirical observation. Propositions

  that cannot be translated into scientific statements of fact do not

  even refer to possible but factual y false states of affairs — they are, according to the Tractatus, quite literal y sense-less. In other words, Wittgenstein assumes that no sensory experience could serve to verify or falsify them. Such statements violate the isomorphism

  of language and reality: “the limits of that language (the language

  which I understand) mean the limits of my world.”10

  Though it is whol y non-ethical, this position is clearly

  comprehensible. However, the tractarian Wittgenstein descends

  into incoherence when he tries to salvage ethics by means of an

  ill-defined transcendental mysticism concerning the relationship

  between Will and the World. Wittgenstein acknowledges how

  profound dissatisfaction with the inhuman doctrine above could

  motivate a recourse to the mystical: “The urge toward the mystical

  comes of the non-satisfaction of our wishes by science. We feel that even if all possible scientific questions are answered our problem is still not touched at all. ”11 Although this sounds like a warning against taking recourse to the mystical, if that is what it is Wittgenstein

  himself apparently fails to heed it.

  9 Ibid., 5.641; Notebooks, 2.9, 12.10, 4.11.16.

  10 Wittgenstein,

  Tractatus, 5.62.

  11 Wittgenstein,

  Notebooks, 51; cf. Tractatus, 6.52.

  320

  jason reza jorjani

  In the Tractatus, from 5.62-5.641, Wittgenstein lays out a doctrine of a metaphysical subject that lies at the “limits of the world”. In

  6.373 and 6.374, Wittgenstein attributes a “wil ” to this metaphysical subject, but claims that the facts of the world are independent of this so-called “wil ”. In 6.423 he draws a distinction between two senses

  of “wil ”, namely, the will as a mere phenomenon, and “the will as

  the bearer of the ethical”. The former would be part of the world of

  facts, which, according to 6.4 and 6.41, means that it can have no

  value. However, “the will as the bearer of the ethical” is something

  of which “we cannot speak” because: “It is clear that ethics cannot

  be expressed. Ethics are transcendental.”12 Most significantly,

  Wittgenstein does not take this to mean that the ethical will does not exist: “There is indeed the inexpressible. This shows itself; it is the mystical.”13 “Whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent.”14

  Despite this injunction to reverent silence, Wittgenstein does try

  to use words to gesture towards the significance of the ethical wil .

  Presumably, this is one of the instances of his using propositions that are, strictly speaking, nonsensical, as a ladder that can be cast away once it has been used to see the world rightly.15 What Wittgenstein

  abuses his own criteria of proper language use to mumble about

  the ethical will is that, while it cannot change the facts of the world, the true self circumscribes the world in such a way as to allow one

  to encompass the amoral facts of the world and assume an ethical

  attitude towards them.16 This attitude, in turn, somehow qualitatively changes one’s experience of the world as a whole.17 What supposedly

  makes this possible is that, ultimately, the only world is one’s own

  world of experience, which is why Wittgenstein believes that the

  entire world comes to an end at the death of the true self.18

  12 Wittgenstein,

  Tractatus, 6.421.

  13 Ibid., 6.522.

  14 Ibid., 7.

  15 Ibid., 6.54.

  16 Ibid., 6.422.

  17 Ibid., 6.43.

  18 Ibid., 6.431-6.4311.

  321

  lovers of sophia

  This true “I” is neither the physical body nor the psychological

  character (the individual ego). It is, rather, a microcosm of

  some “God” consciousness that can contemplate the world “as a

  limited whole” from “outside of space and time”.19 It seems that to Wittgenstein, this is somehow synonymous with living whol y

  in and for the present moment, which is a kind of eternal life that

  relinquishes any regret over the past or hope to change the future.20

  Thus the qualitative change wrought by the ethical wil , whereby

  one’s life becomes “happy” rather than “unhappy”, occurs on account

  of aligning
one’s will with the divine will that the facts of the world be just as they are. This can only be read from in between the lines of the Tractatus, but it is repeatedly stated in wartime Notebooks that were obviously the matrix for all of those passages in the Tractatus that are cited above:

  I cannot bend the happenings of the world to my will: I am

  completely powerless. I can only make myself independent of

  the world – and so in a certain sense master it – by renouncing

  any influence on happenings.21

  The thinking subject is surely mere il usion. But the willing

  subject exists. If the will did not exist, neither would there be

  that centre of the world, which we call the I, and which is the

  bearer of ethics. What is good and evil is essential y the I, not the

  world. The I, the I is what is deeply mysterious!22

  The will is an attitude of the subject towards the world. The

  subject is the willing subject.23

  And in this sense Dostoievsky is right when he says that the man

  who is happy is fulfilling the purpose of existence. Or again we

  19 Ibid., 6.4312-6.45.

  20 Ibid., 6.4311-6.4312.

  21 Wittgenstein,

  Notebooks, 11.6.16.

  22 Ibid., 5.8.16.

  23 Ibid., 4.11.16.

  322

  jason reza jorjani

  could say that the man is fulfilling the purpose of existence who

  no longer needs to have any purpose except to live. That is to say,

  who is content.24

  To believe in a God means to understand the question about

  the meaning of life. To believe in a God means to see that the

  facts of the world are not the end of the matter. To believe in

  a God means to see that life has a meaning. The world is given

  me, i.e. my will enters into the world completely from outside

  as into something that is already there... That is why we have the

  feeling of being dependent on an alien wil . However this may be, at any rate we are in a certain sense dependent, and what we are dependent on we can call God... In order to live happily I must

  be in agreement with the world. And that is what “being happy”

  means. I am then, so to speak in agreement with that alien will on which I appear dependent. That is to say: ‘I am doing the will

  of God.’25

  In these passages, as in the propositions of the Tractatus that emerge from out of them, Wittgenstein claims that the ethical will

 

‹ Prev