Lovers of Sophia

Home > Other > Lovers of Sophia > Page 55
Lovers of Sophia Page 55

by Jason Reza Jorjani


  Placing all of that aside, my objection is simply that Lewis’s thesis

  of the maximal plurality of worlds does not allow for any free will

  worth having, and by “worth having” I mean to suggest that he does

  not have good grounds for defeating an “indifference” objection. The

  “indifference” objection that Lewis actual y addresses in Section 2.6

  is, of course, a hypothetical one that he himself concocts so that he

  3 Ibid., 127.

  4 Ibid., 126-127.

  433

  lovers of sophia

  can have a response prepared for anyone that might raise anything

  like it. However, it seems to me that he misconstrues what the central concern of such an objection would be, perhaps so as to be able to

  answer it more easily. At issue is not whether we can change the

  ‘sum total’ of ‘good’ and ‘evil’ in view of the fact that all possibilities, including all possible versions of our own life, are actualized at some world or another. The moral semantics of ‘good’ and ‘evil’ confuse

  the point here. Rather, a real indifference objection would be that:

  I should be indifferent with respect to my-so-called-life if there is real y, that is ontological y, nothing that I can add to my world or to the lives of those who cohabit it. Whatever meaning the moral

  terms ‘good’ and ‘evil’ might have is irrelevant to this objection,

  which could be forwarded based on aesthetic rather than ethical

  motivations. If they are to be works of art – the visionary labors of a creator – then at no other possible world do there exist such things to vital y experience, and dynamical y respond to, as Shakespeare’s

  plays, Coltrane’s jazz, Duncan’s dances, Pollock’s paintings, or

  Kubrick’s films.

  It is a question of novelty. I must be able, by my actions, to transform the world around me in such a way as it could never be

  transformed were it not for my decision to take those actions. Of course, this transformation need not always be according to my

  intention, and indeed if it always were exactly what I wanted, that might pose as great a psychological obstacle to a life worth living.

  It may be an extremely subtle and hardly noticeable transformation

  that I effect in the empirical world, and in the large and long view

  it probably always is. However, it must be possible to do something no one has done in just the way that I am contemplating doing it

  – not anyone in this world of mine, or anyone however like me in

  any other world that there might ever possibly be, or that there ever

  has been. Otherwise, I do nothing at al , and for that matter ‘I’ have insufficient personal identity to real y be anyone either.

  To be someone who makes his or her life what it alone uniquely is, and not the life of another, demands a non-reductionist view

  of consciousness, one wherein our minds are not ontological y

  434

  jason reza jorjani

  derivative of some more elementary constituents. Whether these

  simples are taken to be empirical y real (as they are in Physicalism)

  or whether they are constructs of logical possibility is irrelevant.

  When Lewis says that some of his many worlds contain “spirits” who

  do not operate according to any physical laws, much less what are

  taken to be our physical laws, he is presumably conceiving of these

  “spirit” beings as metaphysical simples. Given his reductionism, he

  would certainly have to do so in order to even attempt to attribute

  any power of choice to them.

  However, if they are metaphysical simples, then there seems to be no way that he can conceive of them as ever “doing” anything

  with respect to each other or to some other objects, unless anything

  with which each of them could interact already had a logical y

  predetermined propensity-profile for certain interactions (and not others). In that case, all of the substances with which these “spirits”

  (or any other would-be-choosers) might interact, are substances

  whose predetermined propensity-profiles compel the latter to act

  only according to laws that demarcate a closed system of finite

  possibilities that are all bound to be actualized ‘somewhere’ at some

  ‘time’. It seems that on this view, if ‘I’ were one of these “spirits”, I would only be discursively responsible for what I do – and not an

  ontological y responsible agent of actions that created states of affairs, and brought objects into being, that could otherwise never have

  been as I alone was able to will them to be. Metaphysical simples can

  create nothing at al .

  Lewis claims that radical y isolated causal chains provide real

  agency for counterparts who are (presently) leading perfectly

  identical lives (and in some worlds, lives that have already been

  lived in a perfectly identical way in past cycles or eons of eternal

  recurrence). He makes this claim in reference to a certain “story”

  that he adapts for his own purposes:

  A story by Larry Niven even suggests that knowledge of a

  plurality of worlds might reasonably undermine the will to live.

  Every decision you ever make is made in all the myriad ways it

  435

  lovers of sophia

  might be made. It is made one way by you, other ways by your

  other-worldly counterparts who are exactly like you up to the

  moment of the decision. Not only difficult and momentous

  decisions will be made all different ways; but also easy decisions,

  even decisions too easy to take any thought, like the decision to

  kill yourself on the spur of the moment for no reason at al . Given

  that the decision will in any case be made all different ways, what

  does it matter whether you are one of the ones who makes it one

  way or one of the ones who makes it another way...5

  Lewis goes on to qualify his use of Niven’s story as a hypothetical

  “indifference” objection, by pointing out that he is modifying

  Niven’s story in order to do so. Apparently, the original story is

  about one of two kinds of physical parallel universes: (1) parallel universes between which travel is possible, perhaps through worm-holes or time machines; (2) total y inaccessible parallel universes

  that are posited by Hugh Everett as a solution to the supposedly

  ‘mysterious’ wave-col apse in quantum theory. Lewis seems to think

  that it is not clear which of these two types Niven is talking about.

  On Lewis’s view, the “universes” of (1) would only be discrete parts

  of a single possible world. In regard to (2) he makes the following remark: “Niven may be talking about branching worlds, in which

  one present decider has many futures that are all equal y his. If so, I grant his point. That real y would make nonsense of decision.”6

  Lewis’s criticism of version (2) of the Niven story concerns

  the manner in which a person’s genuine decision making capacity

  would be vitiated by there real y existing a version of him for

  each and every decision that he could possibly have made. Lewis thinks that this does not pose an agency problem for his thesis of

  the plurality of worlds because his possible world counterparts are

  entirely causal y isolated from one another. The decisions made by

  these Lewisian counterparts are supposed to be real choices because

  they are allegedly radical y independent persons. They originate in

  5 Ibid., 124-125.

&n
bsp; 6 Ibid., 125.

  436

  jason reza jorjani

  different worlds. They are not created, together with their worlds,

  as instantiations of alternative decisions faced by a common

  predecessor. What I am arguing is that unless contact between

  worlds is possible, as it is on interpretation (1) of Niven’s original story, even these counterparts are not “deciders” in any real sense that would convince any creatively minded person that life was

  worth living and that decisions were worth making.

  I can well imagine traveling through a worm-hole into an

  alternate universe where I meet a counterpart of myself who has

  lived a very similar life, but has or has had somewhat different

  relationships with counterparts of people with whom I have or have

  had certain relationships. My presence in his life would change

  it and, once I traveled back through the worm-hole to my world,

  my encounter with him would make me reflect on and change the

  circumstances of my own life as wel . Even if these lives were for

  all intents and purposes identical, the possibility of meeting my counterpart would allow each of us to act freely in reaction to the

  other – which, at that point, would cause the direction of our two

  lives, and of our two worlds, to significantly deviate from one another.

  Only in this case would each of us be ontological y independent

  agents, as Lewis mistakenly takes his counterparts to be. Lewisian

  counterparts are rather effects, the ‘cause’ (or sufficient reason) of whose actions is determined by the character of an atemporal y

  complete logical space.

  On the face of it, and at first glance, Lewis’s ontology of maximal

  possibilities appears very creative (at least compared to other

  works of analytic philosophy), and so it seems odd to claim that

  it forecloses every existential y significant possibility (and I take the primary meaning of the word “possibility” to be an existential

  one). However, upon closer scrutiny, one should realize that Lewis’s

  ontology is only ‘creative’ in the sense that certain proofs of higher mathematics seem stunning when first discovered, but then grow

  trivial over time. (Surely, even the Pythagorean theorem seemed

  ‘creative’ in this sense when it was first discovered.) Lewis places

  conditions of “size” and “shape” on what could or could not possibly

  437

  lovers of sophia

  coexist with what within the same possible world, and, by extension,

  what must be the case at all possible worlds. In so doing, he relies

  on a mathematical definition of the possible properties and relations

  that any being could logical y have:

  But now there is trouble. Only a limited number of distinct

  things can coexist in a spacetime continuum. It cannot exceed

  the infinite cardinal number of the points in a continuum...Our

  principle [of the conceivability of states of affairs at possible worlds]

  therefore requires a proviso: ‘size and shape permitting’... Starting

  with point-sized things that are uncontroversial y possible, perhaps

  because actual, we patch together duplicates of them in great

  number (continuum many, or more) to make an entire world. The

  mathematical representations are a book-keeping device, to make

  sure that the ‘size and shape permitting’ proviso is satisfied.7

  Lewis would like to cast his recourse to “mathematical

  representations” as no more than “a book-keeping device” that is

  useful for adhering to some intrinsic logical laws of being. However,

  this manner of representation, of taking things to be so and so, is the matrix of his ontology. In such an ontology, where mathematics is

  read into the foundations of all concrete worlds, there “are no gaps

  in logical space” and so there is no room for contingency in the

  system as a whole. Lewis states this repeatedly:

  It is futile to want the entire system of worlds to satisfy a

  condition, because it is not contingent what conditions the entire system of worlds does or doesn’t satisfy. You might as well want the number seventeen to be prime, or to be even...8

  Is it a matter of wants: should I want there to be less evil and

  more good in total, throughout the worlds? It would be an idle

  wish, since the character of the totality of all the worlds is not a contingent matter. I see no reason why I ought to have so utterly idle and pointless a wish.9

  7 Ibid., 89, 91.

  8 Ibid., 125; my emphasis.

  9 Ibid., 126; my emphasis.

  438

  jason reza jorjani

  Lewis emphasizes that imagination is a poor criterion for defining

  possible worlds.10 Things of any significant degree of complexity

  are usual y imagined imprecisely, and so something that is logical y

  impossible may be thought to be possible simply because what it

  would involve has not been imagined with sufficient clarity. While

  Lewis emphasizes repeatedly that possible worlds, however bizarre,

  are not categorical y different from our ‘actual’ world in their

  ontological status (in the reality of their being), he also clearly states that possible worlds, including our own, are essential y of a different kind than the fantastic worlds of story-tellers:

  If worlds were like stories or story-tellers, there would indeed

  be room for worlds according to which contradictions are true.

  The sad truth about the prevarications of these worlds would

  not itself be contradictory. But worlds, as I understand them, are

  not like stories or story-tellers. They are like this world; and this world is no story, not even a true story.11

  Lewis’s metaphor of a world as a story-teller’s tale, and his warning

  that the impossible can be imprecisely imagined, suggests what

  the world might be like if it were not reducible to quantifiable

  fundamental constituents – if its ontology were not basical y

  mathematical. It is worthy of note that the Greek root of the word

  “mathematical” is mathesi s – which means “that which can be

  learned”, in other words that which is formulaical y anticipatable. On the other hand, logos, the Greek root of the word “logic” original y means “discourse” or even “story” and its first philosophical use in

  reference to the constitution of the cosmos still retained this sense.

  That first use of the notion of “logic” – to refer to dynamical y

  adaptable tactical rules on a cosmic scale – was by Heraclitus, who

  also called the cosmos “a child at play, moving pieces in a game”. It may be that any free will worth having requires the world to indeed be something like a story-teller’s tale – where fundamental ontology

  10 Ibid., 90.

  11 Ibid., 7.

  439

  lovers of sophia

  allows for the same logical y ‘impossible’ phantasmagoria that Lewis

  attributes to the vagueness of imagination.

  In his last years, William James (who was, after al , the brother of

  a great story-teller) came close to seriously advocating such a view in connection to the problem of free wil . In two sections on “Novelty

  and Causation” in Some Problems of Philosophy, James points out that the notion of “causation” primarily derives from our own

  experience of bringing things into being that we intuitively know

  could not otherwise have been.12 Our own
acts of origination, our

  acts of creation, are the basis upon which we then only secondarily attribute causes to other beings in nature (first to animistic spirits, then to the gods or God, and final y to material beings or natural

  laws). To intellectual y abstract “causation” from its primary meaning as an immediate experience of the agency of conscious willing

  beings such as ourselves, and to turn it into an impersonal universal

  principle, leads to an infinite regress wherein causes col apse into

  effects of other causes, without a first cause being found anywhere

  within the limits of possible experience. Without a first cause with

  an ontological y irreducible explanatory power, all causality loses its necessary aspect.

  Lewis thinks of the causal power of inner-worldly individuals

  (who have counterparts at other possible worlds) as a power to

  actualize certain outcomes, not as a power to create them. For example, he argues that even if in many possible worlds similar to

  this one, but slightly different, he completes writing his book while

  in others he does not, it is impossible for him to take vicarious

  pleasure in knowing that some of his counterparts complete the

  book while he does not. Lewis writes: “It matters to me whether I

  am one of those among my counterparts who labour on, or one of

  those who quit.”13 The completed books and those that will never

  be completed already exist in the bounded totality of logical space.

  Lewis does not allow for an ontological y significant “labour” on his

  12 William James, Writings: 1902–1910 (New York: The Library of America, 1987), 1079-1094.

  13 Lewis,

  On the Plurality of Worlds, 126.

  440

  jason reza jorjani

  part, as an agent, that would cause a book to come into being as an object that otherwise would not be. Note the following two passages:

  ..I reply that the argument for indifference relies on a false

  premise...It is not idle to want continued life for yourself; you

  may have it or not, and you will not get what you want if you

  make the wrong decision about whether to kill yourself on the

  spur of the moment.14

  ‘What is wrong with actualizing evils, since they will occur in

  some other possible world anyway if they don’t occur in this

  one?’ – If you actualize evils, you will be an evil-doer, a causal

 

‹ Prev