onkings

Home > Other > onkings > Page 65
onkings Page 65

by Faun Rice


  policies that often completely contradicted the king’s; a royal order to turn over

  rebels might simply be refused (Lorenz 1997). On the other hand, accounts of

  arbitrary executions at whim within the king’s “Great Village,” or of retainers

  willingly offering themselves up for sacrifice at the death of a member of the

  royal family, do not appear to be fabricated. George Milne is probably right to

  speak of the French being overawed by the spectacle of an elaborate Mississip-

  pian “monarchical theatre” (2015: 37); much of what happened in the Great

  Village did have a theatrical quality—except, of course, it was the kind of thea-

  tre where, if a character died, they actually did die.

  As a result, the royal village grew smaller and smaller:

  The great Village of the Natchez is at present reduced to a very few Cabins. The

  Reason which I heard for this is that the Savages, from whom the Great Chief

  has the Right to take all they have, get as far away from him as they can; and

  therefore, many Villages of this Nation have been formed at some Distance from

  this. (Charlevoix 1763: 312)

  This might help explain the contradiction between reports of extreme obeisance,

  and the royals’ reluctance to use the term “Stinkard” in commoners’ presence.

  Foreign observers almost never got outside the Great Village, a place largely

  22. But, of course, so was that of Louis XIV.

  NOTES ON THE POLITICS OF DIVINE KINGSHIP

  395

  reduced to Suns, Nobles, and their servants. The only commoners they were

  likely to encounter were the royals’ own wives and husbands, or the visiting del-

  egations that would periodically appear to offer contributions of choice meats

  and delicacies—neither of whom it would have been wise for the Suns to gra-

  tuitously humiliate.

  Archaeology confirms that not only were the other settlements larger than

  the “Grand Village,” they were actually wealthier (Lorenz 1997: 106–8; 2000:

  168–72). What’s more, relations between center and periphery often seem to

  have taken the form of ritualized hostility. On the one hand, we are told that

  “relatives of the Sun regard the other savages as dirt” (Swanton 1911: 100); on the

  other, we find descriptions of how the common people, in their role of warriors,

  would every year pretend to ambush, capture, and prepare to kil the king, until a

  second mock war party intervened to rescue him (Du Pratz 1774: 319–20). Af-

  terward, those same warriors would combine to cultivate a special field of maize

  whose harvest the female Suns would subsequently mimic stealing.23

  What sort of power, then, did the Great Sun have? And how do we char-

  acterize such a polity? Most contemporary literature is of little help here. Even

  those who see the French accounts as largely a projection of their own ab-

  solutism are content, insofar as they take on the question at all, to fall back

  on the evolutionist language favored by most contemporary archaeologists and

  describe it as a “complex chiefdom” (Lorenz 1997; Milne 2015: 6, 10)—which

  doesn’t really tell you much other than that they think the Natchez should be

  considered one notch lower than a state. Not only is this unedifying, it tends to

  obscure the key feature of arrangements like the Shilluk, or Natchez, or even for

  most of its history the Merina kingdom: that the question of the king’s sover-

  eign power (i.e., his absolute ability to impose his will in any way he wished to

  23. The mock battle was ostensibly a reenactment of a historical event when the Great

  Sun actually was nearly captured by an enemy war party, but it’s hard to read it as

  anything but a reminder of how much his life is ultimately in his warriors’ hands.

  Du Pratz provides a description of two feasts; this one, and a harvest festival, of

  which we have several other accounts as well (compiled in Swanton 1911: 113–23).

  The first feast, in March, corresponded to the equinox, and maize planting, and

  the ultimate victory of the white-plumed warriors of the Great Sun over the red-

  plumed “enemy” warriors led by the war leader, the Tattooed Serpent, no doubt also

  implied a transition to the half of the year marked by agricultural activity. Warriors

  then go on to plant and tend the special field for the king, which is harvested in July,

  and female Suns pretend to run away with the crop. For present purposes, though,

  I only wish to stress the element of ritualized hostility.

  396

  ON KINGS

  when he was physically present) and the question of his political power (i.e., his

  ability to influence events when he was not physically present) are completely

  separate. The first, kings’ ability to place themselves beyond and outside the laws

  which they uphold, was always absolute in principle (however much it might

  not be in practice).24 If a king cannot, at least in theory, kill his subjects without

  reason, he can hardly be said to be a king at all. But it is notoriously difficult

  for monarchs to wield such power in situations where they are not physically

  there.25 The Great Sun, then, seems to have been in a situation quite similar to

  the Shilluk reth: largely confined to a peculiarly constituted village largely con-

  sisting of his wives and attendants (and in his case, his brother and sisters and

  their spouses and attendants), presumably along with the motley assortment

  of criminals, orphans, and runaways who ordinarily collect around such courts,

  inside which his whim was law, outside which his ability to control the course of

  events was almost entirely dependent on his guile and political savvy.

  The Great Sun’s capacity to bring health, prosperity, and fertility to his peo-

  ple, on the other hand, was entirely independent of that political influence. In

  fact, there is even some reason to believe it might have been seen as dependent

  on its containment. According to one account, the secret holy of holies within

  the Great Temple was not the eternal fire, but a stone image which was consid-

  ered to be the petrified body of the original lawgiver. Apparently that original

  Sun who had “formerly been sent to this place to be the master of the earth,

  had become so terrible that he made men die merely by his look; [so] in order

  to prevent it he had a cabin made for himself into which he entered and had

  himself made into a stone statue” (St. Cosme, in Swanton 1911: 172; 1946:

  779), a secret which was known only to the Suns and their closest confidants. In

  24. It is surely significant, for example, that the laws Du Pratz was told were conveyed

  by the founder of the kingdom—“we must never kill anyone but in defense of our

  own lives; we must never know any other woman besides our own; we must never

  take anything that belongs to another” (1774: 314)—seem precisely those most

  likely to be ignored by the Great Sun and his close relatives. I should emphasize

  that in reality, no one ever really has absolute power in this sense: there are always

  lines one cannot cross, at least without eventually being destroyed for it. But kings

  quite regularly insist that they do, in principle, have this power anyway.

  25. Even Tudor kings had trouble with this: their power was so caught up with their

&
nbsp; physical being that in order to get subjects to accept delegated authority they often

  had to rely on members of court who were known to be in the most intimate

  possible physical contact, such as the famous Groom of the Stool of Henry VIII

  (Starkey 1977).

  NOTES ON THE POLITICS OF DIVINE KINGSHIP

  397

  Government by metahuman beings

  [Sovereignty contained in time]

  [Sovereignty contained in space]

  Ritual clown police

  Divine kingship

  Seasonal clown police

  Extreme Frazerian

  Successful assertion

  sacred kingship

  of sovereignty

  Seasonal police

  “The state”

  Figure 1. The “declownification” of sovereignty.

  other words, the Great Sun, who regularly interceded with his ancestors in the

  Temple to bring the powers of life to his people, also kept the potential deadly

  powers of those ancestors contained in precisely the way that his people sought

  to contain his own deadly powers. Again, much as among Shilluk, the divisions

  between heaven and earth were maintained, however tenuously, by the mainte-

  nance on every level of at least potential hostility.

  * * *

  While the Natchez situation might at first seem a far cry from the kind of

  careful circumscription of police powers we saw in California, the Northwest

  Coast, and societies of the Plains, on another level, all of these can be seen as

  structural variations on a single principle. In every case, sovereign power—the

  power to violate the terms of the ordinary moral order, to create rules, give

  unquestionable, unaccountable orders backed up by threat of punishment—is

  held by humans only insofar as it is an embodiment, extension, refraction, or

  delegate of metahuman beings. In each case, too, the contexts in which such

  power can be exercised are carefully defined, and—since marking something off

  398

  ON KINGS

  as sacred is always a way of creating, preserving, or maintaining its power—this

  circumscription itself plays a role in generating the power of which sovereignty

  is a practical expression.

  Seen this way, the difference between the Kwakiutl and the Théoloël is per-

  fectly straightforward. The Kwakiutl contain divine sovereignty in time, giving

  the Fools police powers during the ritual season, but not otherwise. The Théoloël,

  in contrast, contain divine sovereignty in space, limiting it to the theatrical arena

  of the Great Village and the area immediately surrounding the physical body

  of the king. If the Plains societies’ seasonal police represent a partial seculariza-

  tion of the first, then more familiar forms of kingship might equally be said to

  be a partial secularization of the second. Yet this secularization is always partial.

  Kings are always sacred, even when they are not in any sense divine.

  ON THE CONSTITUTIVE WAR BETWEEN KING AND PEOPLE

  The sovereign is not bound by the laws.

  Ulpian

  Government is civil war.

  Anselme Bellegarrigue

  In “The divine kingship of the Shil uk” (chapter 2 in this volume), I suggested

  that monarchies—and, by extension, modern states—are marked by a kind of

  primordial, constitutive war between king and people, one that is prior, even, to

  Carl Schmitt’s purportedly foundational distinction between friend and enemy. It

  is constitutive in the sense that it is through this (antagonistic) relation that both

  king and people can be said to come into being to begin with. This is why even

  when a kingdom is founded on purely voluntary arrangements (as many do ap-

  pear to be), it is nonetheless framed as conquest, or even, as Marshall Sahlins ob-

  serves (chapter 3), the mutual conquest (“encompassment’) of king and people.26

  In stranger-kingship, one might say that the “social peace,” the truce in that

  war that makes stable kingdoms possible, takes the form of those diarchical

  26. It is worth recal ing that immediately after the passage when the Israelites tel Samuel

  they wish to have a king “like other people,” the prophet warns them, prophetically,

  that they’ll soon come to see their relation as adversarial (Samuel 8: 11–19).

  NOTES ON THE POLITICS OF DIVINE KINGSHIP

  399

  arrangements so beautiful y described in Sahlins’ essays on the BaKongo and

  Mexica in this volume (chapters 3 and 4, respectively). In these, royal control

  over the lives of subjects is typical y matched by popular control over the land

  and its products, with the indigenous people represented by earth priests or

  other autochthonous authorities with ritual power over the soil. Stil , I think

  the idiom of war between king and people draws on and is expressive of an

  even deeper structural reality—the ability to step outside the moral order so as

  to partake of the kind of power capable of creating such an order is always by

  definition an act of violence, and can only be maintained as such. Transgression

  is not in itself necessarily a violent act. The kind of transgression that becomes

  the basis for a power of command over others necessarily must be. It is a form

  of compulsion that lies behind any possible accountability. This is also the deep

  truth about the modern state whose disturbing implications Schmitt ([1922]

  2005)—the German jurist credited with creating the legal basis for the Nazi

  concentration camps—was perhaps the first to work out in a systematic fash-

  ion. To say a state is “sovereign” is ultimately to define its highest authorities

  as beyond moral accountability. This not just war; it is total war. Insofar as the

  sovereign intends to apply such compulsion to an entire population within

  a given territory, it ultimately must always be. (The only limitation on such

  total war is that the sovereign cannot wipe out the entire population, or his

  sovereignty would itself cease to exist.) Hence, as I remarked at the end of the

  Shil uk essay, the tendency for modern states to frame their greatest projects in

  terms of some sort of unwinnable war: the war on poverty, crime, drugs, terror,

  and so forth.

  Sometimes, this structural conflict can become explicit: Simon Simonse’s

  (1992: 204; 2005: 84) memorable image of the rainmaker king, armed with

  a rifle, single-handedly defending himself against his outraged subjects be-

  ing only one dramatic case in point. History is full of occasions when things

  actual y did come down to weapons: massacres, insurrections, mutinies, and

  reigns of terror. There is always a continuum, too, between rites of rebel ion,

  actual rebel ions, and outright revolutions; as we have come to learn (e.g., Berce

  1976), almost any of these things can unexpectedly flip into any of the others.

  I’m hardly saying anything new here. Al this has been endlessly debated and

  discussed by historians for many years; but once again, the perspectives and

  materials assembled in this volume suggest that war is by no means the only

  way that the structural conflict can work itself out. And even when it does,

  armed conflict, even between nations, always involves rules, and one might say

  400

  ON KINGS

  (as I have ar
gued for unarmed street actions: Graeber 2007c, 2009) that in any

  war, there are always two levels of conflict: within the frame (in which each

  party tries to win), and about the frame (in which they argue about the rules

  of engagement; ultimately, about what winning even means). Here, sovereignty

  is, again, one of those points where such frames implode; where the two levels

  col apse into one another. When a divine king breaks the rules of conventional

  morality, marries his sister or massacres his brothers, this is never just a political

  move (though it might also be a savvy political move), it is always simultane-

  ously a metapolitical move, a way of shifting the frame of reference upward to

  a level where it is possible to rule over—and hence fight over—the nature of

  the rules themselves.

  I understand this might seem confusing. My distinction between divine and

  sacred kingship is actually meant to provide a way to navigate this often vexed

  territory. So clarification might be helpful. In proposing that we apply the term

  “divine kings” to monarchs who act like gods—that is, with arbitrariness and

  impunity—rather than those who are actually considered to “be” gods, I am in

  no way suggesting that kings are never considered to be gods (as we’ll see, some

  certainly are), or even that, historically, the attribution of divine status, when it

  does occur, must be considered some sort of secondary elaboration on certain

  forms of practice. I do think Hocart was basically right to say royal powers were

  ultimately modeled on and seen to be derived from those of gods; even if I think

  the devolution was likely to have proceeded in a far more circuitous fashion than

  he would likely have imagined.

  So that’s what I’m not saying. What I am saying is this: if you look at the lit-

  erature on divine kingship as we know it from the anthropological record— that

  is, for roughly the last five hundred years—what is really striking is the degree

  to which there is no systematic relation between the theology of kingship—that

  is, the degree to which a monarch is or is not considered to be a god (or the

  avatar or incarnation of a god, or priest, prophet, or earthly representative of a

  god, etc.)—and the degree to which they behave like one. Let us compare the

  Shilluk reth and Ganda kabaka in this context. The reth is explicitly considered

 

‹ Prev