An Introduction to Madhva Vedan

Home > Other > An Introduction to Madhva Vedan > Page 5
An Introduction to Madhva Vedan Page 5

by Deepak Sarma


  rise to direct knowledge.6 I will first examine the components of kevala-pramâõa and then the three components of anu-pramâõa, namely

  pratyakùa, perception, anumâna, reasoning, and âgama, scriptural authority and verbal testimony.

  Kevala-pramâõa, direct knowledge of an object as it is

  For Madhvâcârya, all aspects of the universe, including knowledge,

  are qualitatively and hierarchically arranged. Consequently, kevala-

  pramâõa, direct knowledge, must have distinct components that can be

  arranged hierarchically. Kevala-pramâõa is an innate self-reflective

  knowledge and immediate intuition of objects that is possessed by

  all sentient beings, including Lord Viùõu. The intuitive knowledge of

  Viùõu, though, must be qualitatively better than any other sentient being.

  Hence Madhvâcârya divides the kevala-pramâõas into four types,

  namely Îúa (Lord Viùõu), Lakùmî, yogi, and ayogi (see Fig. 2.1).7

  Kevala-pramâõa

  Îúa

  Lakùmî

  yogi

  ayogi

  2.1 Kevala-pramâõa

  According to Madhvâcârya, the difference between them consists of a

  difference in clarity, where Lord Viùõu’s knowledge has the greatest

  clarity and the knowledge of the ayogi has the least. 8

  5 tad dvividham | kevalam anupramâõaü ca | PL.

  6 yathârthajñânaü kevalam | tatsâdhanam anupramâõam | PL.

  7 kevalaü caturvidham | îúalakùmîyogyayogibhedena | PL.

  8 spaùñþatve bhedaþ | PL.

  35

  22

  An Introduction to Mâdhva Vedânta

  In his PP, Jayatîrtha further separates the intuitive knowledge of Lord

  Viùõu, Lakùmî, yogi, and ayogi into two types: svarûpa-jñâna and manovçtti-jñâna.9 Madhvâcârya defines svarûpa-jñâna in his VTV as knowledge that is inherent to, or part of, the very nature of the cognizer.10

  Manovçtti-jñâna, on the other hand, refers to experiential knowledge, an

  external knowledge dependent on the vçtti, modifications, or operations

  of the manas, mind.11 Such knowledge, as I will explain below, can only be experiential knowledge obtained via the physical sense organs, via

  the anu-pramâõa such as pratyakùa, perception. Svarûpa-jñâna is more valid than manovçtti-jñâna, since it is never linked to the imperfect,

  external sense organs.

  Already the way in which difference and hierarchy is an intrinsic

  part of Mâdhva Vedânta, even in its epistemic categories, emerges.

  True knowledge can be categorized in terms of degrees. Lord Viùõu

  is omniscient and has knowledge that is comprehensive, without

  beginning or end, eternal and independent. His knowledge has all

  things everywhere as its scope and is part of His own nature.12

  Lakùmî’s knowledge is like Viùõu’s and is dependent on Viùõu and His

  knowledge. Its scope is everything except for Lord Viùõu, so its clarity

  is less distinct than His.13 For this reason, Lakùmî’s knowledge must be inferior. Neither Lord Viùõu nor Lakùmî need to rely on manovçtti-jñâna, external knowledge. After all, their knowledge is entirely

  svarûpa-jñâna, part of their nature, and is not linked to flawed

  pratyakùa, perception.

  Madhvâcârya holds that yogi-jñâna is the knowledge obtained by

  yogis, contemplative ascetics, after meditating on Viùõu. There are three

  types of yogic knowledge obtained via meditation and contemplative

  practices. These are çjuyogins, yogins whose knowledge is straight-

  forward, tattvika-yogins, yogins whose knowledge is true, and ayogins, the knowledge of those who are not yogins (see Fig. 2.2). 14

  9 tad [ îúalakùmîjñânaca] dvividham | svarûpa§ manovçttirûpaü ceti | PP 18.

  10 akùâõi ca svarûpâõi nityajñânâtmakâni ca | viùõoþ úrîyastathaivaoktânyany eùâü dvividhâni tu | svarûpâõi ca bhinnâni bhinnâni trividhâni ca | VTV.

  11 Rao, Epistemology of Dvaita Vedânta, 22.

  12 svâtantryapâratantryâbhyâü tadviúeùaþ | pûrvaü svaparagatâkhilaviúeùaviùayam |

  PL. I will hereafter capitalize the pronoun ‘his’ when it is in reference to Viùõu.

  13 dvitîyam îúo ‘nyebhyo ‘dhikam | asârvatrikam | anyatra sarvaviùayam | PL.

  14 yogijñânam çjûnâm anâdinityam | îúo jîvebhyo ‘dhikamanyatrâlocane sarvaviùayam | PL.

  36

  Mâdhva Epistemology

  23

  yogi

  çju

  tattvika

  ayogins

  2.2 Types of yogic knowledge

  The çjuyogins have knowledge that is eternal and without beginning

  but increases with their meditative effort. This knowledge becomes

  static after the knower obtains mokùa, liberation.15 The tattvika-yogins have incomplete knowledge of both Îúvara and other objects but still

  have self-conscious knowledge of reality. 16 Jayatîrtha states that there are also atattvika-yogins who are the other deities.17 The knowledge of the atattvika-yogins is partial. Those remaining are the ayogins

  who have partial knowledge of both Îúvara and objects other than the

  Lord. Jayatîrtha correlates the knowledge of the ayogins with Mâdhva

  soteriology, separating them into three types: the mukti-yogyas, those

  fit for release, the nitya-saüsârins, those bound to the cycle of birth

  and rebirth, and tamo-yogyas, those who are fit only for darkness.18

  The svarûpa-jñâna of the mukti-yogyas is valid, while that of the

  nitya-saüsârins is comprised of both invalid and valid knowledge.

  Though the svarûpa-jñâna of the tamo-yogyas is entirely invalid, the manovçtti-jñâna of all three is only occasionally invalid.19

  These different categories of kevala-pramâõa correlate with the

  hierarchical world that Madhvâcârya envisioned. In the realm of

  epistemology, this vision becomes apparent in terms of distinctions in

  clarity and scope of knowledge. As one proceeds down the category

  system, one moves further and further away from complete and

  unsurpassable knowledge, which only Viùõu has. Though it is possible

  to advance in knowledge, one can only asymptotically approach the

  level of complete knowledge held by Viùõu. As one advances in the

  epistemic hierarchy, one becomes more aware of the nature of brahman

  15 krameõa vardhamânam | âmukteþ tato ‘vyayam | PL.

  16 Nagaraja Rao states that these beings are actually deities who govern the twenty-five tattvas, categories described in Madhvâcârya’s Tantrasârasaügraha. Rao, 24–25.

  17 tadvyatiriktâþ devâdayaþ yoginaþ atattvikâþ | PP 18.

  18 ayoginaþ api trividhâþ | muktiyogyâþ nityasaüsâriõâþ tamoyogyâú ca iti | PP 19.

  More on the doctrine of predestination, svarûpatraividhya, in Chapters 3 and 4.

  19 tatra muktiyogyânâü svarûpajñânaü yathârtham eva | nityasaüsâriõâm tu miúram | anyeùâm ayathârtham eva | PP 19.

  37

  24

  An Introduction to Mâdhva Vedânta

  and the universe and its components. I will address the ways to ascend

  in the hierarchy, in order to gain more complete knowledge of Viùõu, in

  Chapter 4.

  Anu-pramâõa, indirect knowledge

  Kevala-pramâõa, direct knowledge, stands in contrast to anu-pramâõa, indirect knowledge, which is the instruments of valid knowledge. There

  are three instruments. These are via pratyakùa, perception, anumâna, logical inference and reasoning, and âgama, scriptur
al authority and

  verbal testimony (see Fig. 2.3). They are all defined as being without defects. Pratyakùa, perception, is defined as defectless contact of the

  sense organ with an object. Anumâna is defined as defectless inference,

  and âgama as defectless sentences and/or texts.20

  Anu-pramâõa

  pratyakùa anumâna

  âgama

  2.3 Components of anu-pramâõa

  These three instruments are loci for error. What are these defects and

  how are they to be avoided? What mistakes make anumâna, inference,

  unreasonable? What causes error? What are the components of

  cognition?

  Anu-pramâõas: pratyakùa , perception

  Madhvâcârya states that pratyakùa, perception, is comprised of two

  types of cognitive apparatus: the indriyas, six physical sense organs,

  and the sâkùî, the internal witness.21 The six physical sense organs are manas, mind, ghrâõa, smell, rasana, taste, cakùus, sight, úrotra,

  20 anupramâõaü trividham | pratyakùam anumânam âgama iti | nirdoùo ‘rthendriya sannikarùaþ pratyakùam | nirdoùopapattir anumâ | nirdoùaþ úabda âgamaþ | PL.

  21 pratyakùaü saptavidham | sâkùiùaóindriyabhedena | PL.

  38

  Mâdhva Epistemology

  25

  hearing, and tvak, touch.22 This list is not unusual in the history of South Asian thought and has its origins in the Sâükhya tradition which

  preceded Mâdhva Vedânta.23 The objects of the five sense organs are gandha, smell , rasa, taste, rûpa, color, úabda, sound, and sparúa, feeling (see Fig. 2.4).24 These five sense organs are the primary loci for error. If one’s eyes are defective then they can give rise to defective knowledge.

  Jayatîrtha characterizes these errors as those produced by a cataract,

  jaundice and the like.25 Similarly, if one’s ears are filled with wax or damaged, then sounds, which ought to be audible, may not be heard

  or are heard in a distorted way. When addressing visual error in his PP

  Jayatîrtha states that if an object is too far away, too near, too small,

  obstructed, or even mixed with similar things, then it will give rise to

  incorrect knowledge.26

  Pratyakùa

  sâkùî

  manas ghrâõa rasana cakùus úrotra

  tvak

  gandha

  rasa

  rûpa

  úabda sparúa

  2.4 Components of pratyakùa

  The five sense organs send their data (corrupt or otherwise) to the

  manas, mind, which serves to organize them. Though the manas is a

  sense organ, it gets and coordinates information from the other five.

  The manas lies in the middle of the cognitive hierarchy and in turn,

  the knowledge it generates is the object of the sâkùî, internal witness .

  The end result of the observation of the knowledge deriving from the

  physical sense organs by the sâkùî via the manas is pratyakùa, perceptual cognition as is illustrated in Fig. 2.5.

  22 prâkçtam ùaóvidham | ghrâõarasanacakùustvakúrotramanobhedât | PP 25.

  23 See Larson’s Classical Sâükhya: An Interpretation of its History and Meaning.

  24 PP 25. More on the ontology of these components in Chapter 3.

  25 eteùâü pañcânâü mano ‘nadhiùñitvaü kâcakâmalâdayaú ca doùâþ | PP 25.

  26 teùâm

  doùâþ

  atidûratvam

  atisâmîpyaü

  saukùmyaü

  vyavadhânaü

  samândravyâbhighâtaþ | PP 23.

  39

  26

  An Introduction to Mâdhva Vedânta

  indriyas

  manas

  sâkùî

  2.5 Perceptual cognition

  The manas, mind, is as an intermediary between the senses and the

  sâkùî. The manas is not unlike a processor chip in a computer whose purpose is to organize all of the incoming data before relaying it via the

  monitor to the user, which, as I will explain below, can be likened to the

  sâkùî.

  Given that the manas is a sense organ, it too cannot be expected to be

  perfect and can sometimes convey defective knowledge to the sâkùî.

  Defects of the manas include anger, passions and the like.27 When these doùas, fallacies, afflict the manas, then the data deriving from the inaccurate senses are further contaminated.

  These components of pratyakùa, presented in Madhvâcârya’s PL,

  seem to be internally coherent. But Madhvâcârya presents a different

  analysis of pratyakùa in his VTV. In this text, he separates pratyakùa

  into three types, which seems to conflict with the seven outlined in his

  PL. These are Îúvara- pratyakùa, yogi-pratyakùa, and ayogi-pratyakùa.

  All three types of perception originate from the senses. Jayatîrtha adds

  Lakùmî- pratyakùa to this group.28 The perception that derives from the senses of Viùõu and Úrî (Lakùmî) are eternal and inherent to their

  nature.29 The senses that give rise to yogi-pratyakùa and ayogi-pratyakùa are of two kinds: inherent to the nature of the cognizer and not part

  of the nature of the cognizer, namely their physical sense organs.

  Ayogi-pratyakùa is threefold, daiva, divine, âsura, and madhya,

  middling.30 According to Jayatîrtha, daiva is the most valid, asura is the least valid and madhya is partly valid and partly invalid.31 It is

  27 tasya doùâþ râgâdayaþ | PP 25.

  28 pratyakùaü trividhaü jñeyamaiúvaraü yaugikaü tathâ | ayaugiakaü ceti tathâ sarvam akùâtmakaü matam | VTV.

  caturvidhaü pratyakùam | îúvarapratyakùaü lakùmîpratyakùaü yogipratyakùaü ayogipratyakùaü ceti | PP 27. See also Zydenbos for more on these possible

  inconsistencies, 258.

  29 akùâõi ca svarûpâõi nityajñânâtmakâni ca | VTV.

  30 devâsurâõi madhyânîtyetatpratyakùamîritam | VTV.

  31 bâhyendriyaü trividham | daivam âsuraü madhyamam iti | tatra yathârthajñânapracuraü

  daivam

  |

  ayathârthajñânapracuraü

  âsuram

  |

  samajñânasâdhanantu madhyamam | PP 28.

  40

  Mâdhva Epistemology

  27

  not clear how these fit into the seven-fold classification outlined in

  Madhvâcârya’s Pramâõalakùaõa. Subsequent Mâdhva commentators

  such as Râghavendratîrtha and Úrînivâsatîrtha attempted to resolve this

  confusion.32 Contemporary scholars of the Mâdhva school hold that the longer list is merely an elaboration of the shorter one.

  Smçti , memory

  Scholars both in South Asia as well as in the West have long speculated

  about the epistemological status of memory. What determines the

  validity of memories? Can memory be categorized as its own sense

  organ? How are memories generated? Where are they located?

  Madhvâcârya offers answers to these questions by proposing that smçti,

  memory, is a product of the manas.33 Memory is thus characterized as a pramâõa. In fact, Madhvâcârya argues that memory must be considered

  to be valid. Proof that we even had a past experience is dependent on the

  validity of smçti.34 If it were not valid, moreover, then the knowledge of syllogisms produced by anumâna, logical inference and reasoning,

  would be impossible.35 For example, the knowledge that ‘where there is smoke, there is fire,’ necessitates the validity of the memory of the

  relationship between smoke and fire. If smçti had no validity, then one

  could never conclude from seeing smoke that ther
e was fire!

  The validity of smçti is necessary for the integrity of the âgama-

  pramâõa as well as anumâna. If it were not valid then the âgama classified as smçti, traditional human-authored texts, would also be

  invalid. In fact, any kind of knowledge that is transmitted by oral

  recitation and memorization, such as úruti, the revealed texts of the

  Vedic canon, would be invalid if memory was invalid. The âgamas must

  be included as a pramâõa and smçti must be a valid form of knowledge.

  For these reasons, in his Anuvyâkhyâna, Madhvâcârya states that manas

  is a valid form of knowledge which is yathârtha, reveals an object of

  knowledge as it is.36

  Remember that Madhvâcârya is a realist and that therefore the objects

  of our valid cognitions, including memory, must be sat, real. If memory

  were not admitted as a valid cognition or one that could be sublated,

  then Madhvâcârya would have to permit other kinds of seemingly valid

  32 I am reliant on Zydenbos for this information. Zydenbos, 259.

  33 mânasapratyakùajâ smçtiþ | PL.

  34 pûrvânubhûte kiü mânam ity ukte syât kim uttaram | AV 2.1.58.

  35 More on anumâna below.

  36 prâmâõyaü nânuvâdasya smçter api vihîyate yâthârthyam eva prâmâõyaúabdârtho yadvivakùitaþ | AV 2.1.24.

  41

  28

  An Introduction to Mâdhva Vedânta

  cognitions to be sublated. He must avoid this at all costs, otherwise he

  might affirm the position of his rivals, the Advaita school of Vedânta.

  The sâkùî

  The sâkùî, internal witness, is the most important component of

  Madhvâcârya’s epistemology.37 Perceptual cognition has several layers and the sâkùî is the innermost one. The indriyas are at the outermost layer, the manas is in the middle and the sâkùî is at the core (see Fig. 2.6).

  In fact, it refers to the basic level of reflective consciousness, experience

  and awareness that every sentient being possesses. A parallel concept in

  Western philosophy can be found in Descartes’s Meditations. Descartes

  suggests that, though there is little certainty in our knowledge, it is

  nonetheless possible to be certain of one’s own existence. After all,

  according to Descartes, self-reflection and thought, at the very least,

  proves that there is a knower. Hence his famous dictum, cogito ergo

 

‹ Prev