Key Thinkers of the Radical Right

Home > Other > Key Thinkers of the Radical Right > Page 12
Key Thinkers of the Radical Right Page 12

by Mark Sedgwick (ed)


  (1935): 1133– 1135; “Die deutsche Rechtswissenschaft im Kampf gegen den

  jüdischen Geist,” Deutsche Juristen- Zeitung 41 (1936): 1193– 1199.

  7. Carl Schmitt, Völkerrechtliche Großraumlehre mit Interventionsverbot für raumfremde

  Mächte: Ein Beitrag zum Reichsbegriff des Völkerrechts (Berlin: Deutscher

  Rechtsverlag, 1939).

  8. Carl Schmitt, Über Schuld und Schuldarten (1910); Gesetz und Urteil (1912); Der

  Wert des Staates und die Bedeutung des Einzelnen (1914).

  9. Carl Schmitt, Politische Romantik (1919); Die Diktatur (1921); Politische Theologie

  (1922); Die geistesgeschichtliche Lage des heutigen Parlamentarismus (1923);

  Römischer Katholizismus und politische Form (1923).

  10. Carl Schmitt, Die Rheinlande als Objekt internationaler Politik (1925); Die Kernfrage

  des Völkerbundes (1926).

  11. Carl Schmitt, Volksbegehren und Volksentscheid (1927); Der Begriff des Politischen

  (1927).

  12. Carl Schmitt, Verfassungslehre (1928).

  13. Carl Schmitt, Der Hüter der Verfassung (1931); Legalität und Legitimität (1932).

  14. Schmitt, Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty, trans.

  George Schwab (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1985), 50.

  15. Ibid., 13.

  16. Ibid., 33.

  17. Ibid., 49.

  18. Ibid., 65.

  19. Ibid., 63.

  20. Schmitt, Concept of the Political, 33 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996).

  21. Carl Schmitt, On the Three Types of Juristic Thought (Westport, CT: Praeger, 2004).

  22. Carl Schmitt, The Leviathan in the State Theory of Thomas Hobbes: Meaning and

  Failure of a Political Symbol, trans. George Schwab and Erna Hilfstein (Westport,

  CT: Greenwood Press, 1996).

  23. Carl Schmitt, Der Schatten Gottes: Introspektionen, Tagebücher und Briefe

  1921 bis 1924, ed. Gerd Giesler, Ernst Hüsmert, and Wolfgang H. Spindler

  (Berlin: Duncker and Humblot, 2014), 482.

  24. Schmitt, Concept of the Political, 19.

  25. Carl Schmitt, Theory of the Partisan, trans. Gary L. Ulmen (New York: Telos,

  2007), originally published as Theorie des Partisanen (1963).

  26. Schmitt, Concept of the Political, 27.

  27. Ibid., 35.

  28. Ibid., 33.

  53

  Carl Schmitt and the Politics of Identity

  53

  29. Ibid., 35.

  30. Ibid., 37.

  31. Ibid., 46.

  32. Ibid., 70.

  33. Carl Schmitt, The Nomos of the Earth in the International Law of the Jus Publicum

  Europaeum (New York: Telos, 2003), 55.

  34. Schmitt, The Nomos of the Earth, 42.

  35. Stefan Breuer, Carl Schmitt im Kontext: Intellektuellenpolitik in der Weimarer

  Republik (Berlin: Akademie- Verlag, 2012).

  36. See the standard work on this by Dirk van Laak, Gespräche in der Sicherheit

  des Schweigens: Carl Schmitt in der politischen Geistesgeschichte der frühen

  Bundesrepublik (Berlin: Akademie-

  Verlag, 1993). See also Mehring, Carl

  Schmitt: Denker im Widerstreit.

  37. Hugo Ball, “Carl Schmitts Politische Theologie,” Hochland 21 (1924): 263–

  286; Eric Voegelin, “Die Verfassungslehre von Carl Schmitt: Versuch

  einer konstruktiven Analyse ihrer staatlichen Prinzipien,” Zeitschrift für

  öffentliches Recht 11 (1931): 89– 109; Ernst Rudolf Huber, “Verfassung und

  Verfassungswirklichkeit bei Carl Schmitt,” Blätter für Deutsche Philosophie 5

  (1931/ 1932): 302– 315; Otto Kirchheimer and Nathan Leites, “Bemerkungen

  zu Carl Schmitts ‘Legalität und Legitimität,’” Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft und

  Sozialpolitik 69 (1932): 457– 487.

  38. Leo Strauss, “Anmerkungen zu Carl Schmitts ‘Der Begriff des Politischen,’”

  Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik 67 (1932): 732– 749; Helmut Kuhn,

  “Carl Schmitt ‘Der Begriff des Politischen,’” Kantstudien 38 (1933): 190– 196; Karl

  Löwith (Pseudonym: Hugo Fiala), “Politischer Dezisionismus,” Internationale

  Zeitschrift für Theorie des Rechts 9 (1935): 101– 123.

  39. Hasso Hofmann, Legitimität gegen Legalität: Der Weg der politischen Philosophie

  Carl Schmitts (Neuwied: Luchterhandt Verlag, 1964).

  40. Reinhard Mehring, “Otto Kirchheimers Promotionsakte,” in Kriegstechniker

  des Begriffs: Biographische Studien zu Carl Schmitt, ed. Reinhard Mehring

  (Tübingen: Mohr, 2014), 31– 46, 137– 152.

  41. Jürgen Habermas, “Kant’s Idea of Perpetual Peace: At Two Hundred Years’

  Remove,” in The Inclusion of the Other (Cambridge: Polity, 1999), 165– 201; “Does

  the Constitutionalization of International Law Still Have a Chance?” in Jürgen

  Habermas, The Divided West (Cambridge: Polity, 2006), 113– 93; Jacques Derrida,

  The Politics of Friendship (London: Verso, 2005); Giorgio Agamben, The State of

  Exception (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2005); Chantal Mouffe, ed., The

  Challenge of Carl Schmitt (London: Verso, 1999).

  54

  4

  Julius Evola and Tradition

  H. Thomas Hakl (Translated by Joscelyn Godwin)

  J U L I U S E V O L A H A R D LY ever spoke about his outer life and wrote little

  about it. His autobiography, The Path of Cinnabar ( Il cammino del cinabro),

  describes almost exclusively his inner development.1 The uncertainties

  begin with his origins. He was born in Rome on May 19, 1898. Despite

  what standard short biographies say, he most probably did not stem from

  the Sicilian nobility. Both parental lines originated in Cinisi (in the prov-

  ince of Palermo), and were certainly not ennobled.2 The title of baron,

  frequently used even on some official documents, could date from a pro-

  vocative Dadaistic pose of his youth, when he was known for his dandyish

  behavior. However, we can state that Evola never referred to himself as

  a baron.

  Evola was born at a very disturbed time. The Risorgimento (revival),

  with its unification of Italy and the rise of the middle classes, had also pre-

  pared the country for the rise of Fascism. An alternative religiosity in Italy

  led to the emergence of Theosophy, Anthroposophy, and awareness of

  Eastern religions. In philosophy, Benedetto Croce and Giovanni Gentile’s

  idealism served as a counterweight to Marxism.

  Early work and thought

  Evola’s intellectual activity can be divided into several phases, and this

  chapter will discuss its key concepts and resultant writings. Despite his

  multiple fields of interest, Evola’s worldview has a clear and discernable

  structure. Many fundamental ideas, primarily that of transcendence,

  5

  Julius Evola and Tradition

  55

  remained valid and visible as they continually developed and seized on

  each new field of interest.

  Intellectual foundations

  Although Evola was raised in Catholicism, he turned against it and felt

  attracted to writers such as Oscar Wilde, Gabriele D’Annunzio, and Arthur

  Rimbaud. At the same time he pursued technical and mathematical

  interests. His early readings of Friedrich Nietzsche and Otto Weininger

  were especially influential, together with the philosophy of Carlo

  Michelstaedter, whose cousin Emilio was friends with the young Evola.

 
The influence of these three thinkers cannot be overestimated, for they

  were not only decisive in Evola’s youth but also in later life. Nietzsche gave

  him his uncompromising, aggressive attitude, his revulsion toward the

  “humility” and “bourgeois moralism” of Christianity, as well as his oppo-

  sition to “egalitarianism, democratic ideals and conformism.”3 However,

  Evola did not embrace Nietzsche’s Übermensch (superman) ideal, at least

  not until later on, finding it dominated by the naturalistic, biological ele-

  ment, and utterly lacking the transcendent.4

  Otto Weininger’s influence carried equal weight. His work obviously af-

  fected Evola’s attitude to the female sex and to Judaism (of which Weininger,

  though of Jewish origin, was extremely critical), also embracing ethical prin-

  ciples (“Truth, purity, fidelity, sincerity towards oneself: that is the only accept-

  able ethic”)5 and even political views, rejecting popularism in the broadest

  sense. Above all it is the attitude of “virility” in the sense of courage, daring,

  and steadfastness, so characteristic of Evola, that goes back to Weininger,

  who in his book Sex and Character ( Geschlecht und Charakter) proposed that

  everyone carries both masculine and feminine elements, and that no purely

  masculine or feminine type exists. He identified the feminine element with

  sexuality and motherhood, and regarded Judaism as marked by it.

  Carlo Michelstaedter, who came from a Jewish family in northeastern

  Italy, committed suicide at the age of twenty- three after finishing his book

  Inner Conviction and Rhetoric ( La persuasione e la rettorica), apparently

  believing that his philosophical discoveries could go no farther. By “inner

  conviction” Michelstaedter understood an absolute self- sufficiency of the

  “I.” As long as this did not rest exclusively on oneself but depended on

  some “other,” it was subjected to the “necessity” of external circumstances

  and therefore had no freedom. True freedom lay only in autarchy.

  56

  56

  C L A S S I C T H I N K E R S

  Evola called these three thinkers the “holy damned,” because none of

  them, for all their genius, was equal to the power and force of their own

  conceptions. Two of them committed suicide while still young; the third

  became insane. Evola was convinced that it was their own inner tension

  that destroyed them because they lacked the spiritual element— the deep,

  inner connection with the transcendent— that is unshakable and above

  and beyond anything earthly. And as Evola says, this decisive drive to tran-

  scendence had “manifested itself from my early youth.”6 Upon his return

  from the First World War, Evola too was thrown into an existential crisis

  and contemplated suicide. He lost his longing for extinction when he sud-

  denly grasped a passage from the Buddhist Pali Canon.7 It said that he

  who believes that his own extinction is final extinction has in no way un-

  derstood true extinction.8

  Evola came to a transcendent experience of the “I” through spiritual

  experimentation, reinforced by inhaling ether. It changed his life and for-

  ever after gave him the firm grounding that allowed no inner deviation.

  He describes this consciousness expansion as an “idea of peremptory, ab-

  solute, and resounding certainty,” adding “When I compare it to my pre-

  vious and habitual consciousness, only one image comes to mind: the most

  lucid, conscious state of wakefulness in comparison to the deepest, most

  hypnotic and torpid state of sleep.”9 This was the basis for the unshakable

  quality of his views, despite all the hazards of his life. His many ambitious

  mountaineering excursions in the Alpine glacier region helped to deepen

  this attitude. Climbing mountain peaks was for him a symbol of the ascent

  to the divine.10

  Futurism and Dadaism

  Evola’s philosophical and literary interests brought him into the artistic

  circle around the Italian Futurists Giovanni Papini and Filippo Tommaso

  Marinetti, and Evola himself soon began to paint. Papini introduced him

  to Eastern spirituality and above all to Meister Eckhart. In one of his

  earliest writings, Essays on Magical Idealism ( Saggi sull’idealismo magico)

  Evola cites Eckhart’s statement that one should not do one’s work for the

  sake of heaven, God, or salvation, that is, not for anything outside, but

  always without asking why.11 This saying stands as a leading principle of

  Evola’s entire life: action done irrespective of success or of the plaudits or

  opposition of others. Eckhart also wrote: “God and Being are the same.

  57

  Julius Evola and Tradition

  57

  But if I know God directly thus, then I must become him and he must

  become me . . . so completely one that this he and this I are one thing.”

  This may be the origin of Evola’s recurrent urge in his esoteric writings

  toward “identity with God” (deification), often criticized as hubris and

  “supermanhood.”12

  Evola soon broke with Futurism, whose polemical attacks against the

  bourgeois had so attracted him. “What disturbed me in Futurism was its

  sensualist overtones: its lack of inwardness, its noisy and exhibitionist char-

  acter . . .with its chauvinistic nationalism.”13 He then turned to the incipient

  Dada movement. A friendship developed with Tristan Tzara, Dada’s prime

  mover, documented by thirty surviving letters from Evola to the Franco-

  Romanian artist.14 Dadaism was far more radical than Futurism, and like Far

  Eastern philosophy spoke of an identity of the I with the Non- I. In his essay

  Abstract Art ( Arte astratta) Evola speaks of art as coming out of a higher con-

  sciousness. 15 Dadaism could, however, not satisfy his metaphysical thirst,

  and in 1922, at the age of twenty- four, he ended not only his Dadaistic period

  but also, abruptly and finally, his artistic career. Even so, he is reckoned today

  as one of the foremost representatives of Italian Dadaism and is valued by

  collectors, with paintings in Roman and Brescian museums.16

  The philosophical phase and the Far East

  Evola dates this phase to about 1923– 27, although his two main philosoph-

  ical works— Theory of the Absolute Individual ( Teoria del l’individuo assoluto)

  and Phenomenology of the Absolute Individual ( Fenomenologia dell’individuo

  assoluto)— were published later.17 His philosophy goes back to German

  idealism (especially Fichte and Schelling) and beyond that to Plato. Evola

  called it “magical idealism,” a term from the Romantic poet Novalis, in

  which one again detects his transcendent impulse.

  Evola’s question is one of the oldest in philosophy. He seeks the ab-

  solute point of certainty on which to build his structure of thinking. In

  view of his earlier transcendent experience of the I, there could only be

  one certainty for him: the I itself— naturally not the everyday ego but the

  transcendent foundation of one’s own personality. Called the “absolute

  individual” and likened to the Indian ātman, this is for Evola not only the

  “center of universal responsibility”18 but also expr
esses a perfect fullness

  of power, which necessarily grows from absolute knowledge and is at the

  same time boundless freedom.

  58

  58

  C L A S S I C T H I N K E R S

  During this phase, Evola was also deeply involved with the reli-

  gious and esoteric writings of the Far East. It was already evident in

  his Essays on Magical Idealism ( Saggi sull’idealismo magico) how impor-

  tant he found the Tao Te Ching.19 His philosophy thus broke the usual

  academic boundaries and reached far into spiritual traditions. Equally

  important was his study of the Hindu scripture Bhagavad Gita, whose

  statements could only reinforce Evola’s natural leaning toward the

  Kshatriya warrior class. He concluded that the outward battle simulta-

  neously symbolizes the inward battle against one’s own weaknesses and

  negative qualities.20

  Evola’s next book, Man as Power ( L’Uomo come Potenza),21 which

  appeared in 1925, formed the link between his philosophical period and

  the following “magical” one, in which he strove, after his theorizing, for an

  active and practical breakthrough to transcendence. Evola’s all- important

  concept of power, which also applied to politics and which he interprets

  in the sense of Tantrism and Taoism, must be firmly distinguished from

  “force” or “violence.” Power and force stand for him as contraries, for

  power loses its own being when it has to resort to material means, that is,

  to force, rather than working completely from itself, out of its inner supe-

  riority and hence “magically.” In his first political work, Pagan Imperialism

  ( Imperialismo pagano) he stated that “superiority is not based upon power,

  but power upon superiority. To need ‘power’ is impotence.”22

  A very important relationship of Evola’s was with the Italian Arturo

  Reghini, a Pythagorean and a Freemason, who introduced him to al-

  chemy, magic, and the pagan tradition of Rome. In 1927 Evola and Reghini

  founded the magical and initiatically oriented “Group of Ur.”23 Beside in-

  dividual practices there was also “group work” by the leading members,

  aimed at creating a “subtle” entity for magically influencing Mussolini,

  who had spoken of the “Return of the Empire after fifteen centuries to

 

‹ Prev