Why Faith Fails The Christian Delusion

Home > Other > Why Faith Fails The Christian Delusion > Page 53
Why Faith Fails The Christian Delusion Page 53

by John W. Loftus

had been altered or abandoned. In the third century BCE a research institute was

  established in Alexandria, Egypt, where Ctesibius and Philo completed the first

  known scientific works in experimental pneumatics (the study of the behavior of

  air and water); Eratosthenes invented the science of cartography and was one of

  the first scientists in history to measure the diameter of the earth (he overshot by

  only 15 percent) and analyze the effect of the moon on the tides; and Herophilus

  became the first scientist to dissect human cadavers. In fact, Herophilus and his

  pupil Erasi-stratis originated neurophysiology, establishing with detailed

  experiments that the mind is a function of the brain and that specific mental

  functions were controlled in specific areas of the brain, and they distinguished

  motor from sensory nerves and mapped them throughout the body. Altogether,

  their study of the human body and its bones, muscles, and organs, was so

  thorough that we still use much of their anatomical terminology.

  In Sicily, their colleague Archimedes was busy advancing the sciences of

  mechanics and hydrostatics, and discovering, describing, or explaining the first

  mathematical laws of physics. Shortly before that, Aristarchus began measuring

  the distances of the moon, sun, and planets (with values that were increasingly

  refined in subsequent centuries), and proposed the first helio centric theory. In

  Rhodes a century later, Hipparchus discovered and measured celestial precession

  (the rotation of the zodiac over a period of 25,800 years), observed the first

  supernova, established the first detailed scientific star charts, made numerous

  advances in planetary theory, and developed the first scientific system for

  predicting lunar and solar eclipses. Seleucus of Babylon discovered the effect of

  the sun on the tides, not just the moon, developing the first mathematical

  lunisolar tide theory. Then, during the early Roman Empire, science reached its

  pinnacle of achievement, producing works not exceeded until the Scientific

  Revolution: from Dioscorides in botany, mineralogy, and pharmacology; Hero in

  mechanics, pneumatics, and theatrical robotics; Ptolemy in astronomy,

  cartography, optics, and harmonics; and Galen in anatomy, physiology, and

  medicine. Just to name a few. There were many more whose work is now lost,

  advancing fields as diverse as apiology and oceanography, to volcanology and

  hydrostatics.

  None were shackled to any "unrevisable framework" by Aristotlel' but freely

  revised and debated all his physical assumptions. Heliocentrists debated static

  and dynamic geocentrists; theories of inertia, pressure, and universal gravitation

  competed with Aristotelian theories of natural places; visual ray theories

  competed with particle theories of light, and so on.16 By the Roman period,

  Aristotle's conclusion that comets were an atmospheric phenomenon was losing

  ground to the correct view that they were planetary bodies on wide eccentric

  orbits; Hipparchus had developed an increasingly correct theory of projectile

  motion and refitted Aristotle's belief that the heavens never change; Herophilus

  had refitted the Aristotelian theory that the soul resided in the heart, with precise

  experiments proving all thought and sensation occurred in the brain-a conclusion

  Galen then reinforced with a detailed study of the vocal system, demonstrating

  that the brain controlled human speech; Hero had experimentally refitted

  Aristotle's claim that a vacuum was impossible, and proven that wind was air in

  motion, that heated air expands and rises, and that cold air contracts and falls;

  and Ptolemy had abandoned Aristotle's assumption that planetary orbits had to

  be concentrically circular and their velocities constant. Even Aristotle's theory of

  a fundamental division between the sublunar and celestial realms was widely

  challenged and often rejected by subsequent physicists, along with almost every

  other doubtful aspect of his original physics.

  Major advances in logic also occurred after Aristotle,17 as well as in

  mathematics and physical concepts, such that almost everything credited as first

  proposed by medieval intellectuals, had in fact already been conceived in

  antiquity. For example, what we now call Ockham's Razor was already a

  standard methodological assumption.18 Even Stark's dismissive "some

  extensions of geometry" happened to include advanced conics, plane and

  spherical trigonometry, and the rudiments of calculus. They even went beyond

  geometry, developing combinatorics and an early form of multivariable algebra.

  Yet medieval Christians showed such disinterest in these mathematical

  achievements that some were barely preserved at all, while others were literally

  erased from books so they could be replaced with hymns to Ood.19 In fact,

  under Christian tenure almost all the scientific achievements of the ancients were

  forgotten in the West and ignored in the East, or survived only in simplistic

  caricatures. The few books that got copied enough to survive were rarely or

  barely copied at all, often not understood, and never substantially improved upon

  for nearly a thousand years.

  As a result, for many centuries Christians didn't even know scientists after

  Aristotle had significantly expanded the experimental method and began

  confirming mathematical laws of physics, which were predictively successful,

  technologically useful, and thoroughly mechanical. The first correct

  mathematical laws likely predate Archimedes, but his treatises on statics and

  hydrostatics are the earliest surviving record of them. By then scientists knew

  that levers obey the law D1W1 = D,W, (expressed geometrically) and that

  objects don't float because (as Aristotle supposed) it's just their nature to, they

  float because their density is less than the surrounding water, so the heavier

  water pushes up the floating object, by an amount exactly entailed by the

  mathematical difference in their densities, and that even sinking objects become

  lighter, by an amount exactly equal to the weight of the water the body

  displaces-which, incidentally, refitted Aristotle's notion that an object's lightness

  was immutably innate. By Roman times, the correct laws of reflection were also

  known, as well as their correct theoretical explanation (Hero proved they

  followed from a principle of least action), and the laws of refraction were being

  explored and approximated with detailed experiments. Ptolemy experimentally

  measured the difference in indexes of refraction for materials like glass, water,

  and air, discovered that the refraction angle increases with the incidence angle in

  a progressive relationship, and attempted to ascertain a mathematical law of

  refraction. Precise measurement even played a role in physiology, allowing

  Galen to prove the correct theory of kidney function (and explain the entire renal

  system) with a series of controlled experiments.20

  Hutchinson defines modern science as an "emphasis on direct observation and

  experiment, precise measurement, and the formulation of laws of nature," and

  we've just seen the ancient pagans had all those things.21 Stark defines modern

  science as "a method utilized in organized efforts to formula
te explanations of

  nature, always subject to modifications and corrections through systematic

  observations" such that "it is possible to deduce from [the resulting explanations]

  some definite predictions and prohibitions about what will be observed." 22

  That, too, accurately describes ancient science. Ancient scientists continually

  developed and improved their methods-right up to the end: Galen, Hero and

  Ptolemy all had a great deal to say about method and its improvement. Their

  efforts were also organized. Ptolemy's Almagest shows astronomers shared

  observations and created records for future colleagues, Galen's books repeatedly

  show doctors working together on anatomical research and scientists in all fields

  conferring with each other for information and debate, and there were many

  formal scientific associations, including the Museum of Alexandria. And they all

  aimed at producing explanations of nature, often correcting their theories with

  systematic observations and controlled experiments, and deducing from their

  theories exact predictions of what will or won't happen. Ptolemy's planetary

  theory could predict the position of Mars to within a straw's width twenty years

  in advance, and his law of refraction was almost as precise. Galen's theory of the

  renal and vocal systems correctly predicted the effects of specific injuries and

  disease as well as the normal behavior of the organs themselves. Hero could

  predict the precise mechanical advantages of many machines and the general

  behavior of air, water, and steam in the presence or absence of pressure or heat.

  Menelaus could predict the specific densities of different fluids and solids and

  their behavior in different suspending mediums. And on and on. All were

  empirical, all linked theory to practice, and all tested at least some of their

  theories against observed data. Yet Stark still maintains, with complete

  confidence, that "in the end all they achieved were nonempirical, even

  antiempirical, speculative philosophies, atheoretical collections of facts, and

  isolated crafts and technologies-never... real science."23 As should now be

  perfectly clear, not a single bit of that sentence is even remotely true.

  HISTORICAL FANTASYNUMBER 2: "PAGANS HAD A MENTAL BLOCK"

  Already Stark's first fact is so embarrassingly false it's a wonder he stays

  employed. But it gets worse: he confidently declares reasons why his first fact is

  true, even though his first fact isn't true, thus refuting his secondsince if those

  causes obtained, they clearly didn't have the effect predicted. So, too, any other

  "causes" other advocates allege for this nonexistent stagnation in ancient science.

  All these "explanations" amount to claiming that pagans were suffering from

  various mental blocks, which only Christianity could free them from. Stark picks

  three popular examples:

  First, their conceptions of the Gods were inadequate to permit them to

  imagine a conscious Creator [so they couldn't imagine physical laws].

  Second, they conceived of the universe not only as eternal and uncreated,

  but as locked into endless cycles of progress and decay [so they couldn't

  imagine scientific progress]. Third, prompted by their religious

  conceptions, they transformed inanimate objects into living creatures

  capable of aims, emotions, and desires-thus short-circuiting the search for

  physical theories.24

  Even if these claims were true, Stark's theory is already refuted, for as we just

  saw, science flourished despite them, and it's Stark's contention that these three

  facts would surely have prevented that. Since they didn't, Christianity can claim

  no advantage in having abandoned them. Yet as Stark represents them, these

  claims aren't even true, nor do they make any logical sense as barriers to science

  to begin with. In fact, I contend they are so false or illogical, yet declared with

  such confidence, that Stark can only be dishonest, delusional, or incompetent.

  For even the most rudimentary fact checking and analysis would have exploded

  every one.

  Pagan Theology

  Pagan theology supposedly got in the way, but Stark makes little sense of this.

  He claims certain aspects of Platonic theology impeded science.'' But since all

  ancient scientists were philosophical eclectics with strong sympathies for Stoic

  and Epicurean physics, and for Aristotelianism, which from its very foundation

  was anti-Platonist, it wasn't even possible for Platonism to impede the course of

  ancient science, even if it did harbor any antiscientific tendencies.26

  More generally, pagan theology supposedly prevented a conception of an

  intelligible universe governed by natural laws. Hence, according to Stanley Jaki,

  only Christianity could produce science, for:

  The scientific quest found fertile soil only when this faith in a personal,

  rational Creator had truly permeated a whole culture, beginning with the

  centuries of the High Middle Ages ... [providing] confidence in the

  rationality of the universe, trust in progress, and appreciation of the

  quantitative method, all indispensable ingredients of the scientific quest.27

  Of course, as we just saw, the "scientific quest" had already found fertile soil in

  pagan antiquity. But everything else here is false, too. Ancient scientists already

  had confidence in the rationality of the universe (as we'll soon see), already

  trusted in progress (as we'll see next), and already appreciated the quantitative

  method (as we just saw). So Jaki's claim that only Christianity could inspire

  these things is clearly false.

  Like other recent advocates of this new delusion, Stark emphasizes the

  "rationality of the universe" angle: unless you believe in a rational Creator, who

  made everything from nothing, you won't have any reason to believe the

  universe is rational or obeys discoverable laws of physics. But not only is this

  false, it's not even logical. D'Souza insists "the presumption" that "the universe is

  rational [is] quite impossible to prove" and therefore requires theological

  justification.28 But that the universe is rational is observed. So it doesn't have to

  be proved. Such a belief requires no faith or theology because it rests entirely on

  evidence. Pagans responded to this observation in either of two ways: exactly the

  same way later Christians did, or exactly the same way modern atheists do.

  Neither marked any impediment to science.

  Those who didn't believe in intelligent design had to explain where all this

  observed consistency and order then came from, which compelled them to

  scientific inquiry, precisely to discover the real causes. Hence ancient doubters

  and pantheists, like Strato, Erasistratus, Epicurus, or Asclepiades sought

  explanations in the inevitable interaction of natural laws and forces. They didn't

  use our "law" metaphor but others instead, like "physical necessity" and the

  "inherent nature" of things, but these amounted to the same thing: objects floated

  on water, for example, because of the inevitable interaction of innate forces in a

  discernible pattern. No God needed. No belief in Creation required. All is just

  the outcome of natural causes. Hence
even atheism could be no impediment to

  science. To the contrary, it all but entails it, since there is no other way for

  atheists to explain what they see.

  And most likely, if you weren't an atheist, you were a creationist. Most

  intellectual polytheists believed in a Creator who had intelligently ordered the

  cosmos, that this order could be discovered by the human mind, and that such

  discovery honored God. Scientists like Galen and Ptolemy were thus motivated

  to pursue scientific inquiry by their religious piety, exactly as Stark claims

  Christians were, and for exactly the same reasons. In Galen's scientific tour de

  force On the Uses of the Parts, a multivolume survey of human anatomy that

  remains one of the most empirically persuasive defenses of intelligent design

  ever written, he declares his pagan motives for conducting all the meticulous and

  exhaustive handson research the book documents: "I am composing this sacred

  discourse as a true hymn of praise to our Creator. And I consider that I am really

  showing Him reverence not when I offer Him" countless expensive sacrifices

  "but when I myself first learn to know His wisdom, power, and goodness and

  then make them known to others.1129 Most philosophers agreed. Seneca argued

  scientific inquiry was a pious enterprise superior to the sacred mysteries of

  pagan religion, and Cicero argued God actually designed us to pursue scientific

  knowledge.30 We can find many more examples of pagans declaring theological

  motives for scientific inquiry.31 So when D'Souza claims a religious "impulse"

  to pursue science "came originally from Christianity," we can plainly see that's

  false.32 Pagan theology provided just as ample a motivation, as did atheism or

  pantheism.

  Cyclical Theory of Time

  Stark's claim that anyone who believes the world is locked in "endless cycles of

  progress and decay" can't conceive of "progress" is illogical: if they believe in

  cycles of progress and decay, they obviously believe in progress. You almost

  have to be delusional to miss such an obvious contradiction. Nevertheless, Stark

  irrationally insists the Greeks "rejected the idea of progress in favor of a never-

  ending cycle of being."33 Not only is this illogical, it's false.

  Belief in scientific progress is so well evidenced in ancient literature, it's a

  wonder anyone ever claimed the contrary.34 How can Stark claim the opposite?

  By not checking the scholarship on the subject, or even his own evidence. To

  support his claim all Stark provides are various irrelevant quotations that fail to

  demonstrate any connection at all between ancient theories of time and a belief

  in progress. In fact, the ancient idea of eternal cycles could be based on a belief

  in progress: it was assumed the universe was eternal (lacking any evidence to the

  contrary), but it was observed that society had not reached a perfect state of

  advancement in all the arts and sciences, but it would have if it had been

  advancing for all infinite time; therefore, periodic catastrophes must destroy

  civilizations and all record of their achievements, forcing men to start over from

  scratch. Aristotle believed some scarce oral lore might survive each catastrophe,

  but all written record and advanced knowledge must have been lost, otherwise

  we would still have it.35 Believing this in no way entails believing there is any

  end to progress, other than the destruction of your entire civilization-or, of

  course, the whole world, whose end the Christians believed was so imminent we

  should sooner ask why they would believe in progress, as to them it should seem

  futile.36 The pagans at least expected many thousands of years, even tens of

  thousands, in which to continue their advance.

 

‹ Prev