Anger and Forgiveness

Home > Other > Anger and Forgiveness > Page 17
Anger and Forgiveness Page 17

by Martha C. Nussbaum


  Do not destroy me on that day.

  Quaerens me, sedisti lassus:

  Seeking me, you sat in weariness,

  Redemisti Crucem passus;

  You redeemed me by enduring the Cross.

  Tantus labor non sit cassus.

  Let such effort not be in vain.

  Iuste iudex ultionis,

  Just judge of vengeance,

  Donum fac remissionis

  Make a gift of remission,

  Ante diem rationis.

  Before the day of reckoning.

  Ingemisco, tamquam reus;

  I moan like a guilty criminal.

  Culpa rubet vultus meus;

  My face blushes with my fault.

  Supplicanti parce, Deus.

  Spare me, God, your suppliant.

  Qui Mariam absolvisti,

  You who absolved Mary,

  Et latronem exaudisti,

  And heard the thief,

  Mihi quoque spem dedisti.

  Have given hope to me, too.

  Preces meae non sunt dignae:

  My prayers are not worthy:

  Sec tu bonus fac benigne,

  But you, being good, act kindly:

  Ne perenni cremer igne.

  Do not burn me in eternal fire.

  Inter oves locum praesta,

  Grant me a place among the sheep,

  Et ab haedis me sequestra,

  And separate me from the goats,

  Statuens in parte dextra.

  Setting me on your right hand.

  Confutatis maledictis,

  When the wrongdoers are confounded

  Flammis acribus addictis:

  And thrown into the sharp flames,

  Voca me cum benedictis.

  Call me with the blessed.

  Oro supplex et acclinis,

  I implore, bent down, a suppliant,

  Cor contribum quasi cinis:

  My heart as contrite as ashes,

  Gere curam mei finis.

  Show concern for my end.

  4

  Intimate Relationships

  The Trap of Anger

  Do you acknowledge your wife?

  — Seneca, Medea 1021: Medea to Jason, as she throws

  the murdered children down from the roof

  He tried to let reason rise to the surface— how hard he tried.

  — Philip Roth, American Pastoral: Swede Levov, learning

  from his estranged daughter Merry, the “Rimrock Bomber,”

  that she has murdered four people

  I. Vulnerability and Depth

  Betrayed wife, abandoned mother, she says that her anger is morally

  right, and the audience is likely to agree. She invokes Juno Lucina, guard-

  ian of the marriage bed, protector of childbirth, to come to her aid. But

  since her anger demands misery for Jason, she also calls on a darker

  group of divinities:

  Now, now be near, goddesses who avenge crime, your hair foul

  with writhing serpents, grasping the black torch in your bloody

  hands— be near— as once, dread spirits, you stood about my

  marriage bed. Bring death to this new wife, death to her father,

  to all the royal line. (Seneca, Medea 13– 18)

  Medea’s anger seems both justified and hideous. Before long, she mur-

  ders her own children, in order to inflict the maximum pain on Jason—

  despite the fact that their death also deprives her of love, a fact of which

  she has long since lost sight. She tosses their bodies down to him from

  the roof on which she stands, the “last votive offering” (1020) of their

  marriage. Now finally, she says, he must acknowledge the presence of

  his wife. Punishment accomplished, she feels her dignity and self- respect

  restored. “Now I am Medea,” she exclaims (910). “My kingdom has come

  91

  92

  Anger and Forgiveness

  back. My stolen virginity has come back… . Oh festal day, o wedding

  day” (984– 86).1

  Medea’s story is all too familiar. Few betrayed spouses murder their

  children to hurt their betrayer, but many certainly aim to inflict pain, and

  these efforts often have heavy collateral damages. Even when self- restraint

  prevents the enactment of anger’s wishes, ill will seethes within, just hop-

  ing for some bad outcome for the wrongdoer and his new family. And so

  often that ill will sneaks out after all, in litigation, in subtle deflection of children’s affections, or maybe only in an unwillingness to trust men again,

  which Medea aptly expresses through her fantasy of restored virginity.

  But many will say that her payback wish is justified— so long as it

  does not go quite to the extreme point of crime. In the intimate domain,

  even people otherwise sympathetic to a critique of anger often hold that

  anger is morally right and justified.2 (I used to hold this view.) People,

  and women especially, should stand up for themselves and their dimin-

  ished status. They should not let themselves be pushed around. They

  owe it to their self- respect to be tough and uncompromising.3 Maybe,

  just maybe, if the wrongdoer apologizes with sufficient profuseness and

  self- abasement, some restoration might possibly be imagined— or not.

  And if not, the ritual of apology and abasement can become its own

  reward.

  Life is too short. That is in essence what I shall say in this chapter.

  And we could stop there. Nonetheless, since this is philosophical argu-

  ment, I won’t stop there. Instead, following the lead of chapter 2’s analy-

  sis of anger, I shall ask about the role of both anger and forgiveness in

  intimate relationships, and how my previous account of payback, status

  anger, and the Transition applies in this domain. I shall focus on anger

  involving parents and adult children, anger between spouses or partners,

  and anger at oneself.4

  I shall try to accomplish four things in this chapter. First, I’ll describe

  the features of intimate relationships that make them require special

  treatment, where anger is concerned. Second, I’ll argue that in this spe-

  cial domain a Stoic response is usually inappropriate and that emotions

  such as grief and fear are often appropriate— but not anger, apart from

  Transition- Anger. Third, I’ll respond to the claim that anger is essential

  in order to assert one’s self- respect and stand up for one’s dignity when

  one has been seriously wronged in this realm. And fourth, I’ll answer

  the related claim that anger is necessary (in this realm) in order to take

  the other person seriously: that a non- angry response does not show

  sufficient respect for the wrongdoer. Along the way, I’ll attend to related

  issues concerning forgiveness, and also to the issues of empathy and play-

  fulness, which I’ve tentatively marked out as playing a productive role.

  Intimate Relationships

  93

  Here’s where we are. I have argued that the conceptual content of

  anger includes the idea of a wrongful act against something or someone

  important to the self, and that anger (with one important exception) also

  includes, conceptually, the idea of some sort of payback, however subtle.

  This being the case, even when a serious wrongful act has really been

  committed, anger is ethically doomed, in one of two ways. Either the vic-

  tim imagines that payback will restore the important thing that was dam-

  aged (someone’s life, for example)— but
this is metaphysical nonsense,

  however common and deeply engrained in human cultures, in literature,

  and, probably, in our evolutionary equipment. Or the person imagines

  that the offense is not really about life, or bodily integrity, or other important goods, but is a matter of relative status only: it is what Aristotle calls a

  “down- ranking.” In this case, the payback idea does after all make a grim

  sort of sense, since lowering the wrongdoer does relatively raise up the

  wronged. But this emphasis on status is normatively defective. A rational

  person will therefore reject both of these flawed roads, which I call the

  road of payback and the road of status, and will rapidly move toward what I call the Transition, turning from anger to constructive thoughts about

  future welfare.

  There is one species of anger, I argued, that is not flawed in these

  ways. I call it Transition- Anger, because, while it acknowledges the

  wrong, it then moves forward. Its entire cognitive content is, “How out-

  rageous. That should not happen again.” Transition- Anger, a borderline

  case of anger, is not as common as we might at first think. So often the

  wish to return pain for pain sneaks in, contaminating it.

  Let’s also recall another piece of terminology. Anger is “well-

  grounded” when all of its cognitive content is correct apart from the

  payback idea: the person is in possession of correct information about

  who has done what to whom, that it was wrongful, and also about the

  magnitude of the damage that has been wrongfully done. It is something

  worth being intensely concerned about. Anger in intimate relationships,

  I’ll argue, is often well- grounded.

  II. Intimacy and Trust

  What is special about intimate relationships? Four things, I believe. First,

  they are unusually pivotal to people’s sense of what it is for their lives to go well, to their eudaimonia, to use Aristotle’s term. The other person, and the relationship itself, are cherished component parts of one’s own flourishing life— and the relationship weaves its way through many other ele-

  ments of life, in such a way that many pursuits become shared pursuits,

  94

  Anger and Forgiveness

  and goals shared goals.5 A rupture thus disrupts many aspects of one’s

  existence.

  Second, such relationships involve great vulnerability because they

  involve trust. Trust is difficult to define, but one can begin by saying,

  with Annette Baier,6 that it is different from mere reliance.7 One may rely

  on an alarm clock, and to that extent be disappointed if it fails to do its

  job, but one does not feel deeply vulnerable, or profoundly invaded by

  the failure. Similarly, one may rely on a dishonest colleague to continue

  lying and cheating, but this is reason, precisely, not to trust that person; instead, one will try to protect oneself from damage. Trust, by contrast,

  involves opening oneself to the possibility of betrayal, hence to a very

  deep form of harm. It means relaxing the self- protective strategies with

  which we usually go through life, attaching great importance to actions

  by the other over which one has little control. It means, then, living with

  a certain degree of helplessness.

  Is trust a matter of belief or emotion? Both, in complexly related

  ways. Trusting someone, one believes that she will keep her commit-

  ments, and at the same time one appraises those commitments as very

  important for one’s own flourishing. But that latter appraisal is a key

  constituent part of a number of emotions, including hope, fear, and, if

  things go wrong, deep grief and loss. Trust is probably not identical to

  those emotions, but under normal circumstances of life it often proves

  sufficient for them. One also typically has other related emotions toward

  a person whom one trusts, such as love and concern. Although one typi-

  cally does not decide to trust in a deliberate way, the willingness to be

  in someone else’s hands is a kind of choice, since one can certainly live

  without that type of dependency, and Stoics do.8 In any case, living with

  trust involves profound vulnerability and some helplessness, which may

  easily be deflected into anger.

  A third distinctive feature of intimate relationships pertains to break-

  down scenarios. The damage involved in the breakdown of an intimate

  relationship, because it is internal and goes to the heart of who one is,

  cannot fully be addressed by law, though people certainly try. Even

  though, as I’ve said, most forms of wrongdoing are in some sense irrep-

  arable (the murdered person cannot be brought back, rape cannot be

  undone), nonetheless a decent legal system does relieve people of much

  of the practical and emotional burden of dealing with such cases, by

  incapacitating the wrongdoer and deterring future wrongs. It thus assists

  what I’ve called the Transition. When someone you love harms you,

  however, even though in cases of violence or fraud one should turn to

  the law for assistance, the relationship is sufficiently central to one’s well-being that the law cannot exhaust the emotional task of dealing with it.

  Beyond a certain point there is really no place to go, except into your own

  Intimate Relationships

  95

  heart— and what you find there is likely to be pretty unpleasant. So there

  is something lonely and isolating about these harms; they involve a pro-

  found helplessness. Once again, this helplessness can easily be deflected

  into anger, which gives the illusion of agency and control.

  A fourth feature might point in a more constructive direction,

  although all too often it doesn’t: We typically form intimate relationships

  with people we like. We choose our spouses, and even though parents do

  not choose their children or children their parents, there is typically, in

  cases that are not really awful, a symbiosis that produces liking on both

  sides, though adolescence certainly obscures this. Most other people in

  the world, by contrast, are not people with whom one would choose to

  live. It’s pretty easy to find them irritating, or off- putting, or even disgusting. How many people who sit next to one by chance on an airplane are

  people with whom one would be happy living in the same house for an

  extended period of time? But a spouse, a lover, a child— these people are

  welcomed, and there usually remains something nice about them that is

  not utterly removed by whatever it is they have done. The target of anger

  is the person, but its focus is the act, and the person is more than the

  act, however difficult it is to remember this. This nice something could

  become another knife to twist in the wound of betrayal (to the extent that

  a person is appealing, it’s harder to say good riddance), but on the other

  hand it could also be a basis for constructive thought about the future— in

  a restored relationship or some new connection yet to be invented.

  We now need to figure out how, in this special domain, anger and

  forgiveness properly figure. Is anger often well- grounded? If so, might it

  ever be fully justified? What becomes, or should become, of its fantasies

  of payback? Do people owe it to their self- respect to get angry and to be

 
uncompromising (as so many suggest)? Or is anger more likely to be an

  impediment to constructive forward- looking projects and healthy rela-

  tionships, a narcissistic “dance” in which one indulges at the price of not

  trying to figure out what the real problems are?9 As Bishop Butler notes,

  “[C] ustom and false honor are on the side of retaliation and revenge …

  and … love of our enemies is thought too hard a saying to be obeyed.”10

  But we don’t have to agree with custom.

  Such breakdowns typically, and rightly, involve deep grief, and

  grief needs to be dealt with. Grief is amply warranted: intimate relation-

  ships are very important parts of a flourishing life. (Here the Stoics are

  wrong.) But grief, and the helplessness it typically brings with it, are

  usually not well addressed by allowing anger to take the center of the

  stage. All too often, anger becomes an alluring substitute for grieving,

  promising agency and control when one’s real situation does not offer

  control. I shall argue that the way to deal with grief is just what one might expect: mourning and, eventually, constructive forward- looking action to

  96

  Anger and Forgiveness

  repair and pursue one’s life. Anger is often well- grounded, but it is too

  easy for it to hijack the necessary mourning process. So a Transition from

  anger to mourning— and, eventually, to thoughts of the future— is to be

  strongly preferred to anger nourished and cultivated.

  And what of forgiveness? Is forgiveness of the classic transactional

  sort a healthy and morally admirable process, or is it, all too often, a

  covert form of retaliation? Even at its mildest and most morally valuable,

  might it not be (to use Bernard Williams’s phrase, in a different context)

  “one thought too many,” a labored deflection from a spirit of generosity

  and spontaneity that is more valuable still?11

  And if the standard transactional sort of forgiveness turns out to

  have serious defects, might there be a type of unconditional forgiveness,

  a struggle within the self to free oneself from corrosive anger, that does

  have considerable moral value?

  Let me concede at the outset three points in favor of anger that

  I already conceded in chapter 2. Anger is often useful as a signal (to one-

  self and/ or to others) of a problem; thus it is a good idea to attend to one’s angry responses— bearing in mind many of them are unreliable, signs of

 

‹ Prev