Anger and Forgiveness

Home > Other > Anger and Forgiveness > Page 29
Anger and Forgiveness Page 29

by Martha C. Nussbaum


  email), “I don’t have to explain myself to you.” At this point, Louise

  really did have a decision, for she did not have to see that person again

  or teach with him; but she also thought more and more that he had prob-

  ably just had a big memory lapse and was ashamed, and worried about

  aging. Furthermore, she really did want a paper by him. So in the end

  she decided that to try further to extract an apology was going to doom

  future interactions. Looking to the general welfare (!), she proposed that

  he should write the paper anyway, and have someone else deliver it; and

  she invited him to talk about it over a drink. He accepted. (Louise might

  not so quickly invite him to a future event, however.)

  I think that both of these were pretty good solutions (no doubt influ-

  enced by the fact that Louise has been writing a book on anger and its

  futility). Relationships were preserved, she had a clearer idea what she

  could and could not expect from these two people, and she had preserved

  the fruitful intellectual collaboration, and quasi- friendship (real friend-

  ship in Case A). Did Louise get angry? Sure, for a short time. In the first

  case, it probably was Transition- Anger, and nothing more: Louise knows

  the person well enough not to let him make her really mad (usually). In

  the second case Louise really was annoyed, but then she headed back

  from the abyss, and decided that a positive take on the situation would

  create more welfare for all in the long run. So she had a short spurt of real anger, but then turned to the Transition. After all, when you work with

  people you buy into who they are. It’s foolish to expect to change them,

  so you just have to figure out how to grapple with reality.

  Now for the third. This one is slippery, because the whole group is

  involved, and different people react in different ways. What does not

  work: getting visibly angry at the person and treating him rudely. This

  reaction, natural enough among some colleagues, just creates tension

  in the whole group. What doesn’t work for long is talking to him about

  it— his behavior is just too much a part of who he is by now, and the

  whole problem is that he doesn’t know how he affects others. What does

  work, often, is firm and frequent interruption, which he takes very well.

  But the most creative welfare- enhancing solution of all was devised by

  an administrator, who changed the person’s teaching schedule so that

  he would finish class some minutes after the lunchtime discussions had

  already started, and thus arrive late, with the result that he did not get

  to set the topic, and was therefore much less disruptive. This case shows

  that forward- looking thinking is everything. What would be accom-

  plished by getting mad at this person? It would be like getting mad at a

  genius two- year- old. Even Transition- Anger probably is a waste of emo-

  tional energy. And it’s important that this is a nice and generous genius

  two- year- old.

  The Middle Realm

  159

  Let’s briefly contrast another case, Case D, of a genius two- year- old

  who is not so nice. Unfortunately, the academy is filled with such peo-

  ple. This important scholar was being invited to participate in a panel

  inaugurating a new research center Louise’s university was opening in

  a developing country. Louise was in charge of planning one of the big

  opening- event panels, and this person was an important part of the plan,

  because of the unique value of his work, recognized by a Nobel Prize.

  Other high- quality participants would probably accept only if his partici-

  pation was assured. This man engaged in characteristic delay tactics, and

  then requested first- class transportation, along with business- class trans-

  portation for his wife (!), something that is illegal under usual university

  rules and a sign of infantile narcissism. But Louise knew from bitter expe-

  rience that it was futile to get upset or even mention these defects to D, so she told university administrators that this is just how he is, and we want

  him there, so you’d better resign yourself to giving him what he asks.

  They knew their man, and agreed with Louise. In this instance, anger was

  not even in the offing, just weary detachment. But there was also no rec-

  onciliation or restoration of a working relationship: Louise was thinking,

  don’t do anything with this person if you can possibly avoid it, but if you

  really have to work with him, treat him like a selfish genius two- year- old.

  This case shows the limits of non- anger: it doesn’t make a good working

  relationship when people are like this one. (Case C is quite different, and,

  with the help of non- anger, one may continue to feel much affection for

  the protagonist.) But at least non- anger makes it possible to get on with an intellectual event. (The difficulty of working with D is so notorious that

  on the occasion of Louise’s one prior cooperation with D, a conference at

  their own university, their invited plenary speaker, another Nobel Prize

  winner in D’s field, announced to a friend, himself yet another Nobel

  Prize winner in the same field, that he was on his way to city Z to speak

  at a conference co- organized by Louise and D. The friend’s response was,

  “That’s the most implausible thing I’ve ever heard.” So: non- anger can

  achieve the implausible!)

  In short: more or less everything we said about the casual domain

  is true in the collegial domain, with even richer occasions for comedy,

  given the deeper temptations to narcissism that the workplace offers, and

  perhaps especially the academic workplace. And the idea that one owes

  it to one’s self- respect to get mad is even more pernicious here than it was in casual interactions. In all four of my cases one might have had righteous indignation, and been “justified” after a fashion, but with disrup-

  tive consequences all around. The main difference is that in the collegial

  domain apology can be of real, albeit limited, usefulness— as evidence,

  going forward, that things will work better in the future, and thus as evi-

  dence that pursuing a close collaborative relationship could be fruitful.

  160

  Anger and Forgiveness

  But receiving an apology is very different from extracting an apology,

  which is usually a mistake. If people have the character flaw of not want-

  ing to admit they have made a mistake, a very common flaw, you could

  joust with them until doomsday, upping the emotional ante, and you

  would still get nowhere, except into the abyss. Instead of seeing things

  as all about oneself and one’s “due,” however, one can simply realize

  that some people don’t like to admit they are wrong, but they have other

  good characteristics that one can value and even like— and just figure out

  what to do about working with them henceforth. Others have true infan-

  tile narcissism, which comes in many varieties, some more benign than

  others— and then one must once again figure out what to do about that.

  Another thing we learn from these cases is that imagination and see-

  ing the situation from the other person’s viewpoint is an essential cor-

  rective to the narcissistic focus on
one’s own insulted need for payback.

  Extracting an apology would have been a way of (apparently) achieving

  payback, but it would really not have changed the situation in a use-

  ful way. Realizing something about the character and limits of each (that

  both the first and second have a particularly childish aversion to admit-

  ting they were wrong, that the second very likely is annoyed with himself

  for forgetting something important and doesn’t want to admit it, that

  the third is full of good will but incapable of listening) helped construct

  a response that was useful. Human relations are full of problems to be

  solved. It takes empathy to solve them well. And a sense of humor: for

  it helped to think of these interactions as scripts for an academic sitcom.

  Was Louise’s non- anger a way of not taking these four people seri-

  ously? Yes, if “taking seriously” means not finding what they do funny,

  or even childish. But why should we define “taking seriously” that way?

  Louise’s attitudes would probably make for bad intimate relationships

  with all four (although no doubt a strong maternal instinct would be an

  essential ingredient of any good intimate relationship with colleagues C

  and D— for someone else!), but that, fortunately, is not what we are con-

  templating here. Maybe Louise was a bit manipulative in Case B, using

  the colleague as a means to the success of the conference; and maybe the

  administrator was manipulative in Case C. But this just goes to show that

  in non- intimate relations it is not always bad to influence people’s behav-

  ior for the common good.

  V. Gratuitous Gratitude

  Although gratitude is in many respects a backward- looking cousin

  of anger, I argued in chapter 4 that it can be valuable in intimate rela-

  tionships because it helps constitute the reciprocal good will that such

  The Middle Realm

  161

  relationships rightly involve. But what about the Middle Realm? If the

  Stoics are correct that our dealings in this realm are not worthy of seri-

  ous concern (with exceptions to be considered in the next section), what

  then of gratitude? Basically, it seems to be inappropriate for similar rea-

  sons: just as we shouldn’t get angry because of the manifold insults and

  indignities of air travel, driving, and so many other aspects of daily life,

  we shouldn’t feel gratitude either when other people make these things

  go well: such an emotion betrays too intense a dependence on external

  goods. But, as before, we need to observe that gratitude is not exactly

  symmetrical to anger. First, it involves a wish to do good for someone,

  which seems less problematic than the wish to do ill, and is accompa-

  nied by pleasant feelings, which are not welfare- disruptive, rather than

  painful feelings, which often are. Second, it does not seem to be infected

  by magical thinking: the grateful person does not fantasize that giving a

  benefit to the person who has helped her will change the past. She usu-

  ally thinks either that it will promote future goods or that it is just a nice thing to do. So the real problem the Stoics raise is that of inappropriate

  dependency.

  But there is a type of gratitude in the Middle Realm that may be free

  from this problem. This is what I propose to call “gratuitous gratitude.”

  So often one becomes accustomed to the bad things that travel and other

  daily interactions bring with them. Avoiding anger in the Stoic way typi-

  cally involves lowering expectations for how these interactions will go,

  as one practices the usual Stoic praemeditatio malorum. Then, when something really nice happens, it is surprising and delightful. A really smart

  and competent car repairman, a tech support person on the phone at

  Comcast who actually knows what he or she is doing and is pleasant

  to talk to; a sales clerk at Walgreens who does not behave as if the very

  idea of answering a customer’s question is an insult; a guy waiting for

  a weight machine you are using in the gym who does not exhibit steroi-

  dal rage and impatience, but actually smiles and jokes, nicely; a teen-

  age girl at the same gym who returns a piece of paper I have dropped

  with a courteous “Excuse me, ma’am”— all these are windfalls of daily

  life, surprising because so rare, and therefore occasions for real pleasure.

  Is it only pleasure, or is the emotion gratitude as well? Often the latter,

  I believe.

  Is the pleasant emotion to that extent inappropriate? Here’s how one

  might argue that it is: You, Louise, have been insulating yourself from

  anger by expecting the worst, in true Stoic fashion, but you haven’t truly

  stopped caring about these things. Underneath your shield, you really

  care about politeness and good behavior, you child of the Main Line, and

  you are only pretending that you do not, in order to avoid being angry all

  the time. When good behavior arrives as a windfall, the strong emotion

  162

  Anger and Forgiveness

  you feel betrays the residual attachment to these fragile goods of fortune,

  and the emotion therefore is a sign that your Stoicizing project is woe-

  fully incomplete.

  Maybe. But maybe, too, it is perfectly all right to feel sudden pleasure

  and to think that the person who acted so well deserves a good turn in

  return (whether mere thanks and a warm smile, or a good review on the

  Internet). I prefer the more charitable interpretation, since after all, we’re talking about pleasure and doing good, which are always in short supply

  and don’t require elaborate justification.

  Let’s study an example, to make these intuitions more precise. I go

  to the market on the morning of a big dinner party, to buy fish for an

  elaborate Indian dish. I am fully expecting that I will be skinning the filets myself, and that it will take me a long time. (The market is not one where

  extraordinary service can be expected, and I do not expect it.) The man

  from whom I buy six pounds of salmon filets asks me whether I would

  like him to skin them and cut them into pieces (because I have mentioned

  the type of dish I’m making). My eyes widen, and I say yes. Watching

  his tremendous skill with his superior knives and superior deftness and

  strength, I feel more and more grateful: he is not only saving me a lot of

  time, he is doing it much better than I would do it. Part of my emotion

  is pleasure at his artistry, but part, too, is gratitude for the generosity of his offer and the help it has given me. I would definitely not have felt

  annoyed had he not made the offer: it was a total windfall. So I don’t

  think I am betraying any residual attachment to external goods in my

  emotion. But it is a really nice emotion, and I am hoping, in addition to

  warm thanks, to do him a good turn in some way (though, since he is

  head of his department, I am not sure what, despite having written down

  his name, I could possibly do).

  In the collegial domain, these cases take a more complex form. Let me

  give two examples, returning to my alter ego Louise as I narrate them. In

  the first case, Louise is working on a project that involves giving a series

  of lectures, and she suddenly receives lengthy and
extremely helpful and

  insightful comments from a member of her profession with whom she

  has not conversed in years, and who had previously treated her work

  with contempt. He had heard one of her lectures, and then bothered to

  go read, with great care, the related parts of her manuscript. She certainly

  was not awaiting comments from him, and would not have been even

  slightly irritated if he had not sent any. Indeed, after thirty years she had finally brought herself to a point of non- anger at which his presence in

  a large auditorium did not have the psychic effect of Seneca’s dragged

  bench— or, at least, only that of a bench dragged a long way away! But

  nonetheless: she was extremely pleased and grateful, since the comments

  were really very helpful to her revisions. While it would have been a

  The Middle Realm

  163

  mistake for her to carry on her career with any reliance on this person,

  and while it would have been excessive to express her gratitude by invit-

  ing him to a dinner party, since she doesn’t like him, she felt it was right

  to feel gratitude, since the comments were extensive and had taken him

  at least some time to write. (He is a very rapid worker, but even so. …)

  Maybe he did it only out of a rigid deontological standard of hospitality,

  but so what? It was good.

  With the second case, we return to Case D of my earlier discussion,

  and an update. When this difficult colleague did finally attend the open-

  ing in the developing country, he arrived after traveling approximately

  twenty hours. But instead of being tired and cranky he was a bundle of

  positive energy. He not only gave a marvelous lecture at the opening,

  he also rushed out to see the historical sites of the city, returning with

  passionate enthusiasm and many questions. Louise was grateful for his

  excellent contribution, and for the additional contribution that his sheer

  presence gave to the event, since he is truly very distinguished— but also

  for his love of a country she loves, and for his general quite unexpected

  good will and positivity.

  Colleagues can give pleasant surprises. Since many are children, and

  many of the problems of working with them derive from that source, it

  is well to remember that children also delight and please. As in the more

 

‹ Prev