Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Home > Other > Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe > Page 14
Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe Page 14

by Bart Schultz


  efforts to impart them. Strong powers of abstract and discursive thought must be

  always rare: but I lament that we do so little to stimulate and direct them. Nor

  must we forget that it is much more important for ordinary men to learn to think

  correctly about historical and philosophical subjects than about philological: and

  that each study requires to a certain extent a special training; which men who do

  not receive it from others have to acquire for themselves (except in the case of a

  gifted few) by gradually finding out their mistakes and deficiencies in a prolonged

  process of self-education.

  Such thoughts were given fuller expression in “The Theory of Classical

  Education,” which Sidgwick published in . There he pointedly ob-

  served that “the advocates of classical education, while they rightly insist

  that educational studies should be capable of disciplining the mind, forget

  that it is equally desirable that they should be capable of stimulating it.”

  With true Socratic irony, he cites a Mr. Clark’s claim that “it is a strong

  recommendation to any subject to affirm that it is dry and distasteful,”

  commenting that one “cannot help thinking that there is some confusion

  here between ‘dry’ and ‘hard’” (MEA –).

  These may not seem like democratic sentiments, given the concern with

  elite philosophical education, but the message is at least the broadly Millian

  one about making education more relevant and thereby improving the

  quality of public deliberation. When Sidgwick trained his critical acumen

  on his own time and place, he was concerned with both the state of popular

  morality and the inadequate reflectiveness of elite morality, as this was

  molded by elite education.

  Much could be made of Sidgwick’s reform of classics at Cambridge.

  Again, the influence of classical authors on his philosophical vision

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  has sometimes been underestimated out of an exaggerated sense of

  how Sidgwick’s Cambridge differed from T. H. Green’s Oxford. As

  Christopher Brooke has observed, the

  history of Oxford and Cambridge is a saga of mutual imitation; and yet there have

  been some things which Cambridge has failed to copy from Oxford, to its loss.

  By linking philosophy to classics in Mods and Greats the Oxford tutors ensured

  that numerous undergraduates studied history and philosophy as well as classical

  literature; and although no Oxford moral philosopher of the age now seems to us

  to hold a candle to Sidgwick, far more Oxford students studied philosophy than

  sat at Sidgwick’s feet.

  Thus, the suggestion is that despite Sidgwick’s debts to Socrates, Plato,

  and Aristotle, and his feeling that the classics should not be an exercise in

  rote learning, he failed to turn Cambridge into the equivalent of Jowett’s

  Oxford, the hotbed of the Platonic revival, when he had the chance to

  do so by working more of the classics into the Moral Sciences Tripos.

  Robert Todd, quoting Sidgwick’s exasperated confession that he hated

  “the history of philosophy even more than any other history; it is so hard

  to know what any particular man thought, and so worthless when you do

  know it,” argues that it was just this analytical attitude that contributed

  to his downplaying of classical education at Cambridge. According to

  Todd:

  This larger need to understand the contemporary world was clearly one that

  Sidgwick satisfied philosophically in a Moral Sciences Tripos freed from any

  extensive historical studies. It helps explain why he was content to leave the study

  of ancient philosophy to the Classical Tripos, after he had found it unsuitable

  for an undergraduate curriculum in philosophy. In his own work Sidgwick of

  course made constructive use of the history of philosophy, ancient as well as

  modern. He also held general views about the nature and historical evolution

  of Greek ethical thought, and formulated a sound conception of the procedures

  to be followed in dealing with the history of philosophy. But none of this either

  significantly influenced him in the teaching of philosophy, or led him to emphasize

  the study of ancient philosophy in the Cambridge Moral Sciences Tripos. He

  placed limited value on historical studies in philosophy generally in the context

  of an undergraduate curriculum.

  As Todd observes, in “The Theory of Classical Education,” Sidgwick

  emphasized not only science but also modern literature, the branch of

  literature “which explains to us (as far as possible) the intellectual life of

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Unity

  

  our own age; which teaches us the antecedents of the ideas and feelings

  among which, and in which, we shall live and move.” This, as we shall see,

  would prove to be of fundamental importance: Sidgwick would devoutly

  carry on the Apostolic tradition of using modern literature, particularly

  poetry, to explore, express, and refine the human emotional fabric. Again,

  he was himself a poet and critic of some talent.

  And yet, in some respects, what Todd demonstrates is just how rele-

  vant Sidgwick found the classics to his ethical work. Todd notes that in his

  essay on “Liberal Education,” for example, in which Sidgwick posed the

  question of whether philosophy ought “to be studied, to the extent that it

  is at Oxford, through the medium of Plato and Aristotle,” he allowed that

  this would be appropriate for the history of ethics, since “the principles

  of ethics lie still involved in doubt and conflict” and hence might be bet-

  ter confronted via problems from a more remote period. This effort to

  achieve impartiality through greater historical distance would often serve

  as a counterweight to his view that progress had rendered historical ex-

  ample largely irrelevant, and it would be evident in such works as The

  Elements of Politics. But in any event, Sidgwick, in this essay, took the

  opportunity largely to endorse Mill’s recent lecture at St. Andrews on

  the nature of education, noting that he and Mill agreed that “there should

  be some literary element in general education” and that “classical litera-

  ture,” including Plato and Aristotle, is “best adapted for this purpose,”

  though the superiority is only a matter of degree and study of it should not

  preclude interest in other literatures. This is not quite the stock Cambridge

  emphasis on Newton, Locke, and mathematics, but a more balanced view,

  though Oxford is criticized for its “exaggerated neglect of the more defi-

  nite branches of study in favour of the less definite.” For the Sidgwickian

  student: “Be
fore he attempts the problems with which the human mind

  is still militant, he should understand the processes by which it had been

  triumphant.”

  Furthermore, by Sidgwick’s lights, much of the deeper educational en-

  terprise took place more or less outside of the formal institutional context.

  When it came to the discussion societies, for example, the differences be-

  tween Cambridge and Hellenizing Oxford were less marked; education

  could be a very personal affair at both of the ancient universities. Indeed,

  it had to be. Like Mill and the early Apostles, Sidgwick was not enamoured

  with the educational quality of formal Oxbridge: “the warmest admirer of

  these ancient seats of learning is forced to speak of their intellectual aspect

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  in much colder terms; and the comparatively meagre results of the large

  sums spent upon liberal studies there, has become a commonplace with

  the critics who undertake the ungrateful task of making periodic inroads

  on our national self-complacency.”

  To be sure, Sidgwick did have a rather different vision of professional

  philosophy from that of Hellenzing (or idealizing) Oxford, one that was

  more analytical and less historical. But that should not be taken to mean

  that he disparaged the value of this philosophical inheritance in the fashion

  of later (or even Comtean) positivists. In an early paper, probably delivered

  to the Apostles, Sidgwick struggled with the question, as his title put it,

  “Is Philosophy the Germ or the Crown of Science?” He was keenly aware

  that “the great philosophers each has made a system, and his system has

  made a noise and filled a considerable space in the horizon of thought for

  a time but ultimately it has collapsed, dwindled, and vanished, leaving

  behind it what? Why some particular discovery some luminiferous and

  fructiferous ideas in some special department of study.” But he could not

  rest content with this reduction of philosophy to the “germ” of science,

  or with the disparaging views of the ongoing philosophical quest it could

  support:

  Many would say that man is now mature: his time for the stimulating dreams of

  youth is over: he is deeply impressed with the vanity of attempting ever anew the

  solution of the insoluble: and he has been impressed with this in time, because the

  incidental profit of these vain attempts has ceased.

  I confess that to me to argue this seems a flagrant abandonment of just the

  basis of experience on which the arguer plants his feet. How can we tell that

  the function of Philosophy is over? Even if we attribute to it no more than this

  Germinal function? If a man says to me that he and his friends have really no

  interest in solving the Universe, I have nothing to answer but ‘Then in heaven’s

  name leave the universe alone.’ But if he tries to prove that any one else ought to

  leave it alone, I ask by what empirical arguments he proves that this crisis in the

  history of thought has been reached: that the endeavour to grasp the Golden robe

  of complete Wisdom will no longer as of old leave even a fragment thereof in our

  hands.

  But more: it may be said that it is impossible that Philosophy should perform

  this germinal function, as long as we have made up our minds that this is it’s only

  function. The supreme effort from which alone any partial discovery of the kind

  described can come, cannot be made without a hope of the supreme attainment

  that transcends all partial discoveries. Therefore in this as in other matters just

  from the most practical point of view, for the winning of just the most definitely

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Unity

  

  measurable results we must pursue the ideal: and that though the face of the ideal

  is “evermore unseen/and fixed upon the far sea line.” (CWC)

  These last lines, a bit of Tennyson’s “The Voyager” that Sidgwick would

  frequently quote, are perhaps a little too bleak to capture his early vision of

  philosophy. Consider, by contrast, how he responded to his friend Roden

  Noel in a letter of :

  You say that “we do not use terms in the same way” and there is one which

  we certainly do not – Absolute. I do not mean by it total complete: all that can be known about the objects. But I oppose it to relative in the sense in which

  you generally but not always use the word: i.e. implying that two contradictory

  opinions about the same object – say a planet – held by two persons may both be

  true.

  It is this latter opinion, and all that hangs on it, which I feel it important to

  refute. As to the unknowable, I admit that I have a faith that nothing is intrinsically unknowable: that if one thing is true, true today yesterday and for ever, true for

  all men; then is the Spirit of Truth come who will guide us into all truth. Or, (to

  parody Archimedes,) ‘Give me but a locus Standi and I will prove the Universe.

  (CWC)

  To deny the larger philosophical impulse, then, would be self-defeating

  and contrary to his faith in “things in general.” And after all, if Mill

  could join in the Platonic revival, so could Sidgwick, and all the more

  easily. Both thought that they were being truer to the Greek spirit than

  their critics:

  And if there be any who believe that the summit of a liberal education, the crown of

  the highest culture, is Philosophy – meaning by Philosophy the sustained effort, if

  it be no more than an effort, to frame a complete and reasoned synthesis of the facts of the universe – on them it may be especially urged how poorly equipped a man

  comes to such a study, however competent he may be to interpret the thoughts of

  ancient thinkers, if he has not qualified himself to examine, comprehensively and

  closely, the wonderful scale of methods by which the human mind has achieved its

  various degrees of conquest over the world of sense. When the most fascinating of

  ancient philosophers taught, but the first step of this conquest had been attained.

  We are told that Plato wrote over the door of his school, ‘Let no one who is without

  geometry enter here.’ In all seriousness we may ask the thoughtful men, who

  believe that Philosophy can still be best learnt by the study of the Greek masters,

  to consider what the inscription over the door should be in the nineteenth century

  of the Christian era. (MEA –)

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  In effect,
the classicists had abandoned the actual spirit of Greek phi-

  losophy, had become a church of sorts, requiring submersion in scripture.

  Everything vital was missing. And of course, this was in perfect parallel to

  Sidgwick’s thoughts about orthodox religion. The two were scarcely sep-

  arable – the question of the role of philosophy could not be separated from

  the question of the role of religion. By Sidgwick’s time, to promote the

  one was to demote the other, and this was a heavy responsibility, one that

  bore especially heavily on an academic liberal out to improve cultural life.

  Given the fragility of goodness, the precariousness of ordinary decency,

  the philosopher’s position was fraught, even if it was not the main causal

  factor involved in the degeneration of a society’s morals. For Sidgwick,

  it was crucial to understand how the sun of philosophy might rise, in his

  own era, and what this would mean for a popular morality that was of-

  ten as confused and incoherent as that of the ancient Athenians. Indeed,

  materialism and mocking irreverence had never had so much corrosive

  power, and this courtesy of science itself. And this was not to mention

  sexual matters.

  What was a philosopher to do? What was the larger cultural project,

  beyond improving the institutional apparatus of philosophical education?

  Just how important was it not to “be over-conscientious about using words

  which do not to us convey what we believe”? And what kind of Millian

  reformer could insist that “our ideas are more or less incommunicable to

  uneducated minds and that what we have out-grown is actually not only

  ‘best for them’ but perhaps brings them as near as they can be brought to

  the truth”?

  II. After the Way of Heresy

  He who begins by loving Christianity better than truth, will proceed by loving

  his own sect or church better than Christianity, and end in loving himself better

  than all.

  Samual Taylor Coleridge, Aids to Reflection

  The more a man feels the value, the true import, of the moral and religious

  teaching which passes amongst us by the name of Christianity, the more will

  he hesitate to base it upon those foundations which, as a scholar, he feels to

 

‹ Prev