Book Read Free

Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Page 26

by Bart Schultz


  has found with scrupulous veracity, and the greatest attainable exactness and

  precision. (CS –)

  This careful statement, at once so sensitive to the complexities of large-

  scale modern societies and so insistent on the Socratic virtues at work in

  scientific practice and public debate, beautifully encapsulates Sidgwick’s

  hopes for the direction of modern culture. The tone irresistibly recalls

  Dewey’s claim that the “the traits of good method are straightforwardness,

  flexible intellectual interest or open-minded will to learn, integrity of

  purpose, and acceptance of responsibility for the consequences of one’s

  activities including thought.” For Sidgwick, it is pointless for theologians

  to dwell “on the imbecility of the inquisitive intellect” or “the inadequacy

  of language to express profound mysteries” – for clearly, “the exceptional

  protection that has been claimed for theological truth is a fatal privilege.”

  It is a plain fact that “the divergence of religious beliefs, conscientiously

  entertained by educated persons, is great, is increasing, and shows no

  symptom of diminution.” The (highly Apostolic) question, then, is how

  to feel that same security that we feel with respect to science in connection

  with religious inquiry: namely, “that our teacher is declaring to us truth

  precisely as it appears to him, without reserve or qualification.” And from

  this, to ask: how are we to organize “religious instruction, and combine in

  a common formula of worship?” (CS –)

  Here, of course, we confront the specific problem of subscription, the

  different grades of expected conformity, and so on, a problem made all the

  more poignant by the demand for free and open inquiry. After all, Sidgwick

  argues, consider the potentially excruciating position of an “intelligent and

  promising young clergyman.” Suppose, in keeping with the standard of

  modern inquiry, “we impress on him the need which the Church has

  of a learned clergy; we bid him read, study, investigate; we encourage

  him (as his better nature prompts him) to respect learning and sincerity

  wherever he finds them, and to weigh arguments with the single desire to

  be convinced of the truth.” But then, of course,

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  cb.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Unity

  

  we inform him, that if Truth should appear to him to lie anywhere below a certain

  line drawn rather high up in the scale, honour and duty call upon him to withdraw

  from his ministerial functions, resign the prospects of his career, uproot himself

  from a position where he may feel that his means of exercising good are daily

  growing, allow his acquired faculties of special work to become useless, and, amid

  the distress of his friends and kindred, with his abandoned profession hanging

  like a weight round his neck, endeavour, late in life, to learn some new work by

  which he may live.

  Even if such a person was quite thoroughly orthodox when ordained, how

  could he be confident that further study would raise no doubts? Who

  would go into the business on such conditions? As Sidgwick pointedly

  remarks, “No one will venture to be ordained except those who are too

  fanatical or too stupid to doubt that they will always believe exactly what

  they believed at twenty-three” (CS –). And how much good will they

  do the church or, for that matter, society? How can education be translated

  into an ongoing process of educating?

  Here lies the more specific difficulty that especially troubles Sidgwick:

  what is

  the duty which the persons who form the progressive – or, to use a neutral term, the

  deviating – element in a religious community owe to the rest of that community;

  the extent to which, and the manner in which, they ought to give expression

  and effect to their opinions within the community; and the point at which the

  higher interests of truth force them to the disruption of old ties and cherished

  associations. (CS )

  How, given his sympathetic portrayal of the plight of the intelligent

  young clergyman, could Sidgwick take such a rigorist line concerning

  the evils of hypocrisy and the degradation of popular religious and moral

  feeling? After all, he had insisted that even those in his own position, those

  taking definite religious oaths, ought to resign rather than serve under such

  conditions. Would not the same standard, or an even more stringent one,

  apply to the actual teachers of religion?

  The firm Cloughian was clear that it did, hard as such self-sacrifice

  was to live with. His main point is that it is damaging in the extreme to

  pretend that the clergy should maintain an esoteric standard, different

  from the common understandings, that would leave them open to the

  charge of “solemn imposture.” Thus, “we look to the clergy to maintain

  the standard of, at any rate, the peaceful virtues; and . . . it is a serious

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  cb.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  blow to the spiritual interests of the country, that any considerable and

  respectable section of them should be charged with habitual unveracity

  and be unable to refute the charge.” Admittedly, given the state of society,

  it would be painful to always insist on such veracity, but the solution is to

  proceed “by openly relaxing the engagements, not by secretly tampering

  with their obligation” – and it is essential to do this openly, since no one will

  “take a strong interest in grievances by which no one will declare himself

  aggrieved.” (CS , ) Still, the clergy must meet a higher standard than

  the laity. Consider again the problem of the Virgin Birth:

  A man may certainly be a sincere Christian in the strictest sense – that is, he

  may believe that Jesus was God – without holding this belief. Many persons

  now take an intermediate view of miracles between accepting and rejecting them

  en bloc. They hold that miracles may occur, and that some recorded in the Gospels undoubtedly did occur; but that also legends may have been mixed up with the

  evangelical narrations, and that some probably have been. A man who holds this

  general view is very likely to reject the miraculous conception of Jesus. . . . Now,

  to him, this rejection may appear of no religious importance; it may even seem

  to him unreasonable that men should make their view of Christ’s character and

  function to depend upon the nature of his conception. Still, to the majority of

  Christians, the belief is so important – the gulf that divides those who hold it from those who reject it seems so great, that the confidence of a congregation in the

  veracity of their minister would be entirely ruined, if he avowed his disbelief in


  this doctrine and still continued to recite the Creed. And it seems to me, that a

  man who acts thus, can only justify himself by proving the most grave and urgent

  social necessity for his conduct. (CS )

  Clearly, this is what Sidgwick had in mind by way of the dangerous

  degradation of moral and religious feeling that lax subscription fostered –

  even the lax subscription of someone such as himself, a mere taker of

  definite oaths. In fact, even as regards the laity, he goes so far as to suggest

  that it is important to strive to approximate the ideal of a national ministry

  and form of genuine worship, and that the only way this could possibly

  be accomplished is through “the frank and firm avowal, on all proper

  occasions, on the part of the laity, of all serious and deliberate doctrinal

  disagreement with any portion of the service” (CS –). This, however,

  seems to have been a standard from which he exempted himself, as we

  shall see in due course.

  One might forgive Sidgwick for worrying, as he did, that the calculation

  of consequences that he carried out in the case of subscription was indeed

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  cb.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Unity

  

  rather “shadowy.” (As it would transpire, the vast uncertainty attending

  such calculations would be another major theme of the Methods, much to

  Sidgwick’s chagrin.) But in a famous article, “Sidgwick and Whewellian

  Intuitionism: Some Dilemmas,” Alan Donagan went so far as to deny

  that Sidgwick’s words and deeds were at all genuinely utilitarian, or even

  effective on behalf of his cause. Thus,

  In none of these transactions is there the slightest breath of utilitarianism. In The Ethics of Conformity and Subscription, Sidgwick closely followed Whewell’s application of the nonutilitarian principle of truth. And, to judge by the reasons he gave in his correspondence, he likewise acted on Whewellian grounds in resigning his

  fellowship. Both in acting, and in defending his action, utilitarian considerations

  appear to have entered his mind only to be dismissed. Yet of none of this are there

  any traces in The Methods of Ethics.

  Donagan was himself a true Whewellian, and one is tempted to say that

  that may help to explain why he was wrong on all counts. Sidgwick himself

  was quite clear, in writing to Mill, that he wanted to solve the problem

  of subscription in a utilitarian way, and if one misses the way in which

  his solution is in keeping with his utilitarianism, that may be because

  one is working with an inadequate notion of utilitarianism – as, it seems,

  was Donagan. For as Schneewind has explained, Sidgwick’s pamphlet

  anticipates his later views in several ways. First, he “insists on answering

  questions about practice in terms of realistic appraisals of the facts and the

  probabilities. He does not sketch an ideal church or an ideal society and

  ask how we can obtain guidance from considering it.” Second, he “fails to

  find any clear common-sense maxims which both relate specifically to the

  ethical issue concerning him and direct us to a definite solution to it. There

  is a duty of veracity; there are duties of fidelity to one’s chosen church; but

  there is no principle of similar scope which tells us what to do when these

  two sets of duties conflict.” And finally, the “difficulties are resolved, in

  each case, by an appeal to what is expedient or useful or least harmful –

  by an appeal, in short, to some form of the utilitarian principle.”

  This seems right. Schneewind is of course happy to concede – indeed,

  even to argue at length – that Sidgwick learned a tremendous amount from

  Whewell, who was the master of Trinity when Sidgwick arrived there, and

  whose work on moral philosophy was – much to Sidgwick’s dismay – part

  of the established curriculum. But the dual conviction that all “our rules

  are imperfect” and that even so “we must not discard the props which

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  cb.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  we have in our conceptions . . . of Truth, Justice &c.” had been, through the sixties, as close to a constant as Sidgwick could muster. Sidgwick

  would have been the first to agree that the calculation of consequences in

  cases such as this is a very hard thing to carry off with any plausibility;

  but, as with Mill, he would have denied that there was any real alterna-

  tive to trying, or that Whewell himself had effectively circumvented the

  problem.

  However, these are arguments that quickly lead to the heart of

  Sidgwick’s ethical theory, and they are better considered in connection

  with the Methods, the subject of the following chapter. At this juncture,

  the foregoing sketch of the common ground between Sidgwick’s pamphlet

  and his magnum opus should be sufficient to suggest how he could have

  worked out the lines of the latter in connection with the problem posed

  in the former. Those who doubt the connection between these works, or

  the utilitarian nature of that connection, ought to be given some pause by

  the fact that Mill himself weighed in on Sidgwick’s side, and this even

  though he was well known for advising dissenting young clergymen to

  reform the church from within, rather than leaving it in the hands of the

  more reactionary elements. Although Sidgwick expressed a certain dis-

  appointment with Mill’s response to his pamphlet, apparently thinking it

  a little too perfunctory in light of his great crisis, the truth is that Mill

  was warmly appreciative of Sidgwick’s efforts, even giving him a bit of

  sage advice that tacitly suggested considerable confidence in Sidgwick’s

  utilitarian potential:

  What ought to be the exceptions (for that there ought to be some, however few,

  exceptions seems to be admitted) to the general duty of truth? This large question

  has never yet been treated in a way at once rational and comprehensive, partly

  because people have been afraid to meddle with it, and partly because mankind

  have never yet generally admitted that the effect which actions tend to produce on

  human happiness is what constitutes them right or wrong. I would suggest that

  you should turn your thoughts to this more comprehensive subject.

  This Sidgwick did, and the result was The Methods of Ethics and what

  would turn out to be a lifelong engagement with matters of hypocrisy and

  integrity. The destiny that awaited him was an eternal struggle with the

  problems of this turbulent decade: self-cultivation versus self-sacrifice,

  skepticism versus belief, sympathetic unity versus conflictual difference,

  and the private versus the public.

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  cb.xml

  CY�
��/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Unity

  

  Before moving on to the Methods, however, mention should be made of

  a few other consequences that flowed from the Cloughian act of Sidgwick’s

  utilitarian conscience. Against Donagan, it must be said that there are ex-

  cellent reasons for sharing the view of so many of Sidgwick’s peers – that

  his resignation, the action of a high-minded man of spotless reputation and

  academic credentials, did have an important effect in speeding the aboli-

  tion of the educational tests. Donagan too hastily follows the somewhat

  dismissive account in Winstanley’s Later Victorian Cambridge, suggesting

  that, as Sidgwick himself insisted, change was already very much in the

  air and the elimination of the tests inevitable. But what Sidgwick’s more

  knowing champions appear to have recognized was that Sidgwick’s act had

  a disproportionate impact on Prime Minister Gladstone, who, although

  he had already unsuccessfully opposed the tests, would have been given

  a considerable boost in his efforts by Sidgwick’s example. Gladstone had

  for some time held Sidgwick in very high esteem.

  Another, somewhat personalized consequence of Sidgwick’s resigna-

  tion is recorded in the Memoir:

  Sidgwick threw himself heartily into the establishment by the University of an

  examination for women. The examination was first held in the summer of ,

  and he was one of the examiners. The establishment of this examination was

  an outcome of the active movement going on at the time in different parts of

  the country for providing women with improved educational opportunities –

  a movement the crying need for which was emphasised by the report of the

  Schools Inquiry Commission in , and the very unsatisfactory state of girls’

  and women’s education therein revealed. The demand was not for examination

  only, and schemes for instruction by course of lectures and classes were being

  tried in various places. Sidgwick had had his thoughts turned in a general way to

  the subject of the education of women by the writings of J. S. Mill, and doubtless

  also by F. D. Maurice, whose interest in it is well known, and who was . . . at this

  time Professor of Moral Philosophy at Cambridge. But his taking it up actively

 

‹ Prev