Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Home > Other > Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe > Page 45
Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe Page 45

by Bart Schultz


  cilable tension between two ultimate and comprehensive principles of rationality.

  But this is not to say that any dual-source view must fail to provide any practical

  guidance. To take two extreme cases: when I can promote a very great good at

  a very small cost to myself, other things being equal my strongest reason overall

  is to make the sacrifice; likewise, if I can add to the overall good only a little at very great cost to myself, other things being equal my strongest reason is not to

  make the sacrifice. In other words, the strength of the reasons grounded in the

  simple thought or the separateness of persons varies according to the good or bad

  at stake. The dilemma of practical reason is not quite what Sidgwick took it to be.

  It arises most starkly in those cases where I can produce a great increase in overall good at a great cost to myself. Here the simple thought and the separateness of

  persons pull hard against one another. The problem here is essentially a Hegelian

  (or Freudian) one. The intuitions about rationality and reasonableness we consult

  in such cases will have been shaped by an upbringing in a culture itself imbued

  with a particular understanding of the relative strengths of the reason to promote

  the good and the reason to promote one’s own good.

  Arguably, Sidgwick would have appreciated the reference to Hegel and

  felt himself equal to dealing with it, providing his own account of moral

  maturation. At any rate, on Crisp’s intricately developed line, the question

  of “whether morality permits one to pursue one’s own good at the expense

  of the overall good” invites the following response:

  [T]his gets things the wrong way round. If we are asked what morality consists

  in, we can identify it if we wish with the reason to promote the overall good. But

  there is no need for any notion of morality, prior to the reason to promote the

  good and the competing reason based on the separateness of persons, that will

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  rule on whether one is permitted or required to act on certain reasons on certain

  occasions.”

  In addressing Shelley Kagan’s penetrating attempt to defeat all such

  reasons arising from the personal point of view, Crisp develops some

  strikingly Sidgwickian themes:

  But what about the practical implications of the dual-source view? Am I seriously

  arguing that we should see killing and letting die as on a par, and be prepared

  to kill in pursuit of our own good? Am I suggesting that this is how we should

  bring up our children? These consequences may be so counterintuitive that the arguments for the dual-source view will have to be rejected.

  The dual-source view does not have these practical implications. First, since

  we have been brought up to accept common sense morality, and since we live in a

  culture based on common sense morality, killing is likely to be far more psycho-

  logically and socially costly than letting die. Secondly, these facts militate against educating any individual child to use the dual-source view in practice. Further,

  it would probably be a mistake for all of us to begin educating children to be practical dual-source theorists. Human beings are not creatures of pure reason.

  We have an evolutionary background and an emotional make-up which cannot

  be ignored in moral theory. In particular, we show a particular concern for those

  visibly near us, and for what we do to them. It may well be that these concerns, though they might not withstand close intellectual scrutiny, are somehow central

  to our becoming and continuing to be rational agents. The risk that this is so

  would be sufficient to justify not radically changing the moral education of our

  children. What is needed is common sense morality with a far greater emphasis

  on the importance of distributive justice and personal generosity.

  As Crisp notes, these arguments “parallel those for a ‘split-level’ version

  of utilitarianism.” Clearly, they resonate powerfully with Sidgwick’s views

  about the potential limitations of even a more highly evolved utilitarian so-

  ciety, absent any cosmic ordering, and the nature of moral maturation and

  cautious utilitarian reform. Crisp is, in effect, picking up the Sidgwickian

  project without the parapsychological and theistic or Buddhist options.

  Doubtless there is much to be said for all these interpretations and re-

  constructions of Sidgwick’s dualism, which collectively ought to convey

  something of the continuing relevance of the issues raised by the Methods.

  Beyond a certain point, however, it is just very difficult to say, for exam-

  ple, whether Sidgwick shifted his views on the question of “permissive”

  reasons, given that he did not use such terminology.

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Consensus versus Chaos

  

  But at least on the question of whether Sidgwick’s axiomatic grounding

  of egoism is really as elliptical as Shaver claims, it must be owned that a

  great many commentators have followed Sidgwick in moving too quickly to

  identify “prudence” with egoism, when giving a summary exposition of the

  dualism. Even Crisp, for example, flatly states that Sidgwick “took it as self-

  evident that one ought to aim at one’s own good on the whole, accepting

  that this good was merely a particular part of the general good.” And

  Marcus Singer, in a recent work, simply states that the “fundamental

  principles of Philosophical Intuitionism are the intuitively self-evident

  axioms of prudence or egoism, justice, and rational benevolence.”

  However, in a footnote, Singer does call attention to the interpretation

  anticipating Shaver’s advanced by Sidgwick’s student W. R. Sorley, in his

  A History of English Philosophy:

  It would appear . . . that this dualism was not adequately tested by [Sidgwick] and that it really arises from the ambiguity of the term prudence. Prudence may mean

  either “regard for one’s own good on the whole” or (what is not the same thing)

  the principle that “hereafter as such is neither less nor more valuable than now.”

  Both forms of statement are used by Sidgwick; but only the latter has a claim to

  express an absolute ethical principle; and it is not inconsistent with the axiom of

  benevolence.

  This would certainly suggest some powerful support for treating the move

  from axioms to egoism with much greater caution.

  Furthermore, Schneewind’s account, which remains the most ex-

  tensive, ends up reformulating Sidgwick’s axiom of prudence to read

  “Maximizing the agent’s own good is an ultimate right-making charac-

  teristic” and his axiom of benevolence to read “Maximizing the universal

  good is an ultimate right-making characteristic.” His claim is that “these

  formulations seem to express Sidgwick’s understandin
g of the two prin-

  ciples involved in the dualism of the practical reason, and they reveal its

  structure more plainly than his own statements do.” If the world does

  not have the requisite moral order, then it is “logically impossible” for

  both of these to be true, for “it cannot be true that it is actually right to do

  an act maximizing own-good and not actually right to do it.”

  Thus we have found the contradiction, removable by a factual proposition, which

  lies at the heart of Sidgwick’s problem. The urgency of the difficulty it creates

  can perhaps be brought out by recalling that Sidgwick has tried throughout the

  Methods to discover what reason demands of action when applied under the most

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  fundamental conditions of human life. What he finds at the end is that because of

  one such basic and undeniable fact about human life, practical reason inevitably

  makes contradictory demands on action. If this is not a formal contradiction

  within reason itself, its bearing on Sidgwick’s real hope for philosophical ethics

  is sufficiently devastating to make it clear why he thinks his endeavour ends in

  failure.

  And Phillips would also seem to have a point insofar as he suggests

  that Sidgwick was also exercised – justifiably or not – about the simple

  indeterminacy of permissive reasons on both sides, because this still, to his

  mind, amounted to a failure to provide an ultimate unification of practical

  reason. Consider Sidgwick’s pointed and quite characteristic criticism of

  John Grote’s position:

  The non-critical part of Mr. Grote’s book I can scarcely call constructive. It is not even a sketch of a system; it is a collection of sketches. He considers that utilitarians are right in the general assertion (carefully explained to be meaningless) that all

  action is aimed at happiness. But he would distinguish the study of the general

  effects of Conduct on happiness, from the enquiry into the principles of Duty,

  or right distribution of happiness, and from the investigation of the Virtues, or

  generous dispositions, which must be left freely to follow their special altruistic

  aims, and not made to depend on a utilitarian first principle. What the last two

  methods are to be, and how the three enquiries are to be harmonized, Mr. Grote

  does not clearly explain. In his desire to comprehend the diversity of human

  impulses, he has unfortunately neglected the one impulse (as human as any)

  which it is the special function of the philosopher to direct and satisfy: the effort after a complete and reasoned synthesis of practical principles.

  Here again one feels the force of the (frustrated) ambition that was be-

  hind the Methods, and the refusal to “compress the world into a system.”

  What Irwin complained of as an ungrounded demand for clarity at key

  points in the Methods was also in large measure a demand for determinate-

  ness, for the type of clear guidance that Sidgwick lamented losing along

  with his faith.

  But in any event, the illuminating point here is that even Schneewind

  requires a reconstruction of Sidgwick’s axioms in order to make sense

  of the dualism. This, too, supports Shaver’s general account, though

  on Schneewind’s reading, Sidgwick’s pursuit of harmonization is clearly

  much more of a necessity. Shaver, in fact, admittedly takes his point of de-

  parture from Schneewind’s analysis, agreeing with him that it explains – in

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Consensus versus Chaos

  

  a way that Broad’s account does not – much of what Sidgwick says about

  how the axioms are merely “consistent with and needed to prove utili-

  tarianism, and that the issue between rational egoist and utilitarian turns

  on the rationality of taking up the universe’s point of view.” Certainly, as

  we have seen, Sidgwick was extremely insistent that the axioms were too

  abstract to provide much practical guidance about anything – everything

  needed still to be filled in.

  It would be rash, then, to deny what Shaver, Schneewind, and appar-

  ently Sidgwick himself – in his more considered statements – all expressly

  claim in this connection: namely, that the axiomatic basis of egoism is

  insufficient in itself to render egoism truly rather than apparently self-

  evident, much less of the highest certainty. And yet it is also possible to

  think that Shaver has gone too far in discounting the force of the argu-

  ment for rational egoism in Sidgwick’s work, and in painting a picture of

  what Sidgwick “was really getting at” that comports too easily with the

  impartialist attempt to defeat egoism. Schneewind’s work supports just

  such a critique.

  To be sure, Shaver’s view has great advantages. It makes admirable

  sense of Sidgwick’s tendency to describe his own views as “utilitarian,”

  without much qualification. And it suggests how, taking moral theory as

  a going project, Sidgwick could have continued to develop his account of

  the self-evident grounding of utilitarianism, getting beyond the treatment

  of it as only “apparently” self-evident, without then running into the

  problem of a similar development of the egoistic principle producing a

  conflict – an impossible conflict – of genuinely self-evident propositions

  of the highest certainty. After all, Sidgwick manifestly aspired to greater

  certainty in this department, even if he did not find it. Furthermore, it

  helps to explain how so many of those inspired by the Methods and/or

  by Sidgwick himself – from Rashdall, Moore, and Russell down to Baier,

  Kagan, Singer, and Shaver – could take this as the obvious direction for

  the progress that Sidgwick sought but failed to find.

  On the other side, however, Sidgwick clearly did lean toward a nonre-

  ductionist view of personal identity that undercut a number of potential

  challenges to rational egoism, as the following chapter will show. His ar-

  ticulation of moral theory was, for better or worse, steeped in the religious

  orientation of his youth, which had in effect involved a form of reconcili-

  ation. And he did tend, as Crisp suggests, to wield the distinction passage

  as an independent argument for at least the personal point of view, and

  P: IJD,JRQ ,FhN,GLS

  cB.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  not simply as an objection to utilitarianism. Consider his response, in the

  very paper presenting the distinction passage – the relatively late “Some

  Fundamental Ethical Controversies” – to Rashdall’s
objection that he fails

  to reconcile duty and self-interest because he assigns a “different end to

  the individual and to the race.” On Sidgwick’s rendering, Rashdall, try-

  ing to avoid the paradox of altruism apparent in Green’s account of the

  common good, held that if

  “it is pronounced right and reasonable for A to make sacrifices of his own happiness

  to the good of B,” as this must be equally right and reasonable for B, C and D, “the

  admission that altruism is rational” compels us to conceive “the happiness which

  we ought to seek for society,” not as mere happiness but as “moral happiness.” The

  ultimate end, for the race as well as for the individual, thus becomes composite:

  it consists of a higher good, Virtue, along with a lower good, Happiness, the two

  being so related that in case of conflict the higher is always to be preferred to the lower.

  Sidgwick grants “to the full” Rashdall’s starting point, the basic charge

  that he “assigns a different end to the individual and to the race.” But

  he is “unable to see why it constitutes a difficulty, since the individual

  is essentially and fundamentally different from the larger whole – the

  universe of sentient beings – of which he is conscious of being a part: just

  because he is conscious of his relation to similar parts of the same whole,

  while the whole itself has no such relation.” Thus,

  [W]hile it would be reasonable for the aggregate of sentient beings, if it could act collectively, to aim at its own happiness only as ultimate end – and would be reasonable for an individual to do the same if he were the only sentient being in

  the universe – it is yet actually reasonable for an individual to make an ultimate sacrifice of his happiness for the sake of the greater happiness of others, as well

  as reasonable for him to take his own happiness as ultimate end; owing . . . to the double view which he necessarily takes of himself as at once an individual

  essentially separate from other individuals, and at the same time essentially a part

  among similar parts of a larger whole.”

  However odd it may seem, Sidgwick does here imply that the dualism

  would also be overcome by the destruction of all sentient beings save one,

  though this is obviously not the type of harmonization he favors. But at

  any rate, Sidgwick’s use of the argument against Rashdall shows that he,

 

‹ Prev