Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Home > Other > Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe > Page 66
Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe Page 66

by Bart Schultz


  Green’s claims, he does not fall prey to some form of dualism:

  [I]f we take Green’s wider notion of Perfection, namely, complete realisation of capabilities, and understand this to include (as he expressly affirms it to include) the development of Science and Art, of the faculties of knowledge and artistic production and appreciation, we cannot say that our own perfection or approximation

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  to perfection and others’ perfection are not liable to be presented as alterna-

  tives, unless we ignore the facts of experience and the actual conditions of human

  life. And Green’s own language, in speaking of Justice, Self-denial, Self-sacrifice,

  etc., involves a similar conception of ‘Good to one’ incompatible with ‘Good to

  another’ – notwithstanding his assertion that True Good does not consist in objects

  that admit of being competed for.

  So again as regards . . . the uncertainty of hedonistic calculation – I have aimed in The Methods of Ethics at bringing out clearly the uncertainties of hedonistic calculation, and all that I will now observe is, that the uncertainties on Green’s

  view seem to me indefinitely greater, – both more complex and more fundamen-

  tal, – if a wider conception of the end as the complete realisation of capabilities

  is taken. All the alternatives presented for practical choice involve different real-

  isations of different capabilities. What criterion does Green offer for preferring

  one sort of realisation to another? I find none whatever; and if the comparison of

  quantities of pleasure is difficult and doubtful, the comparison of different real-

  isations of capabilities seems to me indefinitely more difficult and more doubtful.

  (GSM )

  Sidgwick would end up forever lamenting the mysterious logical chasms

  separating the Idealist metaphysics from the Idealist ethics and both

  from the Idealist practice. His last philosophical lecture, delivered to

  the Oxford Philosophical Society in May , was on “The Philoso-

  phy of T. H. Green,” and it drew all the chief representatives of Oxford

  Idealism. According to F. C. S. Schiller, who attended, the disciples of

  Green mostly admitted the fairness of the criticism that Green’s view

  was incoherent, though when a prominent Hegelian suggested that the

  incoherence pointed to the dialectical limits of thought in the world of

  appearance, Sidgwick confessed that “he had never been able to make

  out from the school to which he [the critic] evidently belonged how they

  managed to distinguish the contradictions which they took to be evidence

  of error from those which they regarded as intimations of higher truth”

  (M ).

  This was more than a Sidgwicked witticism. The talk distilled decades

  of critical Sidgwickian engagement with Green’s views, and it posed with

  special force the challenge to Green’s Spiritualism: “Let us first take

  Green’s positive account of Spirit, and ask, point by point whether we

  can definitely think the qualities or functions he attributes to it, with-

  out, in so thinking, predicating of it some of the relations which, ac-

  cording to Green, result from its combining and unifying activity, and

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Friends versus Friends

  

  are therefore not properly predicable of it.” Point by point, Sidgwick

  answers no:

  And this view, I think, will be confirmed by a rigorous examination of Green’s

  main argument for establishing the existence of a spiritual principle in nature. It

  is the source of the relations that constitute experience a connected whole: but

  where lies the logical necessity of assuming such a source? Green answers that

  the existence of the relations involves ‘the unity of the manifold, the existence

  of the many in one. . . . But,’ he adds, ‘a plurality of things cannot of themselves unite in one relation, nor can a single thing of itself bring itself into a multitude of relations . . . there must’ – therefore – ‘be something other than the manifold things themselves which combines them.’ The argument seems to me unthinkable,

  because, as Green has emphatically declared, I cannot even conceive the manifold

  things out of the relations: and therefore I cannot even raise the question whether,

  if I could so conceive them, I should see them to require something other than

  themselves to bring them into the relations. (LPK , )

  This was an important point, one that Sidgwick had often stressed in his

  class lectures. As he alternatively put it, for Green, nature is “conceived as

  essentially a single unalterable all-inclusive system of relations, by which

  all phenomena are combined into a systematic whole: and the source of

  connexion, the combiner and unifier, must be a non-natural or Spiritual

  Principle.” But then,

  How, as no element of nature is conceivable out of relation, can we conceive it as

  requiring a non-natural principle to bring it into relation? It seems that in order to exhibit the evidence for a non-natural principle Green has first to conceive Nature

  as analysed into elements; yet this in the same breath he declares to be irrational

  and inconceivable! (LPK )

  Should Green appeal to self-consciousness as yielding a “positive con-

  ception of the action of the Divine Mind in the universe,” Sidgwick coun-

  ters that, as for himself, “I seem to find, not to originate, truth”; but even granting the consciousness of “action absolutely from itself ” – human

  freedom – how “can we infer from this the action of the Universal Mind,

  consistently with Green’s theory of the human spirit?” After all, “if my

  self-consciousness is to be the causa cognoscendi of the causality of the unifying principle in the world, that self-consciousness must surely include

  an indubitable cognition of the essential unity of the self: but in trying

  to think Green’s conception of the human spirit, I find that notion of its

  essential unity vanishes.” Green, that is, has not reconciled the mental and

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  the physical, despite his appeal to the analogy of a two-sided shield: “For

  I see clearly that a shield not only may but must have two opposite sides, united into a continuous surface by the rim: whereas I cannot see how

  one indivisible self can possibly have as its two sides an animal organism

  and a self-limiting eternal consciousness” (LPK –). In the fuller

  formulation of the point in Sidgwick’s lectures:

  One of the things I am most certain of is the unity of myself. Green says that

  () I am really two things, so disparate as an eternal consciou
sness out of time, and a function of an animal organism changing in time; and yet at the same time that

  () I am one indivisible reality contemplated from two different points of view.

  I submit that Green is bound to reconcile this contradiction, which he does not

  do by simply stating that both contradictory propositions are true. As it is, his

  doctrine is rather like the theological doctrine of the Athanasian Creed, only the

  Athanasian Creed does not profess to give an intelligible account of the mysteries

  it formulates. (LPK )

  For his part, Green would probably have thought this a prime example

  of the cheap mirth one ought to expect from utilitarians. But for Sidgwick,

  from the self-contradictions of empirical experience Green has only pro-

  duced a self-contradictory metaphysics, unable to present its own basic

  tenets in a consistent and coherent fashion. What can’t be said can’t be

  said, and it can’t be whistled either, as later Wittgensteinians were fond of

  singing.

  It is not stretching it to find in these and many other passages of Sidg-

  wick’s critique the springboard for the (not much) later arguments of

  Moore and Russell, particularly during their early, realist period of re-

  bellion against Idealism. Sidgwick had urged in his lectures that “when

  Green draws the inference that this knowing consciousness is not a ‘phe-

  nomenon,’ not an ‘event in the individual’s history,’ he seems to be con-

  founding the knowing consciousness with the object known” (LPK ).

  And of course, Russell attacked head on the central Idealist doctrine

  that, as he put it, “Every apparently separate piece of reality has, as it

  were, hooks which grapple it to the next piece; the next piece, in turn has

  fresh hooks, and so on until the whole universe is reconstructed.” Russell,

  like Sidgwick, found this question-begging, a view that presupposed that

  existing incomplete things demanded the existence of other things, and

  that the nature of a thing was constituted by all the truths about it. Russell

  argued that the relations that a thing has do not necessarily constitute

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Friends versus Friends

  

  its nature, and that one can know things by direct acquaintance while

  remaining quite ignorant of many other relations:

  I may be acquainted, for example, with my toothache, and this knowledge may be

  as complete as knowledge by acquaintance ever can be, without knowing all that

  the dentist (who is not acquainted with it) can tell me about its cause, and without

  therefore knowing its ‘nature’ in the above sense. Thus the fact that a thing has

  relations does not prove that its relations are logically necessary.

  Sidgwick had struggled hard with analogous claims in Green, con-

  cerning internal relations. He confessed himself unable to make out how

  Green could claim that “the single things are nothing except as deter-

  mined by relations which are the negations of their singleness, but they

  do not therefore cease to be single things. . . . On the contrary, if they did not survive in their singleness, there could be no relation between them –

  nothing but a blank, featureless identity.” Among other things, Sidgwick

  wondered why the “fact that they survive in their singleness” – whatever

  that singleness is – should show “that they need something other than

  themselves to make them so survive” (LPK ). Furthermore, as John

  Gibbins has plausibly suggested, Russell’s appeal to knowledge by ac-

  quaintance versus knowledge by description can be traced back through

  Sidgwick to John Grote. In any event, Sidgwick plainly recognized the

  crucial point of the distinction, and the problematic that would animate

  much of Russell’s epistemological work, at least during its phenomenalistic

  and reductionistic phases:

  Let us suppose that both Materialists and Mentalists agree to affirm () that we

  immediately know the external world, so far as it is necessary to know it for the

  purpose of constructing physical science; () that we immediately know nothing

  but our own consciousness; and () that these two statements are perfectly con-

  sistent. It still remains to ask who are the ‘we’ who have this knowledge. Each

  one of us can only have experience of a very small portion of this world; and if

  we abstract what is known through memory, and therefore mediately, the portion

  becomes small indeed. In order to get to what ‘we’ conceive ‘ourselves’ to know

  as ‘matter of fact’ respecting the world, as extended in space and time – to such

  merely historical knowledge as we commonly regard not as ‘resting’ on experience,

  but as constituting the experience on which science rests – we must assume the

  general trustworthiness of memory, and the general trustworthiness of testimony

  under proper limitations and conditions. I do not for a moment say that we have

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  no right to make these assumptions; I only do not see how we can prove that we

  have such a right, from what we immediately know. (LPK –)

  However, it must be allowed that on various points, Sidgwick, while clearly

  pointing to the possibility of a program resembling Russell’s logical atom-

  ism, would have resisted any overly ambitious formulation of it out of a

  fairly robust sense of the theory-ladenness of obervation, a sense of just

  how conceptualized perception, in any useful sense, always already is:

  The truth seems to be that the indubitable certainty of the judgment ‘I am con-

  scious’ has been rather hastily extended by Empiricists to judgments affirming that

  my present consciousness is such and such. But these latter judgments necessarily

  involve an implicit comparison and classification of the present consciousness with elements of past conscious experience recalled in memory; and the implied classification may obviously be erroneous either through inaccuracy of memory or a

  mistake in the comparative judgment. And the risk of error cannot well be avoided

  by eliminating along with inference this implicit classification: for the psychical

  fact observed cannot be distinctly thought at all without it: if we rigorously purge

  it away, there will be nothing left save the cognition of self and of we cannot say

  what psychical fact. Nay, it is doubtful whether even this much will be left for

  the Empiricist’s observation: since he may share Hume’s inability to find a self

  in the stream of psychical experience, or to maintain a clear distinction between

  psychical and material fact. Thus the Empiricist criterion, if extended to purge

  away comparison as well as inference, may leave us nothing free from error but

  the bare affirmation of Fact not further definable. (LPK –)
>
  Sidgwick takes pains to explain that he does not want to deny “the value

  of the Empirical criterion” and that he has no doubt of “the importance of

  distinguishing the inferential element in our apparently immediate judg-

  ments as far as we can, with a view to the elimination of error.” The point is

  simply that “the assertion that we can by this procedure obtain a residuum

  of certainly true cognition seems to me neither self-evident nor confirmed

  by experience.” Often enough, in Sidgwick’s eyes, the “given” turned out

  to be a myth.

  Thus, although Sidgwick was well aware of the type of neo-Humean

  direction that empiricism might take – and later would take, in the work

  of the mature Russell – his own conception of experience held on to some

  of the more holistic and nonreductive elements of Idealism, in at least

  proto-pragmatist fashion. The empiricists and the rationalists offered up

  “useful” criteria for “guarding against error,” but neither their schools

  P: GYQ

  ca.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Friends versus Friends

  

  nor any other had found the key to infallibility. This comports well with

  the account of his epistemology set out in Chapter  in connection with

  the Methods.

  Beyond all this, Sidgwick always found the whole Idealist business just

  terribly overimpressed by thought, at the expense of feeling. In his final

  talk, as in so many other places, he explained of Green:

  He is equally willing to admit that there is ‘no such thing as mere thought’; and

  in fact only to contend that feeling and thought are inseparable and mutually

  dependent. And he expressly affirms this mutual dependence of thought and

  feeling, not only in the case of our empirical consciousness, but in the case also of

  ‘the world-consciousness of which ours is a limited mode.’ But if this be so, I do not see how Green is justified – or thinks himself justified – in making the thought

  element so prominent, and the feeling element so subordinate in his account

  of Nature; or in speaking of Nature as a system of relations, instead of related

  feelings; or in resolving – as we saw – the particularity of a feeling entirely into

 

‹ Prev