Book Read Free

Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Page 106

by Bart Schultz


  :

  Colors

  

  the English method, since the provision compulsorily made extends to labourers

  generally, whereas the English system only provides for the destitute: on the other

  hand, the method of compulsory insurance is, from another point of view, less

  anti-individualistic, so far as the burden of the provision is thrown on the persons

  who receive the benefit of it. (EP –)

  Sidgwick goes on to suggest that a “careful combination” of all three

  systems – regulated private almsgiving, public relief, and compulsory

  insurance – would probably yield the “practically best plan” for deal-

  ing with poverty, but at the same time he admits that just how to combine

  them, and in what degree, are problems to which there is no general the-

  oretical solution. Consequently, he is only willing to conclude that “the

  proper nature and limits of governmental action for the relief of indigence

  must largely depend upon () the actual extent of effectiveness of volun-

  tary association among the citizens, and () on the amount of philanthropic

  effort and sacrifice habitually devoted by private persons to the supply of

  social needs, and the wisdom with which these efforts and sacrifices are

  directed.” These lessons are similar to those drawn in other departments –

  thus, “we actually find that the promotion of education and culture, and

  the cure of diseases, have been largely provided for in modern civilised

  communities . . . by the donations and bequests of individuals. So far as

  these needs can be adequately met in this way, there is an advantage in

  avoiding the necessity for additional taxation.” (EP ) Should the state

  start intervening in an area where private beneficence had been effective,

  “there is a serious danger of the latter withdrawing from it, unless the

  spheres of action appropriate to the two agencies respectively are well and

  clearly defined.”

  These general remarks do not actually convey Sidgwick’s more detailed

  convictions, the result of his work with the Cambridge Charity Organiza-

  tion Society. For example, in an unpublished lecture on the “Poor Law,”

  delivered to the London COS, he explained that he did not think that the

  English system, workhouses and all, was fundamentally misguided, de-

  spite the attacks on it as “hard-hearted” by sentimental socialists, trades

  union congresses, and so on. Moreover, he opposed transferring to the

  government the tasks of discriminating desert and dealing with specially

  deserving cases – which was the “the semi-official work of experts” such as

  the COS. At most, he favored an intermediate course of reform: “keeping

  the work-house system as at present, we might supplement it – so far as

  P: IJD

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  out-door relief is concerned – by something like the French system – some

  cooperation with local governments which should yet keep the financial

  and administrative basis of the work mainly voluntary.” Presumably, this

  is where he hoped for the involvement of minds of “nobler stamp,” as he

  had put it in the Principles. His fear was that

  an astute socialistic leader, taking advantage of popular sentiment, might easily

  construct a series of apparently moderate steps by which our existing system

  of poor-relief might be transformed into a system securing a fairly comfortable

  provision for old-age and industrial emergencies, for the manual labour classes;

  so that it might serve as a valuable military basis enabling them to conduct their

  industrial wars with more staying-power than at present. (CWC)

  Now, such sentiments and affiliations were hardly likely to win Sidgwick

  a reputation for radicalism. Again, the Charity Organisation Societies were

  generally regarded as bastions of the laissez-faire thinking that went into

  the Poor Law reforms of , the first result of the reformed Parliament,

  which did away with the Speenhamland system that had sheltered rural

  England against the first ravages of capitalism. As Polanyi put it in his

  classic work, The Great Transformation,

  To the bewilderment of thinking minds, unheard-of wealth turned out to be

  inseparable from unheard-of poverty. Scholars proclaimed in unison that a science

  had been discovered which put the laws governing man’s world beyond any doubt.

  It was at the behest of these laws that compassion was removed from the hearts,

  and a stoic determination to renounce human solidarity in the name of the greatest

  happiness of the greatest number gained the dignity of secular religion.

  Altruistic rightness of heart was being subordinated to utilitarian hardness

  of heart, a focus on consequences as calculated by experts.

  What is missing from such an imputation of want of human feeling

  and solidarity is, at least in the case of Sidgwick, any recognition of how

  he simply sought to combine altruistic feeling with effective giving, and

  how he held out the hope that human nature would change and that a far

  more socialistic system would prove possible. Moreover, he did think the

  English system too purely deterrent. After all, he himself had effectively

  undermined most of the orthodox attempts to legitimate the economic

  system, and his brief was against industrial war, not creeping socialism.

  It was this curious combination of countenancing too many of the com-

  placencies of orthodox political economy with respect to the present, while

  P: IJD

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Colors

  

  recognizing the empirical, debatable nature of the issues and keeping an

  open and hopeful mind about the future obsolescence of libertarian theory

  and practice, that made Sidgwick such an elusive, easily misunderstood

  figure. A revealing case in point involved the famous socialist playwright

  George Bernard Shaw, who used to enjoy recounting how Sidgwick had

  stormed out of one of his socialist speeches, while loudly objecting that

  he would have no truck with anyone advocating the theft of property.

  Sidgwick’s journal, however, leaves a different impression:

  The Committee had invited a live Socialist, redhot ‘from the Streets,’ as he told

  us, who sketched in a really brilliant address the rapid series of steps by which

  modern society is to pass peacefully into social democracy. The node of the transition was supplied by urban ground-rents (it is interesting to observe that the

  old picture of the agricultural landlord-drone, battening on social prosperity to

  which he contributes nothing, is withdrawn for the present as too ludicrously

  out of accordance with the facts). It is now urban ground-rent that the municipal governments will have to seize, to meet the ever-growing necessity of providing
<
br />   work and wages for the unemployed. How exactly this seizure of urban rents was

  to develop into a complete nationalisation of industry I could not remember af-

  terwards, but it seemed to go very naturally at the time. There was a peroration

  rhetorically effective as well as daring, in which he explained that the bliss of

  perfected socialism would only come by slow degrees, with lingering steps and

  long delays, and claimed our sympathy for the noble-hearted men whose ardent

  philanthropy had led them to desire to cut these delays short by immediate rev-

  olution and spoliation. It was, indeed, a mistake on their part; the laws of social

  development did not admit of it; but if we were not quite lost in complacent self-

  ishness we should join him in regretting that this shorter way with property was

  impossible.

  Altogether a noteworthy performance: – the man’s name is Bernard Shaw:

  Myers says he has written books worth reading. (M )

  This encounter at the British Association was in September of ,

  well after the publication of Sidgwick’s Principles and his own quasi-

  Millian sketch of the possible transition to socialism through the increasing

  success of public industries. According to legend, when Shaw was finally

  confronted with this passage from the Memoir, he was rendered quite

  speechless.

  One of the primary reasons why Sidgwick’s views on gradual socialism

  and the growth of government interference were so cautious in the case

  of such matters as poor relief has to do with his more general fears about

  P: IJD

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  the corruption of the political process. Thus, he concludes his chapter

  on “Socialistic Interference,” with its discussion of poor relief, with an

  expression of concern about the disadvantages of governmental action.

  These disadavantages involve:

  () the danger of overburdening the governmental machinery with work, () the

  danger of increasing the power capable of being used by governing persons op-

  pressively or corruptly, () the danger that the delicate economic functions of

  government will be hampered by the desire to gratify certain specially influential

  sections of the community: – for instance, when legislation is in the hands of a

  representative assembly, the more the functions of Government are extended in

  a socialistic direction, the greater becomes the risk that contested elections will

  exhibit an immoral competition between candidates promising to procure public

  money for the benefit of particular classes and districts. (EP )

  Along with these dangers, he warns that the work of government is apt

  to be done by persons lacking some of the drive of persons in the private

  sector, and that it is therefore a mistake to conclude “that governmental in-

  terference is always expedient, even where laisser faire leads to a manifestly unsatisfactory result; its expediency has to be decided in any particular

  case by a careful estimate of advantages and drawbacks, requiring data

  obtained from special experience.”

  Clearly, Sidgwick feared that government, too, was under the going

  conditions insufficiently high-minded, and that the evolution of public

  spirit had some ways to go. Indeed, with the increasing democratization

  coming with the reforms of  and , he was inclined to think that

  short-sighted party strife was becoming even more of a danger. When,

  in Part II of the book, he finally comes around to an extended discus-

  sion of democracy, he makes it abundantly plain that his conception of

  democracy – quite like Mill’s – would not harbor any excessively generous

  view of the capabilities of the plain man. Thus,

  There seem to be two competing principles, one or other of which is more or

  less definitely assumed in current arguments for democratic institutions. One of

  these, – which I myself accept, with important qualifications, – is ‘that government

  should rest on the active consent of the governed’; the other is ‘that any one honest and self-supporting citizen is, on the average, as well qualified as another for the

  work of government.’ This latter proposition I in the main reject; but I admit

  that, in one view of the proof of the first proposition, the second is to some extent implied, and that where democracy – as defined by the first proposition – is fully

  P: IJD

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  Colors

  

  developed, there is likely to be a tendency to accept and act upon the second to

  some extent. (EP )

  The qualifications have to do especially with the legislative side of gov-

  ernment (Sidgwick accepts the familiar threefold division of executive,

  judicial, and legislative), and on many counts they follow Mill’s Consid-

  erations on Representative Government. Yet he is, if anything, even pickier

  about expertise than Mill, and often sounds very like a precursor to Walter

  Lippmann, with his scathing assault on the myth of the “omnicompetent

  citizen” in Public Opinion. Thus, the

  ideal legislator ought to know law as well as the lawyer, but he ought to know much

  more than law. He must have an insight . . . into the actual relation of the laws to the social life of the community regulated; the manner in which they modify the

  conduct of the individuals whom they affect; the consequences, proximate and

  remote, that are likely to result from any change in them.

  But getting a body of legislators who, in addition to general knowledge,

  “combine special experience in different departments of social life” is

  only one part of the problem. Harder still is to secure “in legislators a

  keen concern for the interests of the various elements of the community for

  which they legislate.” This requires the familiar solution of a “system of

  popular election for a limited time,” which even when it yields bad laws, at

  least makes the legislation more acceptable to the governed. (EP –)

  Needless to say, Sidgwick has little patience for the claims of direct

  democracy, or for a natural right to self-governance. The latter he treats

  as akin to the individualistic principle, as something that may be justified

  on utilitarian grounds, but only with important exceptions and qualifi-

  cations. On the former, he insists that legislation is “a difficult art, the

  mastery of which requires such an expenditure of time and energy as the

  citizens at large – even if otherwise qualified – cannot ordinarily afford.”

  Although he allows that under certain conditions, it could be justifiable

  to rely more rather than less heavily on such direct democratic means as

  the referendum, this does not translate into any sympathy for the idea of

  doing away with representation. Against the claim that the incompetence
r />   of the electorate for directly producing legislation will simply translate

  into an incompetent choice of legislators, he thinks it sufficient

  to reply that, in the division of labour which civilisation has brought, ordinary

  members of a community organised on an individualistic basis have continually

  P: IJD

  cA.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  February , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  to choose experts for skilled work of which the chooser does not understand the

  methods: and the result is commonly accepted as tolerably satisfactory. Thus . . .

  most men value highly the control that they acquire, by the free choice of their

  physician, over the operation of applying drugs to the cure of their diseases;

  though they know themselves to be wholly unable to prescribe medicines for

  themselves.

  If this cannot be exactly imitated in the case of government’s coercive

  power, nonetheless “we imitate it as far as we can by giving the individuals

  coerced a share in the appointment of the supreme organ of legislation.”

  (EP –)

  Yet it must be said that Sidgwick was awfully sensitive to the inade-

  quacies of the people. All of Mill’s fears – or Tocqueville’s – about the

  potential tyranny of the majority loom large for him, in the context of

  the s, though in somewhat altered form. He is not one to suffer any

  confusion about the multiple meanings of “freedom”:

  When a writer speaks of ‘Free’ institutions he sometimes means to imply that the

  government leaves the individual alone to look after his own affairs; sometimes that

  the private members of the community collectively exercise an effective control

  over the government: sometimes he seems to imply both together, apparently as-

  suming a necessary connection between the two facts, which we may conveniently

  distinguish as ‘civil’ and ‘constitution’ freedom respectively.

  But there is no such necessary connection; alluding to a favorite example

  of Mill’s, he notes “that Government does nothing to prevent a man from

  getting as drunk as he likes in Russia: whereas the vigorous democracy

  of North America has established in several States severely restrictive

 

‹ Prev