The Omnibus Homo Sacer

Home > Other > The Omnibus Homo Sacer > Page 35
The Omnibus Homo Sacer Page 35

by Giorgio Agamben


  224

  HOMO SACER II, 1

  Thus, not only is the correspondence between anomie and anxiety taken for granted

  (while, as we will see, ethnological and folkloristic research show the contrary), but the possibility that anomie has a more intimate and complex relation to law and the social

  order is also ruled out in advance.

  5.2. Equally inadequate are the conclusions of the study published by Seston

  a few years later. The author seems to be aware of the possible political signifi-

  cance of the iustitium as public mourning, insofar as he stages and dramatizes

  the funeral of the sovereign as a state of exception: “In imperial funerals there

  survives the memory of a mobilization. . . . Framing the funerary rites within

  a sort of general mobilization, with all civil affairs stopped and normal politi-

  cal life suspended, the proclamation of the iustitium tended to transform the

  death of a man into a national catastrophe, a drama in which each person was

  involved, willingly or not” (Seston 1962, 171–72). This intuition, however, comes

  to nothing, and the nexus between the two forms of iustitium is accounted for

  by once again presupposing that which was to be explained, that is, an element

  of mourning implicit in the iustitium from the start (172–73). It is Augusto Fra-

  schetti’s achievement to have underscored, in his monograph on Augustus, the

  political significance of public mourning, showing that the link between the two

  aspects of the iustitium lies not in a presumed character of mourning in extreme

  situations or anomie but in the tumult that the sovereign’s funeral can cause.

  Fraschetti recovers its origins in the violent riots that had accompanied the fu-

  nerals of Caesar, which were significantly described as “seditious funerals” (Fra-

  schetti 1990, 57). Just as the iustitium was the natural response to tumult in the Republican era, “it is clear how the iustitium comes to be identified with public mourning through a similar strategy, by which the deaths in the domus Augusta

  are likened to civic catastrophes. . . . The upshot of this is that the bona and the mala of a single family come to be the concern of the res publica” (57). Fraschetti readily shows how, in conformity with this strategy, Augustus, beginning with

  the death of his nephew Marcellus, would proclaim a iustitium every time the

  family mausoleum was opened.

  It is certainly possible to see the iustitium (in the sense of public morning) as

  nothing other than the sovereign’s attempt to appropriate the state of exception

  by transforming it into a family affair. But the connection is even more intimate

  and complex.

  Take, for example, Suetonius’s famous description of Augustus’s death at

  Nola on August 19 of the year 14 ce. The old sovereign, surrounded by friends

  and courtiers, has a mirror brought to him and, after having his hair combed

  and his sagging cheeks made up, seems solely concerned to know whether he has

  STATE OF EXCEPTION

  225

  acted the mimus vitae, the “farce of his life,” well. And yet, alongside this insistent theatrical metaphor, he stubbornly and almost insolently continues to ask

  ( identidem exquirens)—with what is not simply a political metaphor— an iam de

  se tumultus foris fuisset, “if there was now a tumult outside that concerned him.”

  The correspondence between anomie and mourning becomes comprehensible

  only in the light of the correspondence between the death of the sovereign and

  the state of exception. The original nexus between tumultus and iustitium is still present, but the tumult now coincides with the death of the sovereign, while the

  suspension of the law is integrated into the funeral ceremony. It is as if the sov-

  ereign, who had absorbed into his “august” person all exceptional powers (from

  the tribunicia potestas perpetua [perpetual tribunicial power] to the imperium pro-consolare maius et infinitum [greater and endless proconsular imperium]) and who had, so to speak, become a living iustitium, showed his intimate anomic character at the moment of his death and saw tumult and anomie set free outside of him

  in the city. As Nissen had intuited in a limpid formula (which is perhaps the

  source of Benjamin’s thesis according to which the state of exception has become

  the rule), “exceptional measures disappeared because they had become the rule”

  (Nissen 1877, 140). The constitutional novelty of the principate can thus be seen

  as an incorporation of the state of exception and anomie directly into the person

  of the sovereign, who begins to free himself from all subordination to the law and

  asserts himself as legibus solutus [unbound by the laws].

  5.3. The intimately anomic nature of this new figure of supreme power ap-

  pears clearly in the theory of the sovereign as “living law” ( nomos empsukhos),

  which is elaborated among the neo-Pythagoreans in the same years that see

  the rise of the principate. The formula basileus nomos empsukhos is found in

  Diotogenes’s treatise on sovereignty, which was partially preserved by Stobaeus

  and whose relevance to the origin of the modern theory of sovereignty must not

  be underestimated. The usual philological myopia has prevented the modern

  editor of the treatise from seeing the obvious logical connection between this

  formula and the anomic character of the sovereign, even though this connection

  is unequivocally stated in the text. The passage in question—corrupt in part,

  yet nevertheless perfectly consistent—is divided into three points: (1) “The king

  is the most just [ dikaiotatos] and the most just is the most legal [ nomimōtatos].”

  (2) “Without justice no one can be king, but justice is without law [ aneu nomou

  dikaiosunē; Delatte’s proposed insertion of the negative before dikaiosunē is totally unjustified philologically].” (3) “The just is legitimate, and the king, having become the cause of the just, is a living law” (L. Delatte 1942, 37).

  226

  HOMO SACER II, 1

  That the sovereign is a living law can only mean that he is not bound by it,

  that in him the life of the law coincides with a total anomie. Diotogenes explains

  this a little later with unequivocal clarity: “Because the king has an irresponsible

  power [ arkhan anupeuthunon] and is himself a living law, he is like a god among

  men” (L. Delatte 1942, 39). And yet, precisely because he is identified with the

  law, he is held in relation to it and is indeed posited as the anomic foundation

  of the juridical order. The identification between sovereign and law represents,

  that is, the first attempt to assert the anomie of the sovereign and, at the same

  time, his essential link to the juridical order. The nomos empsukhos is the original form of the nexus that the state of exception establishes between an outside and

  an inside of the law, and in this sense it constitutes the archetype of the modern

  theory of sovereignty.

  The correspondence between iustitium and mourning shows its true mean-

  ing here. If the sovereign is a living nomos, and if, for this reason, anomie and nomos perfectly coincide in his person, then anarchy (which threatens to loose

  itself in the city upon the sovereign’s death, which is to say, when the nexus that

  joins it to the law is severed) must be ritualized and controlled, transforming

  the state of exception into public mourning and mourning into iustitium. Cor-

 
responding to the undecidability of nomos and anomie in the living body of the

  sovereign is the undecidability between state of exception and public mourning

  in the city. Before assuming its modern form as a decision on the emergency,

  the relation between sovereignty and state of exception appears in the form of

  an identity between the sovereign and anomie. Because he is a living law, the

  sovereign is intimately anomos. Here too the state of exception is the—secret and truer—life of the law.

  א The thesis that “the sovereign is a living law” found its first formulation in the treatise by Pseudo-Archytas On Law and Justice, which was preserved for us by Stobaeus along with Diotogenes’s treatise on sovereignty. Whether or not Gruppe’s hypothesis that these

  treatises were composed by an Alexandrine Jew in the first century of our era is correct, it is certain that we are dealing with a group of texts that, under the cover of Platonic and Pythagorean categories, seek to lay the foundations for a conception of sovereignty that

  is entirely unbound by laws and yet is itself the source of legitimacy. In Pseudo-Archytas’s text this is expressed in the distinction between the sovereign ( basileus), who is the law, and the magistrate ( arkhōn), who must only observe the law. The identification between the law and the sovereign leads to the division of the law into a hierarchically superior

  “living” law ( nomos empsukhos) and a written law ( gramma) that is subordinate to it: I say that every community is composed of an arkhōn (the magistrate who commands), one who is commanded, and, thirdly, the laws. Of these last, the living

  STATE OF EXCEPTION

  227

  one is the sovereign ( ho men empsukhos ho basileus) and the inanimate one is the

  letter ( gramma). The law being the first element, the king is legal, the magistrate is in conformity (with the law), the one who is commanded is free and the entire

  city is happy; but if there is any deviation, then the sovereign is a tyrant, the

  magistrate is not in conformity with the law and the community is unhappy.

  (A. Delatte 1922, 84)

  By means of a complex strategy, which is not without analogies to Paul’s critique

  of the Jewish nomos (this proximity is also at times textual: Romans 3:21: khōris nomou dikaiosunē; Diotogenes: aneu nomou dikaiosunē; and in Pseudo-Archytas the law is defined as a “letter,” gramma, exactly as in Paul), anomic elements are introduced into the polis through the person of the sovereign, with evidently no effect on the primacy of the nomos (the sovereign is, indeed, “living law”).

  5.4. The secret solidarity between anomie and law comes to light in another

  phenomenon, which represents a symmetrical and in some ways inverse figure

  to the imperial iustitium. Folklorists and anthropologists have long been familiar with those periodic feasts (such as the Anthesteria and Saturnalia of the classical

  world and the charivari and Carnival of the medieval and modern world) that

  are characterized by unbridled license and the suspension and overturning of

  normal legal and social hierarchies. During these feasts (which are found with

  similar characteristics in various epochs and cultures), men dress up and behave

  like animals, masters serve their slaves, males and females exchange roles, and

  criminal behavior is considered licit or, in any case, not punishable. That is, they

  inaugurate a period of anomie that breaks and temporarily subverts the social

  order. Scholars have always had difficulty explaining these sudden anomic explo-

  sions within well-ordered societies and, above all, why they would be tolerated

  by both the religious and civil authorities.

  Contrary to those interpretations that traced the anomic feasts back to agrar-

  ian cycles tied to the solar calendar (Mannhardt, Frazer) or to a periodic function

  of purification (Westermarck), Karl Meuli, with a brilliant intuition, instead re-

  lated them to the state of suspended law that characterized some archaic juridical

  institutions, such as the Germanic Friedlosigkeit or the persecution of the wargus in ancient English law. In a series of exemplary studies, he showed how the

  disturbances and violent acts meticulously listed in medieval descriptions of the

  charivari and other anomic phenomena precisely replicate the different phases

  of the cruel ritual in which the Friedlos and the bandit were expelled from the

  community, their houses unroofed and destroyed, and their wells poisoned or

  made brackish. The harlequinades described in the unprecedented chalivali of

  the Roman de Fauvel ( Li un montret son cul au vent, / Li autre rompet un auvent, /

  228

  HOMO SACER II, 1

  L’un cassoit fenestres et huis, / L’autre getoit le sel ou puis, / L’un getoit le bren aus visages; / Trop estoient lès et sauvages [One showed his ass to the wind, / Another smashed a roof, / One broke windows and doors, / Another threw salt in the

  wells, / And another threw filth in faces; / They were truly horrible and savage])

  cease to appear as parts of an innocent pandemonium, and one after the other

  find their counterpart and their proper context in the Lex Baiuvariorum or in

  the penal statutes of the medieval cities. The same can be said for the acts of

  harassment committed during masked feasts and children’s begging rituals in

  which children punished whoever denied their obligation to give a gift with acts

  of violence that Halloween only distantly recalls.

  Charivari is one of the many names (which vary from country to country and

  region to region) for an ancient and widely diffused act of popular justice, which

  occurred everywhere in similar, if not identical forms. Such forms are also used

  as ritual punishments in the cyclical masked feasts and their extreme offshoots,

  the traditional children’s begging rituals; one may therefore immediately draw

  upon these for an interpretation of charivari-like phenomena. A closer analysis

  shows that what at first sight seemed simply to be rough and wild acts of harass-

  ment are in truth well-defined traditional customs and legal forms, by means

  of which, from time immemorial, the ban and proscription were carried out.

  (Meuli 1975, 473)

  If Meuli’s hypothesis is correct, the “legal anarchy” of the anomic feasts does

  not refer back to ancient agrarian rites, which in themselves explain nothing;

  rather, it brings to light in a parodic form the anomie within the law, the state of

  emergency as the anomic drive contained in the very heart of the nomos.

  That is to say, the anomic feasts point toward a zone in which life’s maximum

  subjection to the law is reversed into freedom and license, and the most unbri-

  dled anomie shows its parodic connection with the nomos. In other words, they

  point toward the real state of exception as the threshold of indifference between

  anomie and law. In showing the mournful character of every feast and the festive

  character of all mourning, law and anomie show their distance and, at the same

  time, their secret solidarity. It is as if the universe of law—and more generally,

  the sphere of human action insofar as it has to do with law—ultimately appeared

  as a field of forces traversed by two conjoined and opposite tensions: one that

  goes from norm to anomie, and another that leads from anomie to the law and

  the rule. Hence a double paradigm, which marks the field of law with an essen-

  tial ambiguity: on the one hand, a normative tendency in the strict sense, which

  aims at crystallizing
itself in a rigid system of norms whose connection to life is,

  however, problematic if not impossible (the perfect state of law, in which every-

  STATE OF EXCEPTION

  229

  thing is regulated by norms); and, on the other hand, an anomic tendency that

  leads to the state of exception or the idea of the sovereign as living law, in which

  a force-of-law that is without norm acts as the pure inclusion of life.

  The anomic feasts dramatize this irreducible ambiguity of juridical systems

  and, at the same time, show that what is at stake in the dialectic between these

  two forces is the very relation between law and life. They celebrate and parod-

  ically replicate the anomie through which the law applies itself to chaos and to

  life only on the condition of making itself, in the state of exception, life and

  living chaos. And perhaps the moment has come to try to better understand the

  constitutive fiction that—in binding together norm and anomie, law and state

  of exception—also ensures the relation between law and life.

  6

  Auctoritas and Potestas

  6.1. In our analysis of the state of exception in Rome, we neglected to ask

  what was the foundation of the Senate’s power to suspend the law

  by means of the senatus consultum ultimum and the consequent proclamation of

  a iustitium. Whoever may have been the subject qualified to declare a iustitium,

  it is certain that it was always declared ex auctoritate patrum. Indeed, it is well known that in Rome the term designating the Senate’s most proper prerogative

  was neither imperium nor potestas, but auctoritas: auctoritas patrum is the syntagma that defines the specific function of the Senate in the Roman constitution.

  In both the history of law and, more generally, philosophy and political

  theory, all attempts to define this category of auctoritas—particularly in contrast to potestas—seem to run into almost insurmountable obstacles and aporias. “It

  is particularly difficult,” wrote a French legal historian at the beginning of the

  1950s, “to bring the various juridical aspects of the notion of auctoritas back to a unitary concept” (Magdelain 1990, 685); and, at the end of that decade, Hannah

  Arendt could open her essay “What Is Authority?” with the observation that

 

‹ Prev