Book Read Free

The Omnibus Homo Sacer

Page 96

by Giorgio Agamben


  the order of the world,” which “could not violate this order without ceasing to

  be God” (Fénelon, p. 342).

  1.3. What is in every way decisive is the function that Malebranche gives to

  Christology in providential government. He interprets the Trinitarian oikonomia

  in the sense that Jesus Christ, after his sacrifice, where he acted as the meritorious cause of redemption, was constituted by the Father as the occasional cause of

  grace and, as such, he executes and renders effective in its particulars the grace

  that God established through his general laws. “Thus he himself applies and

  distributes his gifts, as occasional cause. He disposes of everything in the house of God, like a well-loved son in the house of his father” (Malebranche 1992,

  p. 201). In other words, he is an integral part of the governmental machine of

  providence, and occupies the place of the determining node that articulates its

  execution in every area and for all individuals. It is in this sense that, according

  to Malebranche, one must understand both the affirmation in the Gospel that

  states that to Christ has been given “omnis potestas in coelo et in terra” (Matthew

  28:18), and that of Paul according to which Christ is the head of the Church of

  which the faithful are members (Ephesians 4:6). The words of Paul

  [ . . . ] do not simply say that Jesus Christ is the meritorious cause of all graces: they express even more distinctly the notion that Christians are members of the

  body of which Jesus Christ is the head; that it is in him that we believe and that

  614

  HOMO SACER II, 4

  we live a wholly new life; that it is through his internal working kat’ energeian, that his Church is formed, and that he has thus been established by God as the

  sole occasional cause who, by his different desires and different efforts, distributes the graces which God as true cause diffuses in men. (Malebranche 1992, p. 203)

  Christ acts, in other words, as the chief of the executive of a gubernatio of which God is the supreme legislator. But, just as the oikonomia did not imply the division of the divinity, in the same way the power [ potenza] assigned to Christ

  does not involve a division of sovereignty. For this reason Malebranche is able

  to speak, with respect to Christ, of a “sovereign power” (“puissance souveraine

  de cause occasionnelle”: Malebranche 1979, p. 148, even if this was given to him

  by the father) and, at the same time, to define its function simply as “ministry”:

  Jesus Christ, as a man, is the head of the Church, and it is he who distributes

  among its members the grace that sanctifies. But since he only has this power as

  a consequence of the general laws that God has established in him in order to

  execute his great design, the eternal temple, one can truly say that it is God, and

  only God, who gives inner grace, although he only gives it in truth through the

  ministry of Jesus Christ, who—as a man—determines the efficacy of the divine

  will through his prayers and his desires. (Malebranche 1979, p. 185)*

  In this sense, Christ is compared to the angels that, in the Bible, act as “ministers

  of God” (ibid., p. 183). In the same way as the angels gave the Old Law, of which

  they were ministers, so Christ “is the angel of the New Law” (ibid., p. 186) and,

  as “minister” of it, he has been elevated above the angels (ibid., p. 187).

  א Even in Malebranche the definition of the providential role of the angels betrays

  a “ministerial,” that is, genuinely governmental, preoccupation. Not only are the angels

  the envoys and ministers of God, but their action—which coincides with the area tra-

  ditionally assigned to miracles—provides, within the system of laws and general wills,

  something like the paradigm of the state of exception, which allows Malebranche to

  formulate in new terms his critique of miracles. According to Malebranche, there are

  in the Old Testament many places that testify to miraculous events, but these must not

  be interpreted as being caused by the particular wills of God that are contrary to his

  general laws. Instead, they should be understood as the consequence of a general will

  through which he has communicated his power to the angels: “I believe I can prove

  with the authority of Sacred scripture that the angels have received from God a power

  over the present world; that God executes their wills and, through them, his designs,

  according to certain general laws, in such a way that everything that appears miraculous

  in the Old Testament in no way proves that God acts in accordance with particular wills”

  * The English translation of the Eclaircissements appended to Malebranche’s Treatise on Nature and Grace is only partial. This passage and the subsequent ones are unavailable. Page references refer to the French original.—Trans.

  THE KINGDOM AND THE GLORY

  615

  (ibid., pp. 182–183). So-called miracles are the consequence of a general law with which

  God has given to his angelic ministers the power to act in apparent violation of another

  general law (for instance, that of the communication of movements). The exception is,

  in other words, not a miracle (a particular will outside the system of general laws), but

  the effect of a general law that confers on the angels a special power of government.

  Miracles are not outside the legal system but represent a particular case in which a law

  is not applied so that another law, through which God delegates his sovereign power to

  the angels in view of the best possible government, can be.

  Schmitt’s theory of the state of exception—which, though suspending the application

  of some norms, is not situated outside the global legal order— corresponds perfectly to

  the model of angelic power to be found in the Treatise.

  1.4. What is at stake in the treatise is the definition of the best possible

  government. The difficulty that the task runs into (the same as that with which

  Jansen struggles) is the conciliation of two propositions that are in apparent

  contradiction with one another: “God wants all men to be saved” and “Not all

  men are saved.” It is nothing less than a contrast in God between the will, which

  wishes that all men, even the wicked, will be saved, and the wisdom that cannot

  but choose the most simple and general laws for this end. The best government

  will therefore be that which is able to find the most economic relationship be-

  tween will and wisdom or, as Malebranche writes, between the wisdom that

  has order and constancy in its sights, and fecundity (which demands that the

  Church be broader and more numerous):

  God loves men and wants them all to be saved; he wants to sanctify them all; he

  wants his work to be beautiful; that his Church be the broadest and the most

  perfect. But God loves his wisdom infinitely more, because he loves it invincibly

  with a natural and necessary love. He cannot therefore dispense with acting in a

  manner that is most wise and worthy of himself; he must follow the behavior that

  corresponds best to his attributes. But by acting in ways that are most simple and

  worthy of his wisdom, his work cannot be more beautiful or greater than it is.

  For if God had been able to make his Church greater and more perfect than it is,

  by following other equally simple paths, it would mean that by acting as he did,

  he did not intend to execute the wo
rk that was most worthy of him [ . . . ] The

  wisdom of God, which prevented him from complicating his paths and carrying

  out miracles at each instant, obliges him to act in a general, constant, and uniform

  way. For this reason he does not save all men, although in reality he wishes them all

  to be saved. Despite loving his creatures, he only does for them what his wisdom

  enables him to do; and, although he wants a broad and perfect Church, he does

  not make it absolutely greater and more perfect but the greatest and most perfect

  in relation to the paths that are most worthy of him. For, once again, God does not

  form his designs other than by comparing the means with the work that they can

  616

  HOMO SACER II, 4

  execute. And when he knew that there was a better relationship between wisdom

  and fecundity, between certain means and certain works, then, to speak as humans

  do, he took the decision, chose his paths, and established his decrees. (Ibid., p. 171)

  Bayle had already begun to ask how such statements could be in accord with

  the commonly accepted notions of the nature and omnipotence of the supreme

  being. In his Réponse aux questions d’un provincial, which Leibniz cites in his

  Theodicy, he writes:

  These [notions] teach us that all things not implying contradiction are possible

  for him, that consequently it is possible for him to save people whom he does

  not save: for what contradiction would result supposing the number of the elect

  were greater than it is? They teach us [ . . . ] that [ . . . ] he has no will which he

  cannot carry out. How, then, shall we understand that he wills to save all men

  and that he cannot do so? (Leibniz, §223, pp. 266–267)

  In reality, Malebranche’s theses become fully comprehensible only if one places

  them on their true terrain, which is that of the government of the world. In

  question is not the abstract point regarding the omnipotence or impotence of

  God, but the possibility of the government of the world, that is, of an ordered

  relation between general laws and particular occasional causes. If God, as the possessor of sovereignty, acted from start to finish according to particular wills,

  infinitely multiplying his miraculous interventions, there would be neither gov-

  ernment nor order but only chaos and what one might call a pandemonium of

  miracles. For this reason, as sovereign, he must reign and not govern; he must fix the laws and the general wills and allow the contingent play of occasional causes

  and particular wills their most economical execution:

  A God that knows everything must not disturb the simplicity of his paths. An

  immutable being must always maintain uniform behavior. A general cause must

  not act through particular wills. The government of God must bear the signs of

  his attributes, unless the immutable and necessary order does not force him to

  change it; because, with respect to God, order is an inviolable law; he loves it

  invincibly and will always prefer it to the arbitrary laws with which he executes

  his designs. (Malebranche 1979, p. 188)

  But what results from the relationship between general will and occasional

  causes, between Kingdom and Government, God and Christ is an oikonomia

  in which what is at stake is not so much whether men are good or evil, but in

  what way the damnation of many can be reconciled in an ordered way with the

  salvation of few, and the evil nature of some people is nothing but the collateral

  effect of the goodness of others.

  THE KINGDOM AND THE GLORY

  617

  א In Leibniz’s polemic with Bayle, from which resulted his Essais de Théodicée sur

  la bonté de Dieu, la liberté de l’homme et l’origine du mal, he evokes the name of Malebranche on more than one occasion and declares himself in agreement with his theory

  of the general wills, which he claims— rightly or wrongly—to have fathered. He writes:

  The excellent author of The Search for Truth, having passed from philosophy to

  theology, published finally an admirable treatise on Nature and Grace. Here he

  showed in his way [ . . . ] that the events which spring from the enforcement

  of general laws are not the object of a particular will of God [ . . . ] I agree with

  Father Malebranche that God does things in the way most worthy of him. But I

  go a little further than he, with regard to “general and particular acts of will.” As

  God can do nothing without reasons, even when he acts miraculously, it follows

  that he has no will about individual events but what results from some general

  will. (Leibniz, §204–206, pp. 254–256)

  The proximity of his theory of preestablished harmony and of the best of possible worlds

  to Malebranche’s system seemed to Leibniz so great that it led him to remind his readers

  that he had been the first to elaborate it:

  While I was in France I showed to M. Arnauld a dialogue I had composed in

  Latin on the cause of evil and the justice of God [the Confessio philosophi ]; it was not only before his disputes with Father Malebranche, but even before the book

  on The Search for Truth appeared. (Ibid., §211, p. 260)

  The very idea of “theodicy” is, in fact, already present in Malebranche: “It is not enough,”

  he writes, “to have it understood that God is powerful and that he makes his creatures

  do what he wishes. It is necessary, if possible, to justify his wisdom and his goodness”

  (Malebranche 1979, p. 174). Like Malebranche, Leibniz also affirms that God always

  chooses the most simple and general paths,

  [ . . . ] which it is easiest to explain, and which also are of greatest service for the

  explanation of other things [ . . . ] And even though the system of Pre- established

  Harmony were not necessary otherwise, because it banishes superfluous mira-

  cles, God would have chosen it as being the most harmonious [ . . . ] It is as if

  one said that a certain house was the best that could have been constructed at

  a certain cost. One may, indeed, reduce these two conditions, simplicity and

  productivity, to a single advantage, which is to produce as much perfection as

  possible: thus Father Malebranche’s system in this point amounts to the same

  as mine. (Leibniz, §208, p. 257)

  The consequences that Leibniz drew from his system with regard to the problem of the

  origin and necessity of evil are well known. Divine wisdom embraces all possible worlds,

  compares them, and weighs them up in order to penetrate the major or minor degree of

  618

  HOMO SACER II, 4

  perfection. It sets them out and distributes them in an infinity of possible universes, each of which contains an infinity of creatures:

  The result of all these comparisons and deliberations is the choice of the best

  from among all the possible systems, which wisdom makes in order to satisfy

  goodness completely; and such is precisely the plan of the universe as it is. (Ibid.,

  §225, pp. 267–268)

  But the choice of the best possible world has a price, which is the quantity of evil, of

  suffering, and damnation that is contained within it as the necessary attendant effect.

  Once again Malebranche is called upon to justify the providential choice in the name

  of general laws:

  But one must believe that even sufferings and monstrosities are part of order; and

  it
is well to bear in mind not only that it was better to admit these defects and

  these monstrosities than to violate general laws, as Father Malebranche some-

  times argues, but also that these very monstrosities are in the rules, and are in

  conformity with general acts of will, though we are not capable of discerning

  this conformity. It is just as sometimes there are appearances of irregularity in

  mathematics which issue finally in a great order when one has finally got to the

  bottom of them: that is why I have already in this work observed that according

  to my principles all individual events, without exception, are consequences of

  general acts of will. (Ibid., §241, pp. 276–277)

  Even the most beautiful minds have zones of opacity in which they get lost to the point

  that a much weaker mind can ridicule them. This is what occurred to Leibniz with

  Voltaire’s caricature of his position in Candide. In the case of Leibniz this defeat has two reasons. The first is juridical-moral, and concerns the justificatory intent that is expressed in the very title, Theodicy. The world as it is does not require justification but saving; and, if it does not require saving, it needs justifying even less. But to want to justify God for the way in which the world is amounts to the worst misunderstanding of Christianity that

  one can imagine. The second and more important reason has a political character, and

  concerns his blind faith in the necessity of the law (of the general will) as the instrument of the government of the world. According to this aberrant idea, if the general law requires as a necessary consequence that Auschwitz takes place, then also “monstrosities are within the rules,” and the rule does not become monstrous for this reason.

  1.5. The influence of Malebranche on Rousseau’s political theory has been

  widely documented (Bréhier, Riley, Postigliola). However, scholars have merely

  reconstructed the considerable terminological debts and the remarkable influences

  that run between them, but they have rarely investigated the structural analogies

  that accompanied and made possible the shift from the theological context to

  the political one. In particular, the monograph by Patrick Riley, The General Will

  THE KINGDOM AND THE GLORY

  619

  Before Rousseau, has traced a broad genealogy of the notions of volonté générale and volonté particulière, which leads from the theology of the eighteenth century

 

‹ Prev