Paul Collier - Wars, Guns, and Votes

Home > Other > Paul Collier - Wars, Guns, and Votes > Page 7
Paul Collier - Wars, Guns, and Votes Page 7

by Democracy in Dangerous Places (pdf)


  them: in addition to being British I am English, more particularly

  Northern English, and getting right to the bone, I am a Yorkshire-

  man; I have taught my son Daniel to sing our anthem, “On Ilkley

  Moor bar t’at.” The British general election of 2001 pitched a York-

  shireman against a Scot for prime minister. Yet like most people

  from Yorkshire I supported the Scot. A society can function perfectly

  well if its citizens hold multiple identities, but problems arise when

  those subnational identities arouse loyalties that override loyalty to

  the nation as a whole. As the Luo vote suggests, in the societies of the

  bottom billion, ethnic identity usually trumps national identity.

  The societies of the bottom billion are for the most part far more

  ethnically diverse than those of the high-income countries. Often

  this diversity verges on being a taboo subject: it is just too upsetting.

  I think that it poses genuinely tough, but not insuperable, problems.

  They will not be overcome unless they are faced.

  Ethnic diversity compounds the problems that the societies of

  52

  WARS, GUNS, AND VOTES

  the bottom billion would in any case face in making electoral com-

  petition work. Yet more fundamentally, diversity impedes the basic

  role of the state, the provision of public goods. It is tempting to con-

  clude that what an ethnically diverse society of the bottom billion

  needs is a strongman. Wrong: bad as democracy is in ethnically di-

  verse societies, dictators are even worse. But there is a vital role for

  political leadership: leaders must build the nation before they can

  build the state.

  Wh at was t h e o r i g i n o f these strong ethnic loyalties? In the absence of states, ethnicity was the obvious basis for collective action, and in a rural society bumping along at a subsistence level of

  income, one form of collective action was supremely important: in-

  surance. Life at subsistence is risky: if you fall sick when you should

  be plowing, planting, or harvesting, your income will collapse. If

  vermin eat your food stores, you face starvation. You need catas-

  trophe insurance. The problem with insurance is what economists

  coyly term moral hazard: if I’m insured, what the heck! If you could

  insure yourself against a decline in income, why get up in the morn-

  ing? And so such insurance does not exist unless the moral hazard

  problem can be solved. The solution to moral hazard is not indig-

  nantly to protest that the insurer should not doubt your good faith,

  it is to make your behavior observable. Only if the insurer can see

  that you are trying your best does the insurance become feasible. For

  a private insurance company such observation would be prohibi-

  tively expensive, but for a community it is feasible. Nosiness, gossip,

  friendly intimacy, all the ingredients that are natural to a commu-

  nity also happen to be just what is needed for insurance.

  Observability is necessary but not sufficient. The right to rely

  upon other people in the community when faced by a personal ca-

  tastrophe depends upon a reciprocal obligation to provide such as-

  sistance to others: but who is in and who is out? If anyone can join

  Ethnic Politics

  53

  or leave the insurance group at any time, then it will be in perpetual

  deficit: people will declare themselves to be members of the com-

  munity when they fall on hard times and declare themselves fancy-

  free when things are going well. This is known in economics as the

  problem of adverse selection: unless insurance companies take care,

  instead of getting a random selection of clients from the popula-

  tion, they get people who know that they are bad risks. That is why

  insurance companies use some device for restoring a random selec-

  tion, such as offering much better terms for all the employees of a

  firm than they offer to individuals who turn up at the door. This

  is where ethnicity comes in: you do not choose your ethnic group.

  If you are not a member of the ethnic group, you cannot choose to

  become a member when times are hard. If you are a member, you

  cannot choose to exit the group when things go well. That is the

  economic basis for strong ethnic loyalties: it enables income insur-

  ance to work in the high-risk, low-income conditions under which

  it is supremely valuable. Over time, loyalty to the group becomes

  reinforced by all the normal power of morality: it is morally good to

  meet your obligations.

  Insurance sustained by loyalty helps everyone within the group

  and is not at the expense of other groups. However, even in the tra-

  ditional economy loyalty to the group is sometimes at the expense of

  other groups, most obviously in respect of violence against enemy

  groups. But ethnic loyalties have far more scope for being at the

  expense of other groups when they are transferred to the context of

  the modern economy. The public purse becomes the common pool

  resource that the collective action of one group can capture at the ex-

  pense of other groups. It is at this stage that moral obligations to the

  ethnic group collide with moral obligations to society as a whole.

  My friend John Githongo, anticorruption commissioner in the

  Kenyan government, blew the whistle on the corruption at the heart

  of the government, becoming internationally famous and an exile

  in the process. Even I could see that what John did took courage.

  54

  WARS, GUNS, AND VOTES

  But in talking to him I got a surprise: it had taken more than cour-

  age. John is a Kikuyu, the tribe that dominates the government. Un-

  surprisingly, when he blew the whistle against the government, his

  Kikuyu friends had accused him of betrayal. But the surprise was

  that John had felt this himself as an inner struggle of conflicting

  loyalties. Like many of the finest African reformers, John is a com-

  mitted Christian: religious faith gives a moral framework that helps

  people to put their ethnic obligations in perspective. Another com-

  mitted Christian reformer, Oby Ezekwesili, who bravely slammed

  the door shut on Nigeria’s public procurement scams, described the

  prevailing morality: “They see themselves as good if they benefit a

  few thousand kin at the expense of the nation.” It is that prevailing

  morality that gives ethnic loyalties a whole new possibility for being

  valuable to the group yet damaging for the society.

  Far from the transition to the modern economy weakening

  ethnic bonds, there are strong forces intensifying them. Occasion-

  ally an event gets under the skin of a society and reveals much more

  than its direct importance. Here is the story of a Kenyan funeral.

  Like Raila Odinga, Mr. Otieno was a Luo. However, he had left

  his native region in his youth and moved to Nairobi, where he had

  become a successful businessman and married a Kikuyu woman.

  So far we have a standard story of the melting pot. On his death in

  1986, his widow, in accordance with Mr. Otieno’s last will and testa-

  ment, arranged for his burial in Nairobi. At this point Mr. Otieno’s<
br />
  Luo relatives objected: they wanted him buried back home. Indeed,

  they wanted him home so badly that they took the matter to court.

  Faced with a choice between adhering to the wishes of the dead

  man and his wife, or the wishes of the relatives, the court was in no

  doubt: he was duly buried back in his Luo village.

  What on earth was going on? Think back to the key policing

  roles of ethnicity: entry and exit from the obligations of the group.

  There is little difficulty in policing entry: “Very sorry but we won’t

  help you because you’re not one of us.” But policing exit is rather

  Ethnic Politics

  55

  harder. The people who will want to exit from their obligations are

  the successful: and how do you stop them? This is where the place of

  burial comes in. The spirits of ancestors loom large in the belief sys-

  tems of most ancient societies, and spirits are usually localized. Mr.

  Otieno might have managed to exit his obligations during life, but

  he might now be getting his comeuppance in death. Consciously, or

  subliminally, an enforcement mechanism for ethnic loyalty was at

  work; and unlike Mr. Otieno it was alive and well.

  S o w h at h a p p e n s i f t h e r e are many ethnic groups, each with powerful loyalties? How does it affect the politics?

  Electoral competition is an activity with powerful economies of

  scale: if I can get 51 percent of the votes I win. Indeed, in the absence

  of restraints on the use of power, I win everything. To reap these

  economies of scale, power seekers group together into political par-

  ties that develop brands and try to build voter loyalty. In ethnically

  homogenous societies with winner-take-all voting systems, this pro-

  cess tends to be driven to the extreme in which everyone amalgam-

  ates into only two parties. Although the leaders of these parties are

  chosen only by their respective supporters, once chosen, both leaders

  chase the median voter to get elected. This produces a politics of

  moderation that broadly describes how modern democracies func-

  tion. One hallmark is that the activists within each political party are

  usually dissatisfied with the moderation of their leaders. We see the

  process played out most clearly in America, but with minor varia-

  tions it is the general pattern.

  When I first tried to work out how this process was affected by

  ethnic diversity I came away quite heartened. Of course, if voters

  had strong ethnic identities then politicians would organize their

  parties on ethnic lines: this would simply be the cheapest way of at-

  tracting voter loyalty. The election itself would sound very different

  from an election in an ethnically homogenous society: leaders would

  56

  WARS, GUNS, AND VOTES

  simply be mobilizing their own ethnic base rather than reaching out

  to the median voter. But after the election these ethnic parties would

  need to form coalitions. Any ethnic group that got too demanding

  would not be able to bid itself into the winning coalition. Ethnic pol-

  itics might produce a merry-go-round of changes in governments,

  but each group would get close to its fair share of power.

  Since publishing those ideas in 2001 I have started to have

  doubts. First, ethnic politics seems likely to contaminate the content

  of the election campaign. Policy choices get crowded out by iden-

  tity. Let’s go back to those winning electoral strategies: remember

  the one that involved playing the ethnic card. Playing on ethnic

  fears and hatreds is truly the politics of the gutter: unfortunately, it

  works. The holy grail of modern economic field research is the ran-

  domized experiment, something that medics have been doing for

  years, but it is usually more difficult to arrange with economic in-

  terventions. When it comes to the content of an election campaign,

  you would imagine that the scope for conducting a genuinely ran-

  domized experiment is decidedly limited. Not one bit of it: Leonard

  Wantchekon, a remarkable economist from Benin now working in

  America, did just that. He managed to persuade the politicians of

  Benin randomly to adopt different campaign messages in different

  localities. This alone tells you most of what you need to know about

  the election campaign in Benin, but Wantchekon’s story is yet more

  depressing. Not only were politicians willing randomly to adopt

  either a campaign message that they would provide good national

  governance or a message that they would provide ethnic favorit-

  ism, but once the results were subject to statistical analysis, it became

  clear that favoritism was more effective at pulling in the votes.

  Not only does identity trump policies, but to the extent that

  policies do enter, instead of a race to capture the vote of Ms. Moder-

  ate the All-Powerful Median Voter, there is a race to the extremes.

  Colin Jennings introduced me to this tendency via the expressive

  voting idea. His work analyzes how electoral competition is likely

  Ethnic Politics

  57

  to work out in ethnically divided societies. Voting for the extremist

  parties offers the strongest identity fix. It also selects the most ar-

  dently sectarian leaders, so that when it comes to the stage of reach-

  ing compromise in a grand coalition, the starting point for the ne-

  gotiations is as far toward the position of your own ethnic group as

  possible.

  One graphic instance of this unattractive process is evident in

  Northern Ireland, where electoral competition was meant to force

  moderation, with parties heading for the center ground in order to

  build a coalition. Instead, precisely the opposite happened. There

  are four major political parties in Northern Ireland, two Protes-

  tant and two Catholic. On each side one of these parties is moderate

  and one is extreme. Prior to power sharing, the largest parties on

  each side of the Protestant-Catholic divide were the moderate par-

  ties: indeed, they were the parties that brokered the power sharing.

  But once power sharing was introduced, voters polarized; now the

  dominant parties on each side are the extremists. The ruling coali-

  tion is a coalition of the extremes headed by grinning bigots who

  cannot believe their luck. This seems to be a likely consequence of

  identity politics more generally. Indeed, it happened in the Kenyan

  elections of December 2007. The forty-eight ethnic groups coalesced

  into pro-Kikuyu and anti-Kikuyu coalitions.

  I also came to see that electoral competition is not the only as-

  pect of democracy that matters. Electoral competition needs to be

  complemented by checks and balances. In turn, checks and balances

  are public goods: that is, they have to be supplied by cooperation.

  Ethnic politics makes such cooperation to build checks and balances

  much harder. I came across this graphically in the aftermath of the

  Nigerian elections of 2007. The new speaker of the House of Rep-

  resentatives, Patricia Etteh, was soon caught misappropriating the

  funds meant for her office. She had, for example, acquired twelve

&nb
sp; Mercedes. I do not want to get Scandinavian about the odd dozen

  Mercedes: I am quite prepared to believe that any self-respecting

  58

  WARS, GUNS, AND VOTES

  speaker needs them. But many Nigerians seemed not to think so:

  they regarded it as outrageous and she was pilloried in the media.

  So far there is nothing remarkable in this story: a relatively minor

  infringement that met its fate. It is the reaction to the criticism that

  is of significance. As soon as she was criticized in the media, the

  other politicians from her own ethnic group, the Yoruba, leaped to

  her defense. Quite explicitly, their message was “Hands off: she’s

  our only representative at the trough.” If a corruption charge can be

  deflected by playing the ethnic card, then standards of public con-

  duct are bound to be low.

  So ethnic electoral politics may not be as benign as I had previ-

  ously thought. This would certainly gel with the evidence on ethnic

  diversity and public goods, much of which is derived from contexts

  in which political choices are the result of vigorous electoral compe-

  tition, such as North American cities.

  M a n y s t u d i e s h av e f o u n d t h at public services are systematically worse as a result of ethnic diversity among citizens. The

  association is causal: it is not just that ethnically diverse societies

  happen also to have poor public services. Controlling for other char-

  acteristics, greater diversity implies worse public services. Not only

  that, but expenditure on channels suited to ethnic patronage, such as

  the public payroll, is higher. Why does diversity make public goods

  provision harder? For that we need to turn to micro-level evidence

  on how collective decisions are taken.

  One result clearly established by research is that trust is weaker

  across ethnic groups than within them. One rather clever way of

  demonstrating this was the work of Abigail Barr, a researcher in

  my group, who investigated variations in the level of trust among

  the communities of rural Zimbabwe. Trust is difficult to measure,

  but she followed a recent line of research and used experimental

  games played by volunteers who could win small amounts of money

  Ethnic Politics

  59

  depending upon the strategies they adopted. Zimbabwe was par-

  ticularly well suited to the investigation because alongside ethnically

 

‹ Prev