The Life of Alcibiades

Home > Other > The Life of Alcibiades > Page 29
The Life of Alcibiades Page 29

by Jacqueline de Romilly


  gained a perspective that sheds light on us today.

  At other times, even recent times, these similarities and perspectives

  would no doubt have presented a different order of importance.

  I am certain, for example, that fi fty years ago, when I was writing a

  book on Thucydides and Athenian Imperialism , and with the war against

  Hitler raging throughout Europe and beyond, the most striking thing to

  me about the life of Alcibiades would have been the way in which he

  identifi ed with imperialism in Athens, and, thanks to Thucydides, with

  imperialism in general. I would have been struck by his desire to take on

  the Peloponnesians, then by the audacity of the Sicilian expedition and

  the grand design that was lurking behind this initial desire for conquest. I

  would have admired the way in which all those forces that impel the pow-

  erful to new conquests are revealed in him as he makes more and more en-

  emies. And I would have appreciated the example of that expedition that

  constituted the beginning of the end; for fi nally everyone united against

  the conqueror. Consequently, I would have been keenly aware of the way

  in which Thucydides marked the differences between the imperialism of

  Alcibiades and the more moderate, more prudent imperialism that Pericles

  embodied. I would also have stressed the way in which, as Thucydides’s

  analyses foreshadowed, the alliance against Athens quickly formed, fi rst

  in Sicily, then in Ionia, and in almost the entire Greek world. And I would

  have marveled to observe how, across the years, Hitler’s forces overex-

  tended themselves in the same way and ended with a similar disaster.

  Of course, Alcibiades and Hitler have nothing in common; but the les-

  son that the Greeks themselves read in the history of Alcibiades would

  have meaning when applied to altogether different circumstances.

  More generally, I would no doubt have recognized in these events what

  linked hubris to nemesis . And in particular I would have delighted to see the birth, in terms of imperialism and Alcibiades, of the concept that public opinion can be highly signifi cant.

  This concept emerges, negatively, from the work of Thucydides. Some

  of his speakers dared to say to the Athenians: “Aren’t you going to alien-

  ate the goodwill of the cities by behaving like this?” Others noted that

  they would have to rely on what remained of that goodwill. The Greek

  Conclusion 195

  word is eunoia . Isocrates, at the beginning of the following century, con-

  structed a theory of eunoia , of the need to know how to achieve recon-

  ciliation, in external and internal politics, and in the work of the orator. 4

  In his imperialist politics, Alcibiades contributed to Athens’ loss of this

  important asset; and the conduct of the cities of Sicily provides proof of

  that. But at the same time, Alcibiades, through his insolence and his prov-

  ocations, lost the support of a whole sector of Athens. He made enemies,

  and those enemies were his undoing.

  Thucydides put it simply: his insolence in private life impacted his polit-

  ical career: “His habits gave offense to everyone, and caused them to com-

  mit affairs to other hands, and thus before long to ruin the city” (6.15.4).

  Alcibiades, who could be persuasive whenever he wished, was unable

  to inspire confi dence in those on whom, ultimately, his fate would depend.

  According to Isocrates, this was the way a sense of morality could prove

  benefi cial.

  Today, in that same domain of foreign relations, perhaps we might be

  more sensitive to the drama of the quarrels between Greek cities, quarrels

  that the gold of rich Asians crudely settled.

  There, too, experience was painful for the Greeks. As was often the

  case for them, however, it soon bore good fruit. They grasped the folly of

  all these quarrels dividing cities so close in culture. Alcibiades had been

  part of these quarrels, had encouraged and exacerbated them; to them

  he owed, indirectly, his downfall. Even during his lifetime we encounter

  Greek opposition to these deals with barbarians. And some years later, at

  the beginning of the fourth century, there were calls for unity and the cre-

  ation of a Greek bloc to oppose the most powerful barbarians: Gorgias,

  Lysias, Isocrates supported this effort and fought for it. The Greeks estab-

  lished federations and confederations. Can we not, in building Europe,

  recognize in the scandal of Alcibiades’s fi nal years and his plots with the

  satraps a call to rally and to do better?

  The lesson is that we must not follow either path: that of the imperialist

  Alcibiades in the beginning or that of the beggar at barbarian courts play-

  ing one city-state off the other. Alcibiades’s actions are a wake-up call, one

  that has meaning right now.

  4. See my article “Eunoia in Isocrates, or the Political Importance of Creating Good Will,” Journal of Hellenic Studies 78 (1958): 92–101.

  196 Conclusion

  But this analogy with the unifi cation of Europe is, in the case of Alcibi-

  ades, indirect and superfi cial; when we look back at his life, the crisis in

  democracy is what is most striking and moving today. Here the parallels

  come into full view and constantly astonish us.

  First, there were the personal rivalries that ultimately paralyzed the

  state. It was Nicias against Alcibiades. Though there was almost no

  difference in their external policies, the people trusted only one or the

  other. The fi rst result of this dichotomy was that it ensured the failure of

  every effort. The second problem was that it led to tensions, ruses, and

  futile attacks. Even ostracism, created, at least in part, to avoid these

  confl icts, was manipulated by various efforts and shifting alliances. Am-

  bition, when it wants something, overcomes every obstacle, regardless

  of the means.

  And that is precisely what it was: personal ambition, the desire of a

  single person to exercise power. Athenians distrusted Alcibiades for what

  they thought was his aspiring to tyranny. But ambition, as everyone

  knows, can also leave its mark in democratic institutions and cause just as

  much harm as tyranny would.

  These selfi sh ambitions lead not only to demagoguery, but, when pushed

  to the extreme, to political provocation and retaliation of the worst kind.

  And that brings us to the “affairs,” something we see in our own day.

  The scandals involving Alcibiades were of all types.

  His taste for luxury, closely linked to the appetite for power, led him

  to spend money for athletic glory, and that brought him the attention of

  everyone. But the expenses he incurred for this purpose were suspicious

  and led to a long trial. Such things happen when ambition, tied to bold-

  ness, knows no limits or scruples. They are not the signs of a healthy

  democracy.

  There are times when one scandal or another arises, and the “prob-

  lems” multiply. There are accusations and denunciations. There is an

  arrest. Careers are wrecked by a wave of panic. Alcibiades was such a vic-

  tim. This man, who had so much to be held to account for, was probably

  brought down by accusations that he could have s
uccessfully countered.

  And emotions are so much stronger in a democracy. Conspiracy theo-

  ries arise easily: “He aspires to tyranny,” said the enemies of Alcibiades,

  the way we would today say “to fascism.” In both cases, there is talk of a

  plot against the state. Fear turns contention into drama.

  Conclusion 197

  After that, the domains of justice and politics become intermingled.

  In Athens, this tangle was common and almost constant: the same peo-

  ple were voting in the Assembly and in the courts of justice. Sometimes

  the Assembly had the power of a court. In our country, however, justice

  is a separate domain, and everyone insists that it must remain so. The

  press, however, links justice to shifts in public opinion. People are not so

  insistent on the independent judiciary when troublesome facts interfere.

  Among individuals today who are under scrutiny, how many feel them-

  selves caught in a trap like Alcibiades?

  Clearly, it is not necessary to force the comparison. The two eras in this

  comparison are not alone in scandals. Cicero’s Rome was rife with trials

  dealing with embezzlement and criminality. In Europe today, our country

  is not alone in its scandals.

  And yet how can we help feeling startled by such connections? And

  how can we avoid the questions they raise?

  For example, whether in ancient Greece or France today, one cannot

  escape the impression that scandalous behavior among leaders is getting

  worse.

  Thucydides says clearly that rival ambitions arose after Pericles’s death;

  and he explains that this happened because no paramount leader of the

  people emerged. Is that true today as well? There have been other times in

  the history of democracy in France when there were enormous scandals,

  but we are unlikely to fi nd another period in which the habit of pursuing

  and imprisoning politicians for corruption fl ourished as it does today, in

  full view of everyone. Is this because, as in Athens, the power struggle be-

  tween political leaders leaves no clear winner? That explanation does not

  seem to fi t, at least not very tightly. But the fi ghting between parties, or be-

  tween individuals, offi cially recognized, is expensive and leads to careless-

  ness. Isn’t this, cast in terms of groups and economics, the same principle?

  Could this be a weakness inherent in democracy? The Athenian exam-

  ple suggests not. In desperation, the Athenians renounced the democracy

  in 411, but there was no change in individual passions or in the policies of

  the cities. In fact, if there was a real danger inherent in competition within

  the democracy, that problem existed only in the character of the citizens

  themselves, in the power of leading men, and in civic pride.

  Everyone knew that Athens, having entered the war with confi dence,

  had lost its vigor and its faith. Everyone knew that the sophists had

  198 Conclusion

  managed to encourage realism and skepticism in the youth. And every-

  one knew that morality had been undermined by the war. Thucydides

  analyzed all these moral effects of the war and of civil war. Is it any dif-

  ferent today? Do people today, as in Athens, not talk endlessly about our

  moral crisis? Democracy cannot survive the debasement of values. That

  is why the quality of education, the formation of future leaders, must be

  the primary concern of politicians who care about democracy—and this is

  clearly not the case today.

  In some ways, the Athenian experience can also be reassuring: a U-turn

  is always possible. There was one in Athens, following the defeat and the

  occupation, and after the Athenians had overthrown the government of

  the Thirty. The fi rst great decision of the restored democracy was to end,

  once and for all, the political quarreling. For us as well, defeat and oc-

  cupation were the occasion for a comparable reversal around newfound

  values capable of inspiring heroic acts. There may be other occasions as

  well, and, if we are clear-eyed, they might not come at such great cost.

  These thoughts have led us far from Alcibiades. And they exceed the

  experiences of his lifetime: the reconciliation of the parties and the desire

  for unity among the cities came only as a reaction, after him and without

  him. He had experienced years of crisis, contributing valuable talents to

  the fray, but they were all quickly lost in intrigues, quarrels, and revolu-

  tions. He added to this chaos both casually and boldly, both thoughtlessly

  and with imagination. He was also a victim of it. He could have done

  great things for Athens and for Greece. Reviewing his life we see how

  much he did, ultimately, to harm his city and country, not to mention the

  ruin he brought to himself. This amazing man is a model for all time—one

  to study, but not to imitate.

  In the fi nal analysis, will I have simply offered an example of a Greek

  historian of dazzling lucidity and an example of a Greek hero whose life

  provides only negative lessons? That would mean forgetting all the beau-

  tiful images of Alcibiades we have seen. That would mean forgetting his

  charm as well as his sharp intelligence, his way with words, and his cour-

  age in facing enemies and adversity. When we remove the political evalu-

  ation, his abilities and talents come to the fore. Alcibiades is like a hero in

  Greek tragedy who outshines the average man, but who is brought down

  by a fatal fl aw. He is an Agamemnon who sacrifi ced his own daughter,

  an Ajax who once insulted Athena, an Eteocles who could not escape his

  Conclusion 199

  paternal curse, a Hercules foolishly in love with a young captive. Alcibi-

  ades was as magnifi cent as they were and ended just as badly.

  We should not fool ourselves. This story is about the fact that admirable

  heroes are destroyed by a fl aw or an indiscretion, and that they illustrate

  the contrast, eminently tragic, between glory and ruin, something that is

  characteristic of both Alcibiades and tragedy. It is not about any particular

  resemblance to one of those tragic heroes. And yet I have pointed out the

  parallels throughout this book. Some would recognize Alcibiades’s ambi-

  tion in Euripides’s hero Eteocles and his desire for power; others would

  fi nd a resemblance to Philoctetes, Socrates’s hero, who, far from home,

  was indispensable for future success, and on whom the sacking of Troy

  depended. The parallels in these situations are not the point here—though

  the impact of such a strong personality makes comparison quite easy.

  In any case, there was an undeniable tragic element in Alcibiades’s life.

  Perhaps he himself was caught in a vise, not the vise of fate, but of po-

  litical necessity. The trap we referred to before closed on him, as did those

  set by the gods for the tragic heroes.

  Obstinately he stood his ground against everything. Never beaten, he

  fought with bravery in every battle. Socrates obtained for him an award

  for bravery. Alcibiades’s bravery never faltered in an attempt to escape

  disaster. He faced everything with clarity and obstinacy, with skill and

  boldness. The picture we have of his death illustrate
s this quality perfectly.

  Like the Homeric heroes who, knowing they were about to die, cried out,

  “So what? I will fi ght!” he fought, alone. This, at least, is a positive lesson.

  In one edition of Thucydides, I found it distracting that the publisher

  had chosen for the cover of the book a picture of Leonidas, nude, hold-

  ing a sword. Leonidas was the Spartan hero of the Persian Wars, at the

  beginning of the fi fth century. He was also a legendary hero, one whose

  style of combat was very different from the strategic maneuvers described

  by Thucydides at the end of that same century. Now here I am today,

  imagining Alcibiades leaving his burning house just like that cover picture

  of Leonidas. We have to expect this with Greece. Even when describing

  dark times and events that, as told by the harshest critics, are comparable

  to the most sordid events in our modern experience, we can expect to see

  them all in a heroic light, one that transfi gures man, wrenching him from

  his sad context to cast him outside of time, into a universal beauty where

  we can look on him with pride.

  Index

  Adeimantus, 170 n5

  orator, 3 , 9 – 13 , 91 – 97 , 192 ; ostracism

  Aegospotami, battle of, 167

  of, 7 – 8 , 22 , 50 – 51 , 81 – 87 , 89 – 103 ;

  Aelius Aristides, 33 n3, 145 n9

  scandals of, 14 – 31 , 73 – 81 , 86 – 87 ,

  Aeschines of Sphettos, 25 , 33 , 172 ,

  102 – 3 ; treacheries of, 90 – 97 , 108 – 22 ;

  183 – 84

  on trust, 89 – 90 ; wealth of, 6 – 8 , 18 ,

  Aeschylus, 56 , 163 – 65

  185 ; youthfulness of, 12 – 14

  Against Alcibiades (attrib. to Andocides),

  Alcibiades of Lyon, Saint, 192 n1

  xvi, 18 , 28 , 50 , 73 – 74

  Alcibiades of Phlegonte, 79 n15

  Agesilaus, 103

  Alcibiades of Sparta, 5

  Agis, Spartan king, 46 , 91 , 102 , 106 – 9 ,

  Alcibiades the elder (grandfather), 5

  127

  Alcibiades’s son, 28 – 29 , 76 , 170 ;

  Alcibiades, 6 ; chariot horses of, 19 ,

  scandals of, 97 – 98 , 180 ; trials of,

  27 – 29 , 87 , 135 – 36 , 179 ; charisma of,

  178 – 80 . See also Leotychidas

  2 – 4 , 24 , 103 , 109 – 10 , 113 , 130 , 195 ;

 

‹ Prev