Sixth Century BCE to Seventeenth Century

Home > Other > Sixth Century BCE to Seventeenth Century > Page 32
Sixth Century BCE to Seventeenth Century Page 32

by Ying-shih Yü


  For the person who knows the meaning of the rites must roam beyond

  the realm so as to keep order in the mundane sphere, must cling to the

  mother in order to preserve the son, must acknowledge his feelings and

  straightaway act accordingly. Should he display anxiety about his reputa-

  tion or be restricted by the formalities, then his fi lial piety will not be

  sincere and his compassion will not be genuine. Father and son, elder

  brother and younger (as formalized relationships, make one) hold feel-

  ings that lead to mutual deceptions. How can that be the larger meaning

  of the rites?86

  Here Guo Xiang charged that the Confucian ritual system of his time was de-

  void of meaning because it could no longer freely express the true feelings of

  man. Quite to the contrary, it had been formalized to the point of sheer artifi ci-

  ality.87 Guo Xiang’s interpretation of “rituals” and “feelings” as antithetical to

  each other proves beyond dispute that in the early fourth century, the Neo-

  Daoists were still grappling with the prob lem of freedom of the individual in

  the face of a strong and deep- rooted Confucian ritual order.

  The Neo- Daoist revolt against the ritual order was more radical, widespread,

  and profound than its attack on the po liti cal order. The reason for this is not

  diffi

  cult to see. The confl ict between feelings and rituals arose, after all, from

  the everyday experiences of the spiritually liberated individual who was caught

  between the growing need to express freely and openly his personal feelings

  on the one hand and the inadequacy of the existing ritualistic forms on the

  other. Naturally, the Neo- Daoist individualist would not hesitate to do away

  with “rituals” whenever and wherever they proved to be in the way of free emo-

  tional expression. Thus, when someone chided Ruan Ji for having violated ritu-

  als by saying good- bye to his sister- in- law, he replied: “ Were the rites estab-

  lished for people like me?” 88 In response to a criticism of his excessive grief

  indi v idua l is m a nd t h e ne o - daois t m ov e m e n t 155

  over the loss of a son, Wang Rong said: “a sage forgets his feelings; the lowest

  beings aren’t even capable of having feelings. But the place where feelings are

  most concentrated is precisely among people like ourselves.” 89 Needless to say,

  for individualists like Ruan Ji and Wang Rong, it was far more meaningful to

  be true to one’s au then tic self than to conform to a ste reo typed social norm. It

  was precisely this search for inner authenticity that turned individualists of the

  period away from Confucian ritualism.

  An inside view that links the rise of Neo- Daoism to the self- discovery and

  self- awareness of the individual has been provided by Xi Kang. In a debate on

  the nature of Confucian learning, he explained why the Six Classics were unac-

  ceptable to him:

  The emphasis of the Six Classics is placed mainly on repression whereas

  human nature experiences joy in the following of desires. Repression

  goes against a man’s inclinations; he attains to naturalness by following

  his desires. Therefore it follows that attainment of naturalness does not

  come from the repressive Six Classics, and preservation of man’s nature

  does not need a base in rituals and laws which run counter to feelings.90

  Thus, in the fi nal analy sis, it was Xi Kang’s profound resentment of ritualistic

  repression that led him to reject Confucianism. In a letter to a friend, he fur-

  ther explained how he was drawn to the Daoist view:

  Further, I was long left to my own devices, and my disposition became

  arrogant and careless, my bluntness diametrically opposed to etiquette;

  laziness and rudeness reinforcing each other. . . . Besides, my taste for

  in de pen dence was aggravated by my reading of Zhuangzi and Laozi; as a

  result, my desire for fame and success grew daily weaker, and my commit-

  ment to freedom increasingly fi rmer.91

  Here, we are told, it was love of in de pen dence and freedom that pushed him to

  Daoism. These two self- revelatory accounts are complementary, and together

  they reveal most vividly the inner dimensions of the rise of the Neo- Daoist

  movement.

  In view of the evidence we have examined thus far, the transition from Confu-

  cian classical scholarship to Neo- Daoist metaphysics may be more intelligently

  interpreted as what Michel Foucault calls a “rupture” in Chinese consciousness.

  It was clearly the case that neo- Daoist metaphysics was not established in the

  places formerly occupied by Confucian classical scholarship, but in an area

  where the latter simply did not exist.92 Han Confucianism was ultimately con-

  cerned with the collective life in an imperial order, and Wei- Jin Neo- Daoism

  with the prob lem of freedom of the individual. The transition from one to the

  other was by no means a smooth one. Viewed from this perspective, it may

  156 indi v idua l is m a nd t h e ne o - daois t m ov e m e n t

  justifi ably be contended that the central historical signifi cance of the develop-

  ment of Pure Conversation lies in the emergence of a totally new mode of

  discourse—an individualistic mode of discourse that superseded the old, col-

  lectivistic one of the Han Period.

  R E C O N C I L I AT I O N B E T W E E N D A O I S T

  I N D I V I D U A L I S M A N D C O N F U C I A N R I T U A L I S M

  So as not to overstate the case of Wei- Jin individualism, we must, in conclud-

  ing, say something about the ritualistic side of the coin. Throughout the period

  under consideration, Confucian ritualism with its marked emphasis on moral

  order and conformity never ceased to be a social and intellectual force with

  vigor and vitality. Side by side with the new individualistic type of familial rela-

  tionships described above there also existed a sharply contrasting type of family

  order. The case of He Zeng

  (199–278) may be proff ered as an illustrative

  example. His was prob ably a family life of the most ritualistic kind. He was not

  only a well- known fi lial son of the day but also maintained a highly formalized

  relationship with his wife throughout his life. In his old age, we are told, he saw

  his wife only two or three times a year; each time, he was formally dressed and

  treated her in strict accordance with the Confucian etiquette between host and

  guest.93 He was clearly following a ritualistic tradition of the Han Period that

  managed the private house hold in the manner of the “government offi

  ce.”94

  Little won der that he found Ruan Ji’s transgression of mourning rites abso-

  lutely intolerable and proposed to have him banished “beyond the sea.”95

  It is in ter est ing to note that there are also indications of a strug gle between

  Confucian ritualism and Neo- Daoist naturalism as two competing ways of life.

  The following story will help to illuminate this contest:

  Wang Rong and He Qiao

  (d. 292) experienced the loss of a parent

  at the same time, and both were praised for their fi lial devotion. Wang,

  reduced to a skeleton, kept to his bed; while He, wailing and weeping,

  performed all the rites. Emperor
Wu

  (r. 265–290) remarked to Liu

  Yi

  , “Have you ever observed Wang Rong and He Qiao? I hear that

  He’s grief and suff ering go beyond what is required by propriety, and it

  makes me worry about him.”

  Liu Yi replied: “He Qiao, even though performing all the rites, has suf-

  fered no loss in his spirit or health. Wang Rong, even though not per-

  forming the rites, is nonetheless so emaciated with grief that his bones

  stand out. Your servant is of the opinion that He Qiao’s is the fi lial devo-

  tion of life, while Wang Rong’s is the fi lial devotion of death. Your Majesty

  should not worry about Qiao, but rather about Rong.”96

  indi v idua l is m a nd t h e ne o - daois t m ov e m e n t 157

  In the fi nal analy sis, the strug gle is clearly reducible to a contest between “ritu-

  als” ( li ) and “feelings” ( qing ) . The story is unmistakably pro- Daoist in tone,

  however. The judgment that Wang Rong surpassed He Qiao in fi lial devotion

  suggests that Neo- Daoist naturalism could beat Confucian ritualism on the lat-

  ter’s own ground. On the other hand, the story also reveals that at the end of the

  Western Jin, Confucian ritualism, though crippled by a social and spiritual cri-

  sis that had lasted for a century, was still very much alive.

  The controversy over “feelings” and “rituals” was carried to the south by

  Western Jin émigrés during the early de cades of the fourth century. It took at

  least another century to bring the debate to a conclusion. The end of the contro-

  versy was not as vis i ble and colorful as the beginning had been, but from the

  historical point of view, it was as impor tant.

  By the middle of the fourth century, Neo- Daoist naturalism and Confucian

  ritualism began to show signs of reconciliation. We fi nd, for example, that the

  idea of “rituals” was no longer being treated with contempt and resentment by

  the elite. On the contrary, they came to the realization that interpersonal feel-

  ings cannot be meaningfully and fully expressed without a sensitive ritual

  system in the fi rst place. Thus, speaking of both the ruler– subject and father– son

  relationships, Yuan Hong (328–376) could now say that their handling required

  the presence of both “feelings” and “rituals” at the same time.97 How is such a

  drastic change in attitude to be accounted for? To answer this question, atten-

  tion must be drawn to a quiet but enduring movement in ritual reforms trace-

  able to as early as the middle of the third century. It is particularly signifi cant

  that the emphasis of the reform movement was focused quite specifi cally on

  the mourning rites, the very battleground on which, as we have seen, wars had

  been fought between Confucian ritualists and Neo- Daoist naturalists. The move-

  ment was by no means a Confucian mono poly. As a matter of fact, Neo- Daoist

  participants were just as active in it. Especially with the founding of the refugee

  regime in the south, the study of the mourning rites gained an unpre ce dented

  popularity. Leading specialists in the fi eld included not only Confucianists and

  Neo- Daoists but Buddhists as well.

  Ritual studies during the period are too complicated to be discussed here.

  For our purposes, however, it will suffi

  ce to note that the spirit of the reform

  movement consisted in the particularization of the rites with a view to satisfy-

  ing, as much as pos si ble, the individuated feelings of the members of each

  mourning community.98 In this way, the reformists claimed that they had com-

  pletely renovated the ritual system, thereby making it, once again, an eff ective

  vehicle for the free expression of personal feelings. Thus, we see that along

  with the self- discovery and self- awareness of the individual, there was also a

  genuine search for ritualization throughout the Wei- Jin Period. Ironically

  enough, even Pure Conversation, the very symbol of Wei- Jin individualism, be-

  came highly ritualized in the course of its development. To qualify as a Pure

  158 indi v idua l is m a nd t h e ne o - daois t m ov e m e n t

  Conversationalist, for instance, one had to be trained in the art of speech, in-

  cluding voice and logic,99 to know how to gesticulate the fl y whisk properly,100 to

  be well versed in the three metaphysical works (the Classic of Changes, the

  Laozi, and the Zhuangzi), and, above all, to belong to the elite circle.101 Wang

  Sengqian’s

  (426–485) letter to his son contains the following in ter est ing

  admonition:

  You have read only about fi ve feet each of the scrolls of the Laozi and the

  Classic of Changes. You have neither known what Wang Bi and He Yan

  had to say, nor the diff erences between the commentaries of Ma (Rong)

  and Zheng (Xuan), nor (Wang Bi’s Laozi) zhi ( - lüe) and ( Zhouyi) li ( - lüe) .

  And yet you have already picked up the fl y whisk and styled yourself a

  Conversationalist. Nothing is more dangerous than this. Suppose Prefect

  Yuan (Can,

  420–477) asks you to talk about the Classic of Changes,

  Palace Secretary Xie (Zhuang,

  421–466) challenges you to a discus-

  sion on the Zhuangzi, or Mr. Zhang (Xu,

  433?–490?) questions you

  about the Laozi, can you answer by admitting that you have not read

  them? Pure Conversation is like the game of archery: the player must

  always be aware of the marks already hit by others. A player who knows

  nothing about them simply loses the game.102

  This is a most vivid account of the basic intellectual qualifi cations of a Pure

  Conversationalist. Clearly, by the middle of the fi fth century, Pure Conversa-

  tion had developed a ritual framework of its own. It fi ts remarkably well with

  Foucault’s description of the socie ties of discourse “whose function is to pre-

  serve discourse by producing it in a restricted group.”103 Thus, with the teach-

  ing of names fi rmly established on the basis of naturalness, and “rituals” on

  that of “feelings,” as it were, a balance between order and individuality was

  restored at long last.

  not e s

  1.

  See Lu Xun

  , “Wenhua pianzhi lun”

  , in Lu Xun quanji

  , 20

  vols. (Beijing: Renmin wenxue, 1973), 1:45–46.

  2.

  Bohu tongde lun, SBCK chu, 7.58; Fung Yu- lan, A History of Chinese Philosophy, trans.

  Derk Bodde, 2 vols. (Prince ton: Prince ton University Press, 1953), 2:44.

  3. Yü

  Ying-

  shih

  , Lishi yu sixiang

  (Taipei: Lianjing, 1976), 39–41.

  4.

  HHS, 12 vols. (Beijing: Zhonghua, 1959), 5.1554; T’ung- tsu Ch’ü, Law and Society in Tra-

  ditional China (Paris: Mouton, 1961), 279.

  5.

  HHS, 10.2775.

  6.

  Ruan Ji ji

  (Shanghai: Guji, 1978), 66. For En glish translation, see Kung- chuan

  Hsiao, A History of Chinese Po liti cal Thought, trans. Frederick W. Mote, 2 vols. (Prince ton:

  indi v idua l is m a nd t h e ne o - daois t m ov e m e n t 159

  Prince ton University Press, 1979), 1:622–623, and Donald Holzman, Poetry and Politics:

  The Lif
e and Works of Juan Chi, a.d. 210– 263 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976), 195–196.

  7. For more details, see Yü Ying- shih, “Mingjiao weiji yu Wei- Jin shifeng di zhuanbian”

  , originally published in Shihuo

  9, nos. 7–8 (November

  1979): 2–4; now collected in Zhongguo zhishi jieceng shilun

  (Taipei:

  Lianjing, 1980), 333–337.

  8. BPZ, 4 vols., WYWK, 4:773–774; En glish translation in Wolfgang Bauer, China and the

  Search for Happiness, trans. Michael Shaw (New York: Seabury Press, 1976), 138–139.

  9. Yang Bojun

  , Liezi jishi

  (Shanghai: Longmen, 1958), 102; A. C. Graham,

  trans., The Book of Lieh Tzu (London: John Murray, 1960), 102. As Graham rightly

  points out in his introduction, the consensus among scholars in China is that the Lieh

  Tzu is a product of the third century c.e. Most of these scholarly opinions are now

  con ve niently collected in Yang Bojun’s Liezi jishi, 185–245.

  10.

  Wang Wengong wenji

  , 2 vols. (Shanghai: Renmin, 1974), 2:439. See Chen

  Yinke

  , Tao Yuanming zhi sixiang yu qingtan zhi guanxi

  (Chengdu: Harvard- Yenching Institute, 1945), 52–53.

  11. See passages quoted in Yü Ying- shih, “Mingjiao weiji,” 336 and n6.

  12. For a general study of Wei- Jin anarchism, see Tan Jiajian

  , “Lüe lun Wei- Jin shiqi

  di wujunlun sichao”

  , Zhongguo zhexue

  2 (March

  1980): 120–136.

  13. Fuzi

  (Writings of Fu Xuan

  ), quoted in SGZ, punctuated edition, 5 vols. (Bei-

  jing: Zhonghua, 1959), 2:213; ZZTJ, 20 vols. (Beijing: Zhonghua, 1956), 5:2018–2019.

  14.

  Colin Morris, The Discovery of the Individual, 1050– 1200 (London: S.P.C.K. [for the

  Church History Society], 1972), 160.

  15. Weishu

  , quoted in SGZ, 1:260.

  16.

  HHS, 8.2278.

  17. Jinshu

  , 10 vols. (Beijing: Zhonghua, 1974), 5.1360.

  18.

  BPZ, 3:509.

  19. Richard B. Mather, trans., Shih- shuo hsin- yü: A New Account of Tales of the World (Min-

  neapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1976), 485.

  20. SGZ, 3:647. See Mori Mikisaburō

  , “Gi- Shin jidai ni okeru ningen no hak-

  ken”

  , Tôyô bunka no mondai

  1 (June 1949):

  146–147.

  21.

 

‹ Prev