The Book of Memory

Home > Other > The Book of Memory > Page 41
The Book of Memory Page 41

by Mary Carruthers


  memory phantasm, as we have seen, employs exactly the same model,

  that of ‘‘seal’’ or ‘‘stamp,’’ in wax most commonly, but also on a coin (as in

  Hugh of St. Victor’s Didascalicon). The Greek concept of hexis, crucial to

  an understanding of moral behavior, is a predisposition that ‘‘stamps’’ or

  ‘‘forms’’ the embodied soul towards behaving in certain ways rather than

  others. Perhaps here as clearly as anywhere else in ancient and medieval

  culture, the fundamental symbiosis of memorized reading and ethics can

  be grasped, for each is a matter of stamping the body–soul, of charakteˆr.

  Heloise’s moment of moral decision is articulated as a rhetorical action.

  This is the most telling feature of the entire incident. It gives us a clear way

  of understanding just how ethics and rhetoric were thought to coincide,

  and as there has been a great deal of misunderstanding about this, especially

  in the modern school of Exegetical criticism, I want to analyze her action

  carefully.

  Exegetical critics believe that literature is ethical in nature, but they think

  of the ethical use of texts in entirely normative and definitional terms. All

  medieval literature, they believe, was thought to promote charity, and the

  only value of the specifics of a text, its ‘‘literal level,’’ is as an instance of a

  universal and normative moral principle. But the direction of this analysis

  runs exactly counter to that of any rhetorical situation. Rhetorically con-

  ceived, ethics is the application of a res or generalized content (most often

  expressed in a textual maxim) to a specific, present occasion which is public

  in nature, because it requires an audience. Rhetoric composes common-

  places by a process of adaptation. Normative or transcendental analysis, in

  Memory and the ethics of reading

  225

  contrast, discovers a universal, timeless principle amid the detritus of the

  event, and its moral truth is unconditioned by audience, occasion, speaker,

  or text. But rhetoric does not normalize an occasion, it occasionalizes

  a norm.95

  What is so striking, and so strikingly medieval, in Heloise’s action is her

  articulation of her own present dilemma and decision by means of her

  memory of a text in the public domain (as we would say). She re-presents

  Cornelia in her own present situation; the text from Lucan provides a

  temporal and spatial meeting-ground, a common place, between a public

  memory and her personal situation, and gives her a way of talking about

  herself in the present. Heloise is ‘‘making a commonplace’’ even as she

  speaks to her grieving friends and relatives, and in the process she is

  re-presenting Cornelia. Or rather, she implies, both Cornelia’s action

  and now her own are part of a definitional copiousness, which can be

  usefully held together within a common memory locus – that is why the

  presence of an audience is so crucial. And copiousness, as I argued in

  Chapter 1, is not a process of analytical definition so much as it is compiling

  a memory place that is most like a florilegial entry, an indefinitely expand-

  able grouping of dicta et facta on some common theme or subject. And, as

  I also have said, these themes (‘‘Justice,’’ ‘‘Wifely Chastity,’’ ‘‘Disgraced

  Husbands’’) do not function as a-priori definitive norms, but as labels, the

  mnemonically necessitated listing of the memorial chest. And, of course,

  sayings and stories can be listed in more than one place, for, like ethics

  itself, they are copiously – rhetorically – defined.

  The presence of an audience would appear to be crucial to the making of

  the ethical action. This simply reminds us that a rhetorical conception of

  ethics requires that its social and public nature be stressed. But it is

  remarkable that instances of moral judgment in medieval literature seem

  so often to require both a literary text and an audience to complete them,

  whether the audience is in the work itself or is created by a direct address to

  readers (Petrarch speaks to Augustine about Virgil, Dorigen utters a formal

  complaint ‘‘as ye [that is, we readers] shal after heere’’).

  The function of this audience, however, is not to supply a norm. It is to

  supply a memory. Heloise’s friends and relations try to dissuade her ‘‘in

  pity for her youth’’; sobbing so that she can scarcely speak, Heloise breaks

  out ‘‘as best she could’’ with Cornelia’s lament and takes the veil. The scene

  is deliberately made memorable – perhaps even contrived to give the

  appearance of spontaneity, in the best traditions of Ciceronian rhetoric –

  and speaker and audience together collaborate in this. Memorableness,

  enabled for this occasion by the quality some writers have called

  226

  The Book of Memory

  ‘‘performance’’ (and to which we might apply the rhetorical term, ‘‘deliv-

  ery’’) would, in fact, seem to be the necessary source of the ethical nature

  and efficacy of Heloise’s act. 96 And the mediator of the action is a piece of a

  literary text. Why? Because it is that which is common to both the subject

  and the audience, a piece of their common memorial florilegium. If the

  audience did not recognize Heloise’s quotation, the scene would lose its

  ethical effectiveness. Instead of talking about ethical rules in medieval

  culture, it would be truer to speak of ethical memories, contained in

  texts as dicta et facta memorabilia; they are not ethical algorithms or

  universal definitions, but are ‘‘copious,’’ like literature. And they require

  not to be applied (like a theorem) but to be read, interpreted.

  This brings us back to the third element in the complete, ethically

  valorized action – Heloise herself. For it is her memory that is the first

  mover, as it were, of the whole incident. Clearly, she is not, in our sense,

  expressing herself. Self-expression is a meaningless term in a medieval

  context – on that point I agree with the Exegetes, for there was no concept

  of an autonomous, though largely inarticulate, individual self, to be

  defined and given a voice against social norms. Heloise is not expressing

  herself, but neither is she simply expressing Lucan. She is expressing her

  ‘‘character,’’ which is a function of memoria.

  So instead of the word ‘‘self ’ or even ‘‘individual,’’ we might better speak

  of a ‘‘subject-who-remembers,’’ and in remembering also feels and thinks

  and judges. In other words, we should think of the apprehending and

  commenting individual subject (‘‘self ’’) also in rhetorical terms. Her sub-

  jectivity is located in Heloise’s memory, including her whole florilegium of

  texts, one of which she invents (in the ancient sense) for this occasion,

  thereby investing it, the occasion, and her own action with common ethical

  value, and giving her audience something to think about.97

  It seems to me that the basic notion of a memory-place as a commonplace

  into which one gathers a variety of material is essential to understanding how

  the process of ethical valorizing occurs. In considering what is the ethical

 
nature of reading, one could do much worse than to start with Gregory the

  Great’s comment, that what we see in a text is not rules for what we ought to

  be, but images of what we are, ‘ our own beauty, our own ugliness.’ It is this

  which enables us to make these texts our own. We read rhetorically, memory

  makes our reading into our own ethical equipment (‘‘stamps our character’’),

  and we express that character in situations that are also rhetorical in nature,

  in the expressive gestures and performances which we construct from our

  remembered experience, and which, in turn, are intended to impress and

  give value to others’ memories of a particular occasion.

  Memory and the ethics of reading

  227

  Thus, the entire ethical situation in Abelard’s account is socially and

  rhetorically conceived: it requires a recollecting subject, a remembered text,

  and a remembering audience. These, of course, are also the three ingredients

  found in virtually all medieval narrative literature. What makes a poem like

  Chaucer’s The Book of the Duchess ethical is its construction: a recollecting

  subject (the dreamer, the Man in Black), remembered dicta et facta (the

  dream itself, fair White, the Ovidian tale of Ceyx and Alcyone), and the

  remembering audience (the dreamer who listens to the Man in Black, and we

  readers).98 That the poem also talks generally about death, love, or honor

  does not in itself make it an ethical poem. Rather, the ethical content is made

  by both the common and specific topics of death, love, and honor, recol-

  lected and spoken by somebody to somebody else in this poem, which

  thereby lodges as an experienced event in the memories of its audience,

  memories that are made up equally of imagines (likenesses) and intentiones

  (feelings). Ethics is inseparable from the copiousness of the text itself and its

  effect upon the memoria of its audience and witnesses. It is interesting to

  reflect that the psychoanalytical situation is in some respects parallel to the

  one I have just described, for the same three ingredients are present: recol-

  lecting subject, remembered dicta et facta in all their copiousness, and a

  remembering audience. But psychoanalysis is neither public nor social in its

  occasion, and it is therefore not truly rhetorical, despite these structural

  similarities. Nonetheless, psychoanalysis often presents itself as a modern

  version of memoria (and sometimes as a modern version of ethics too),

  though in fact by privileging the concepts of privacy and subjectivity it is

  greatly different from medieval memoria. Jacques Lacan sounds very much

  like Cassiodorus when he writes that: ‘ [Psychoanalytic] recollection is not

  Platonic reminiscence – it is not the return of a form, an imprint, an eidos of

  beauty and good . . . coming to us from the beyond. It is something that

  comes to us from the structural necessities, something humble’’ (my emphases).99

  But of course the ‘‘structural necessities’’ that Cassiodorus meant when he

  spoke of the containers of trained memory that give shape to the uneducated

  mind (I would have used the adjective ‘ private,’ but it is too anachronistic)

  were neither generic attributes of Man, nor infusions from some vague

  cultural mentality, but were the publicly held commonplaces laid down

  according to a manner and method that everyone knew and approved.

  F L O W E R S O F R E A D I N G I I : F R A N C E S C A

  Italian and French humanism of the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries is

  studded with vernacular florilegia, including Brunetto Latini’s Treśor,

  228

  The Book of Memory

  written in French for the circle at Avignon (c. 1266) but soon translated into

  Italian. A modern editor of Treśor writes disparagingly of it as a compila-

  tion of compilations, which ‘‘contains no element of imagination, no

  artistic pretension.’’100 Yet Dante has memorialized it as Brunetto’s chief

  work, the fame of which will live forever. And Petrarch did not disdain to

  produce an ethical florilegium (in Latin, to be sure, but for a lay audience),

  derived mainly from Valerius Maximus’ very similar compilation (known

  by its medieval title, Dicta et facta memorabilia), though Valerius Maximus

  was also much admired and studied at this time.

  It is certainly true to observe that ethically directed florilegial

  compilations are distinctive (though not original) products of the early

  Renaissance, from Treśor (1266) to such an Erasmian product as Adagia

  (1508). As Thomas M. Greene has observed in a fine essay on the Adagia,

  ‘‘the impulse, whatever it was, that produced this [florilegial] text and its

  thousands of companions, has to be regarded with some curiosity.’’101

  Clearly it was an impulse distinct from, though not in conflict with, the

  equally typical humanistic one to restore the original purity and wholeness

  of ancient texts. These two activities are fundamentally adaptations of the

  two kinds of reading, lectio and meditatio, which had been developed in

  medieval schools. The desire to establish true texts evolved from the

  scholarship of grammar and rhetorical study, a careful restoration and

  analysis of textual litterae. This sort of study – together with commentary

  and the questions it invokes and responds to – were traditionally the tasks

  of lectio, a master reading a text aloud to his students, responding to

  questions, elucidating hard passages, and, above all, establishing the text.

  In monastic tradition, lectio encompasses all the disciplines of the sacred

  page; Hugh of St. Victor makes this clear in the program he sets forth in

  Didascalicon. But lectio is the preface to, and must be completed by,

  meditatio, if study is to be a truly moral, useful activity. This link between

  studious reading and meditative composition based upon the flowers

  culled from reading goes back to the Rome of St. Jerome and is very

  much a heritage of ancient rhetoric. Jerome wrote to Pope Damasus that

  ‘‘to read without also writing is to sleep.’’102 The humanist impulse to

  compile florilegia directs the literary enterprise specifically to forming,

  from humanist sources, the ethical character of the laity, while at the

  same time confirming one’s own memory and providing an occasion for

  meditative composition. Making florilegia is an unbroken tradition of

  medieval pedagogy; these humanist examples in the genre broaden it

  to include exactly the audience to whom the humanist memory-texts

  are also directed: lawyers, physicians, merchants, aristocrats, and clerical

  Memory and the ethics of reading

  229

  bureaucrats of all sorts, the components of the extensive secular society

  coming into existence in southern, and then later northern, Europe.

  And in this enterprise, the florilegial books of ethical instruction compiled

  by the regular clergy also played their part.103 Even in fourteenth-century

  England at least one such compendium was made for personal meditation

  and not primarily as a preachers’ manual. At the very end of the century,

  John of Mirfeld, an Augustinian canon of St. Bartholomew’s, Smithfield,

  made his Florariu
m Bartholomei, which he prefaces by saying that it provides

  a ‘ storehouse’’ of material ‘‘which every Christian soul needs for its virtuous

  behaviour and its salvation . . . Understand, however, that [these texts] are

  not to be read amidst tumults, but in quiet; not speedily, but one subject at a

  time, with intent and thoughtful meditation.’’104

  Bono Giamboni’s role as translateur of both Treśor and Tullius on

  memory is revealing, for it connects both Treśor and the Ammaestramenti

  with memory training, for which the Herennian precepts offered a human-

  istically approved method, more authentically classical (perhaps this is

  what was thought) than methods associated with university training,

  such as those taught by Thomas Bradwardine. Bartolomeo, the Italian

  Dominican, begins his florilegium with the passage from Cassiodorus

  (cited sententialiter and in the vernacular) which I quoted earlier in this

  chapter: ‘‘Siccome dice Cassiodoro: Lo senno umano se egli non eàjutato e

  restaurato per le cose trovate d’altrui, tosto puote mancare del suo pro-

  prio’’, ‘‘As Cassiodorus says: human judgment if it is not adjusted and

  restored by things found in [the works of] others, promptly will fall short of

  its true nature.’’105 There are few clearer statements of this eminently

  florilegial formulation concerning the nature of human character, and

  the role which public memory, enshrined in books, must play in the

  development of individual ethical behavior.

  Human beings are born imperfect, needing to be completed. To be sure

  this Augustinian doctrine is thought of in terms of vice and virtue, but it is

  very easy, especially if one thinks in modern popular-Freudian terms, to fall

  into an essentially Manichaean understanding of the process as a kind of

  war between the superego and the unconscious. It is truer to the assump-

  tions driving the compilers of florilegia to think of character in terms of

  completion or filling-out or building (the root concept in Latin instruo,

  ‘‘instruct’’). Public memory is a needed ethical resource, for its contents

  complete the edifice of each individual’s memory.

  Therefore, says Bartolomeo, it behooves a wise man not to rest content

  with his own ideas, but by diligent study to search out those of others. Of

 

‹ Prev