Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 11
Revolution and the Republic Page 11

by Jeremy Jennings


  of society, in the same way that the true nature of man and his necessary state is

  society in general’. It was, in other words, the constitutive and statutory laws of a

  society that were its natural laws, that embodied what was just, reasonable, and

  necessary, and it was because this had not been recognized that people had been

  preached such absurd nonsense about the disorders inflicted upon man by society.

  Like Maistre, Bonald had only contempt for the supposed merits of the ‘entirely

  man-made’ American republic: its enthusiasts proclaimed it to be eternal when it

  had only existed for a mere fifteen years. It would inevitably disintegrate.78

  Similarly, Bonald rejected the view that natural laws were somehow ‘engraved’

  upon the heart and therefore did not require any ‘visible authority’ or instruction to

  77 Bonald, Législation Primitive, considérée dans les derniers temps par les seules lumières de la raison

  (1800), in Œuvres complètes, (1864), i. 1050–1402.

  78 Bonald, Théorie du pouvoir, 347–50.

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  47

  make them known. A wiser philosophy, he argued, would recognize that these

  truths needed to be inculcated and that this could be achieved by, amongst other

  things, the influence of a good education and of good laws. Above all, Bonald found

  a place for religion in this process and so much so that it was imperative that laws be

  imprinted with the sacred character of divinity. Human justice, he believed, could

  not be separated from divine justice. Civil legislation needed to draw inspiration

  not from the pagan world (as had been the case with the philosophes) but from the

  eternal principles of Christianity, from the Ten Commandments. Men, in short,

  should be taught what they owed to God and to each other before being told what

  they can do to others. One day, Bonald believed, governments––enlightened by

  their own errors and mistakes––would realize that these long-established truths

  formed the foundation of all social and moral order. ‘Therefore’, Bonald concluded,

  ‘the sovereign legislator must be placed at the head of all legislation and we must get

  this philosophical truth, the most philosophical of truths, into our minds: that the

  revolution began with a declaration of the rights of man and that it will only finish

  with a declaration of the rights of God.’79

  Among supporters of the monarchical cause, therefore, the language of rights was

  progressively abandoned as support for a moderate constitutional settlement hard-

  ened into outright opposition towards the Republic and all its ills. At first suspected

  only of undue abstraction, the language of rights was progressively superseded by a

  harsher discourse which associated talk of rights with a rampant egalitarianism and

  which came increasingly to hold the entire natural law philosophy of the eighteenth

  century responsible not just for the disorder of the Revolution itself but also for

  the Terror. Faced with the political, moral, and social disintegration of France,

  for the theorists of counter-revolution there was no room for compromise with such

  an atheistic doctrine.

  I V

  It was not only from the perspective of the post-revolutionary resurgence of

  Catholic thought that the Déclaration des Droits de l’Homme et du Citoyen was

  subject to censure and disparagement. The logic and epistemological bases of

  natural law were treated with growing scepticism among philosophers as the

  eighteenth century progressed and, if its rhetoric continued to enjoy considerable

  popular esteem, it was utilitarianism––in the shape, for example, of Helvétius’s De

  l’Esprit––that came to occupy a central place in Enlightenment philosophical and

  political thinking. Certain writers, most notably Condorcet, had little difficulty in

  recognizing the threat posed to rights by utilitarian principles but others––attempt-

  ing to rescue what perhaps could not be saved––showed little hesitation in attempt-

  ing to break out of the straitjacket imposed by David Hume’s distinction between

  fact and value and, as a consequence, in deriving rights from the basic needs and

  79 Bonald, Législation Primitive, 1133.

  48

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  capacities of human nature. However, the tension between the potentially compet-

  ing claims of utility and rights remained and would be cruelly exposed in the decade

  after 1789. The primary locations of this debate were the salon of Helvétius’s widow

  at Auteuil and the Institut National des Sciences et des Arts, founded in 1795.

  Its principal participants were the group of writers who were to be known as the

  Idéologues.80

  In the case of Condorcet, a refusal to endorse a utilitarian logic which

  countenanced the transgression of the rights of the minority in the interests of

  the ‘greater number’, and therefore condemned society to ‘perpetual war’, brought

  with it the deployment of a sophisticated probabilistic analysis of voting behaviour

  designed to demonstrate that a pure democracy of the type envisaged by Rousseau

  was appropriate neither to contemporary France nor indeed to any situation where

  the existence of the unenlightened many posed a threat to the emergence of a

  rational politics.81 It was this that explained his opposition to the Jacobin constitu-

  tion of 1793. Nevertheless, it was recognized by many that the principle of the

  equality of rights, when grounded in a conception of the natural equality of man,

  appeared to offer the possibility, however unwelcome, of demands for greater

  political and (even) economic equality. For example, Condorcet had no logical

  alternative but to argue that political rights should be extended to include women.

  In an important text entitled Sur l’admission des femmes au droit de cité. 3 juillet

  179082 he drew the following conclusions: ‘the rights of men result solely from the

  fact that they are sensate beings, capable of acquiring moral ideas and of reasoning

  about these ideas. Thus women, having the same capacities, necessarily have the

  same rights.’83 The only serious grounds for denying political rights to women

  were those of social and public ‘utility’ but this, Condorcet contended, was the

  language of tyrants and justified slavery. ‘It was’, he argued, ‘in the name of public

  utility that the Bastille was filled, that books were censored.’ Such motives could

  never outweigh the claims of ‘un véritable droit’.

  It was this conundrum that was faced by those prepared to conflate a discussion of

  rights and utility. An early illustration of this is provided by the two best-known texts

  of the Comte de Volney: La Loi naturelle ou principes physiques de la morale, published

  in 1789,84 and Les Ruines ou Méditations sur les Révolutions des Empires, published in

  1793.85 Nature, Volney argued, had given to all men ‘the same organs, the same

  sensations, and the same needs’.86 From this it followed that all men had the same

  rights to the use of their possessions and that all men had an equal right to life and to

  the means which sustained it. The good therefore was defined in terms of ‘everything

  80 Welch, Liberty and Utility, and Martin S. Staum, Minerva’s Message: Stab
ilizing the French

  Revolution (Montreal and Kingston, 1996). See also B. W. Head, Ideology and Social Science: Destutt

  de Tracy and French Liberalism (Dordrecht, 1985); Emmet Kennedy, A Philosophe in the Age of

  Revolution: Destutt de Tracy and the Origins of Ideology (Philadelphia, 1978); and François Azouvi

  (ed.), L’Institution de la raison: La Révolution culturelle des idéologues (1992).

  81 See Baker, Condorcet, 225–48.

  82 Œuvres de Condorcet, x. 119–30.

  83 Ibid. 122.

  84 Volney, Œuvres complètes (1821), i. 251–310.

  85 Ibid. 1–245.

  86 Ibid. 102.

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  49

  which tends to preserve and to perfect man’ and the bad as ‘everything which tends to

  destroy or diminish man’. Yet, when confronting himself with the possibility that

  these ‘eternal and immutable laws’ might engender a descent into anarchy––France,

  he readily acknowledged, was a country ‘divided into two unequal and contrasting

  bodies’, the people and the privileged––he showed no hesitation in resorting to a

  series of soothing maxims designed to alleviate any such fears. ‘We are men’, Volney

  has the people remark, ‘and experience has taught us well that each one of us tends to

  rule and to enjoy life at the expense of others.’87 In Volney’s opinion, therefore, the

  people would accept with equanimity that the task of establishing ‘the true principles

  of morality and reason’ was best left to ‘hommes choisis’, to experts. In similar

  fashion, Volney believed that the rules of behaviour which would operate in the new

  society could be reduced to one overriding principle: ‘the simplicity of manners’.

  This he defined as ‘the narrowing of needs and desires to what is truly useful to

  the existence of the citizen and his family: that is, the man of simple tastes has few

  needs and lives happily with little’.88 Discord within society, Volney contended,

  thereby disclosing the inspiration behind the entire educational programme of the

  Idéologues, derived not from the order of things themselves but from the manner in

  which they were ‘perceived’ and ‘judged’. We had to be taught to see things as they

  really were.

  Nevertheless, among those who came to gravitate around the salon at Auteuil the

  emphasis in the first place fell resolutely upon the defence of the rights of man and

  if this was to an extent the result of philosophical confusion it did not prevent

  Destutt de Tracy, arguably the most important of the Idéologues, from formulating

  the very first hostile response to Edmund Burke’s diatribes against the Revolution

  or from deflecting criticism of the Déclaration des Droits de l’Homme et du

  Citoyen in the process. Burke, Destutt de Tracy argued, was not only wrong to

  suggest that France would have been better advised to follow the English constitu-

  tional model but, he continued, ‘if our declaration of rights is a load of nonsense,

  our conduct is an excellent commentary on it. It was at the moment when America

  busied herself with nonsense that she became invincible to the whole force of

  England.’89 The real problems for the Idéologues, however, began as the demands of

  the Parisian populace, the sans-culottes, became ever more strident and as France

  lurched towards Jacobin dictatorship.

  P. C. F. Daunou, for example, began his Essai sur la constitution90 with a biting

  and detailed attack upon the Déclaration des Droits de l’Homme et du Citoyen.

  ‘We have drawn up’, he wrote, ‘seventeen articles whose incoherence, ambiguity

  and lack of precision have served as a prelude to injustice, to the feebleness of our

  laws, to the constitutional humiliation of our people, and to our long-drawn-out

  disasters’.91 The source of these errors, he argued, lay in what he described as the

  ‘synthetic method’ used to formulate the original declaration, a method which had

  87 Ibid. 100.

  88 Ibid., p. 305.

  89 Antoine-Louis-Claude Destutt de Tracy, M. de Tracy à M. Burke (1790).

  90 Pierre-Claude-François Daunou, Essai sur la constitution (1793).

  91 Ibid. 2.

  50

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  led subsequently to the continued merging of natural, civil, and political rights into

  one amorphous and confused block. To formulate a new, more complete, and

  better structured declaration, Daunou argued, ‘we ought to go back to the origin of

  our moral ideas: that is, to the first sensation which showed us a man unnecessarily

  preventing another from satisfying his needs’.92 On this account, it was out of the

  relationships between men––principally those of injury and oppression––that

  natural rights were born. Moreover these rights––detailed by Daunou as the natural

  rights to liberty, equality, and the resistance to oppression––themselves quickly

  gave rise to a set of civil rights––essentially the rights to security and to property––

  that had their origin in a ‘social contract’ associating ‘the force of all for the

  maintenance of the rights of everyone’. Finally, political rights emerged as each of

  the contractees realized that they should ‘combine in order to establish the means to

  guarantee natural and civil rights’.93 The outline declaration that followed––in

  which it was made explicitly clear that strict equality in the ownership of property

  was an impossibility––was intended to refute criticism that such principles were a

  matter of ‘pure speculation, inapplicable to the current condition of both morals

  and society’.

  The significance of this argument was at least two-fold. By taking as his starting

  point the analysis of the relationship between men and thereby dismissing ‘the

  figure of a primordial man enclosed in the solitude of his needs’, Daunou effectively

  shifted the emphasis away from the natural to the social.94 The threat to the

  established order posed by the concept of a state of nature where all were equal,

  in other words, was diminished. Second, in purely political terms, it provided

  Daunou with the grounds for arguing that the exercise of executive power should

  be neither abused nor weak. ‘The civil right to property’, Daunou commented, in

  Rémarques sur le plan proposé par le comité du salut publique,95 ‘is the only possible

  tie between twenty-five million individuals joined together in an indivisible repub-

  lic: all other systems will create anarchy.’ If he acknowledged the dangers that

  flowed from an excessively unequal distribution of wealth, Daunou ceased to refer

  to the right to resist oppression, preferring to talk instead of preserving ‘the right to

  petition and the right to assemble, peacefully and without arms’.

  Another, altogether more sophisticated, attempt to deprive the language of rights

  of its radical dimensions was made by Daunou’s fellow Idéologue, the journalist and

  politician Pierre-Louis Roederer.96 Writing in De la philosophie moderne et de la part

  qu’elle a eue à la Révolution française,97 Roederer devoted nearly fifty pages to

  92 Pierre-Claude-François Daunou, Essai sur la constitution (1793) 7.

  93 Ibid.

  94 Gauchet, La Révolution des droits de l’homme, 282.

  95 Pierre-C
laude-François Daunou, Rémarques sur le plan proposé par le comité du salut public

  (1793), 5.

  96 See Kenneth Margerison, P-L. Roederer: Political Thought and Practice during the French

  Revolution (Philadelphia, 1983). See also Ruth Scurr, ‘Social Equality in Pierre-Louis Roederer’s

  Interpretation of the Modern Republic, 1793’, History of European Ideas, 26 (2000), 105–26, and

  ‘Pierre-Louis Roederer and the Debate on the Forms of Government in Revolutionary France’,

  Political Studies, 52 (2004), 251–68.

  97 Pierre-Louis Roederer, De la philosophie moderne et de la part qu’elle a eue à la Révolution française

  (1799).

  Rights, Liberty, and Equality

  51

  challenging the argument advanced by Rivarol that the new ‘analytical’ philosophy

  was predominantly destructive. ‘If ’, he wrote, ‘the Revolution was not a necessary

  product of philosophy, the Terror was less a necessary product of the Revolution

  and even less the fruit of philosophy itself.’98 In so doing he denied Rivarol’s charge

  that the declaration of 1789 was a ‘criminal’ and ‘impossible’ text, contending

  that to affirm rights was also (implicitly) to impose duties and that the text had

  recognized the limits to liberty in a ‘social state’. He further argued that neither the

  constitution of 1791 nor that of 1793 had asserted that ‘man was naturally equal

  without restriction’. Nor, he claimed, had any philosophe endorsed a doctrine of

  ‘natural equality’.

  Despite these assurances, in the Cours d’organisation sociale,99 written some six

  years earlier, Roederer had been obliged to go to great lengths to show that property

  must be included amongst the natural rights of man and therefore must not be

  restricted. Starting from what he described as our ‘anatomical and physiological’

  knowledge of men, Roederer had little difficulty in arguing that morality in general

  had its origin in man’s desire to satisfy his needs and therefore that the primary

  guarantors of subsistence––namely, liberty, security, and property––must be cate-

  gorized as ‘an abridgement of the rights of man’.100 The point was that these rights

  pre-dated what Roederer described as ‘le pacte social’, indeed that the very purpose

  of such a pact was to ensure the protection of rights deemed to be inherent to the

 

‹ Prev