Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 16
Revolution and the Republic Page 16

by Jeremy Jennings


  Absolutism, Representation, Constitution

  71

  provided more effective protection for all the members of a community than

  divided power.’ The point is a straightforward one. The Anglo-American tradition

  has taken it to be axiomatic both that power must be checked and divided if it is not

  to be abused and that the protection of the rights of the individual by the State is of

  fundamental importance. It is only thus that freedom can be said to exist. Yet, as

  Nannerl points out, in France from the sixteenth century until well into the

  eighteenth century, the first of these key conditions for a liberal polity was ‘rejected

  outright’ whilst the second was ‘commonly ignored’. This made sense in the

  context of a society which was both divided and parcellized and in which not

  only was a strong State necessary to secure civil peace but also where that State––in

  the form of an absolute monarchy––came to embody claims to represent the

  generality, as opposed to the partiality and particularity, of society’s interests. As

  Ellen Meiksins Wood has commented: ‘The king embodied the public aspect of the

  State as against the private character of his subjects.’18 In this situation the central

  political question was that of rendering royal power ‘more truly public’, of cleansing

  it of particularistic influences, of ensuring that la monarchie absolue did not descend

  into la monarchie arbitraire.19 The moral prescription––as Bossuet made plain in

  his Politique tirée des propres paroles de l’Ecriture Sainte, first published in 1709––was

  that the divinely ordained monarch should work for the greater good of the kingdom.

  If kings were not subject to the penalties of the laws, they must themselves be just and

  owed to the people the example of justice-keeping.20

  This is not the place to explore the vexed question of whether the absolute

  monarchy in pre-revolutionary France was a myth or a reality.21 Research over the

  last thirty years or more has served to indicate that it was at best a tendency or

  direction towards which policy moved rather than an established form of govern-

  ment.22 Only royalist propaganda taken at face value has led us to believe that the

  crown triumphed over all its opponents.23 It was, however, the propaganda

  generated by the crown that did so much to establish the widely and long-held

  belief that there could exist a single superior and sovereign will capable of expressing

  the permanent and common interests of the entire nation, despite the fact that

  the monarchy had little possibility of actually imposing that will. Here we might

  take one glorious (and enduring) example: the gardens of the Palace of Versailles.

  Summarizing the scale of this magnificent achievement, Ian Thompson writes that

  it ‘was packed with messages about the military might of France, about technologi-

  cal progress, the superiority of French art over Italian, the commanding reach of the

  18 Ellen Meiksins Wood, ‘The State and Popular Sovereignty in French Political Thought:

  A Genealogy of Rousseau’s “General Will”’, History of Political Thought, 4 (1983), 287.

  19 Pierre Rosanvallon has made a similar point. See ‘Political Rationalism and Democracy’, in

  Samuel Moyn (ed.), Pierre Rosanvallon: Democracy Past and Future (New York, 2006), 127–8.

  20 See Jacques-Benigne Bossuet, Politics Drawn from the Very Words of Holy Scripture, tr. Patrick

  Riley (Cambridge, 1999), 85. According to Bossuet there was ‘nothing more distinct’ than the

  distinction between absolute and arbitrary government.

  21 See Fanny Cosandey and Robert Descimon, L’Absolutisme en France (2002).

  22 See Regnheld Hatton (ed.), Louis XIV and Absolutism (London, 1976) and David Parker, The

  Making of French Absolutism (London, 1983).

  23 Roger Mettam, Power and Faction in Louis XIV’s France (Oxford, 1980).

  72

  Absolutism, Representation, Constitution

  Most Christian King and the futility of insurrection. Even the little fleet that bobbed

  around the Grand Canal was an effective piece of propaganda about France’s status as

  a maritime power.’24 At the time of the death of Louis XIV in 1715 France might

  have been ‘impoverished, vanquished [and] riddled with internal dissent’,25 but there

  still remained a powerful conviction that la monarchie absolue received justification as

  an appropriate response to the conditions of urban and religious unrest of the recent

  past. Furthermore, the fear of a return to the wars of religion occupied a central place

  in the minds and memories of the French people.26 Thus, the absolute monarchy

  figured as a mechanism designed to enhance, rather than to diminish, the security

  and liberty of the individual.

  Such a view received its most coherent theoretical justification in the writings of

  Jean Bodin, and especially in Les six livres de la République, first published in

  1576.27 In Bodin’s celebrated phrase, sovereignty was an ‘absolute and perpetual

  power’. It was not only supreme but also indivisible. The source and the exercise of

  sovereignty were deemed to have the same location: the monarch alone. As such,

  Bodin’s theory was designed to counter all claims––and principally those voiced by

  Protestants––to the effect that sovereignty had its origins amongst the people and

  therefore that a right to rebellion existed.

  A version of this argument is visible in the response of Bossuet to the views

  advanced by Pierre Jurieu in his Lettres Pastorales of 1689.28 Exiled in Holland, the

  Calvinist Jurieu contended that it had been the people who, out of prudence, had

  created the sovereign and who therefore were the source of sovereignty. Accepting

  that the people themselves could not exercise sovereignty, it was nevertheless the

  sovereignty of the people that was the source of all authority: it was the people who

  made kings. The authority of the sovereign over the people, thus, derived from ‘a

  mutual pact’ and one that specified that while the sovereign had the right to punish

  the guilty he had no right to punish the innocent. ‘Never’, Jurieu wrote, ‘did the

  people have the intention of giving to the sovereign the power to abuse its laws, its

  liberty, its religion and its life.’ As the scriptures taught us, there was no legitimate

  ‘power without limits’, nor therefore was there such a thing as ‘passive obedience

  without limits’. Accordingly the removal of James II from the throne of England

  and his replacement by William of Orange had been legitimate because James II

  had broken his pact with the people.

  Bossuet’s reply first doubted the biblical accuracy of Jurieu’s account: the

  Jews had not lived for three centuries without a sovereign. Rather, obedience to

  the sovereign was in accordance with the precepts of Jesus Christ and had

  subsequently been confirmed by the scriptures, by tradition, and by the example

  24 Ian Thompson, The Sun King’s Garden: Louis XIV, André Le Nôtre and the Creation of the Gardens

  of Versailles (London, 2006), 285.

  25 Mettam, Power and Faction, 319.

  26 David A. Bell, The Cult of the Nation: Inventing Nationalism, 1680–1800 (Cambridge, Mass.,

  2001), 30–2.

  27 See Jean Bodin, On Sovereignty (Cambridge, 1992).

 
28 Pierre Jurieu, Lettres Pastorales XVI––XVII––XVIII (1689), suivies de la réponse de Bossuet

  Cinquième Avertissement aux protestants (1690) (Caen, 1991).

  Absolutism, Representation, Constitution

  73

  of the early Church. Far from being the ‘sovereign power’, therefore, the people

  had no legitimate mechanism––‘neither arms, nor assemblies, nor any authority

  whatsoever’––through which it could oppose the monarch. Only the Protes-

  tants, Bossuet argued, had thought otherwise, and all had failed to recognize

  that ‘anarchy’ and ‘bloody civil wars’ would be the consequences of their sinful

  doctrines. If ‘Cromwell and his fanatics’ were the ‘true authors of the crime’

  against the person of Charles I, their justification lay in those maxims asserting

  ‘the absolute sovereignty of the people over kings [and] the primordial contract

  between peoples and kings’. Jurieu had specifically denied this charge, arguing

  that it was not ‘legitimate to oppose kings to the point of cutting off their head’,

  but Bossuet observed that he had no grounds for doing so and no grounds for

  placing limitations upon the power of the people, no matter how unreasonable

  their actions. Moreover, Bossuet pointed out, Jurieu had singularly failed to

  offer anything like a convincing definition of either the people or its powers.

  Those who ‘flattered the people’, he concluded, were invariably ‘the henchmen

  of tyranny’.29 Much of what was to occur during the summer of 1789 and its

  immediate aftermath was prefigured in this exchange of views. Even at that late

  date, many were those who believed that the interests of the people and those of

  the crown could not be separated and that the sole sovereign authority resided in

  the person of the monarch.

  The same disposition also brought with it a pervasive distrust of those interme-

  diary powers and voluntary associations that later French liberals were to consider as

  one of the all-important guarantees of English liberty. Estates, parlements, the

  Church, and other similar bodies were seen as feudal remnants voicing private

  (and therefore selfish) corporate concerns and even when defended by Montesquieu

  came to be conflated with aristocratic power and what was known as the thèse

  nobiliaire. This was not all. To quote Ellen Meiksins Wood again: ‘Even in more

  radical attacks on royal absolutism, the public will of the State was not generally

  opposed, as in England, by asserting private interests or individual rights against it.

  Nor was the common good redefined as a public interest essentially constituted by

  private interests.’30 Rather what tended to happen was that the precise location of

  the source and principle of generality was transferred away from the monarch

  towards some other institution deemed capable of expressing its superior claims.

  The Huguenot constitutionalists, for example, simply shifted its setting from the

  king to the public councils of the people, thereby confronting ‘absolutism on its

  own terms by stressing the particularity of the monarch’. The charge, in other

  words, was not so much that the sovereign might have said ‘L’État, c’est moi’ but

  that he acted as if he believed that ‘L’État, c’est à moi’.31

  29 See Lucien Jaume, La Liberté et la loi: Les Origines philosophiques du libéralisme (2000), 37–93.

  30 Meiksins Wood, ‘The State and Popular Sovereignty’, 309.

  31 Herbert H. Rowan, ‘L’État, c’est à moi: Louis XIV and the State’, French Historical Studies,

  2 (1961–2), 83–98.

  74

  Absolutism, Representation, Constitution

  The conclusion drawn by Keohane is unambiguous. ‘Many of Rousseau’s

  authoritarian passages’, she writes, ‘were restatements of hoary arguments in French

  absolutist thought.’32 Nowhere was this more evident than with the concept of

  ‘la volonté générale’. It came replete with the injunction not only that sovereignty

  should be neither divided nor restricted but also with the call for the total alienation

  of each individual and of his rights to the community. Rousseau’s innovation lay

  not with the concept of sovereignty but in his denial that the sovereign will could be

  indefinitely identified with one individual. By doing this he opened up the way for

  the all-important redescription of sovereignty as the will of all those citizens who

  made up the membership of the political body. In this fashion was the theory of

  absolute monarchy transformed into the radical alternative of absolute popular

  sovereignty. The misunderstanding has been to believe that in either case a concern

  for the liberty of the individual was absent. Moreover, this discloses one of the most

  important elements of continuity between pre- and post-revolutionary France. ‘It is

  no exaggeration to say’, Lucien Jaume writes, ‘that the totality of revolutionary

  debate up to Bonaparte is marked by the doctrine of the indivisibility of sovereignty,

  a concept which the Revolution did not forge but which it had taken up from the

  monarchy.’33

  I I

  During the summer and into the autumn of 1789 virtually no one challenged the

  principle of monarchy. As Madame de Staël was later to comment, the desire was to

  secure a ‘monarchie tempérée’.34 Nevertheless, a dramatic transfer of power took

  place. The Estates-General, convened at Versailles in early May, initially sat, in line

  with tradition, as three separate orders. The Third Estate, nominally representing

  95 per cent of the population, soon proposed that the three Estates should conduct

  their deliberations as one body. Initially rebuffed, they pressed on alone, on 17 June

  giving themselves the title of National Assembly. Three days later, finding them-

  selves locked out of the building where they met, the deputies of the Third Estate

  reassembled at a nearby tennis court and swore not to dissolve themselves before

  France had been given a new constitution. In the following days, they were joined

  by the majority of the members of the clergy and then, on 25 June, by forty-seven

  representatives of the nobility. The new body was to vote not by order but by head.

  On 7 July it gave itself a new name: the National Constituent Assembly, thereby

  indicating its clear intention to provide France with a new constitution and

  effectively transferring the location of sovereignty to itself. A week later, the people

  of Paris, fearing military repression, stormed the Bastille. Having lost control of

  32 Keohane, Philosophy and the State, 442.

  33 Lucien Jaume, Échec au Libéralisme: Les Jacobins et l’État (1990), 15. See also Lucien Jaume,

  ‘Citoyenneté et souveraineté: Le Poids de l’absolutisme’, in Baker, Political Culture, 515–34.

  34 Anne-Louise Germaine de Staël, Des circonstances actuelles qui peuvent terminer la révolution et des

  principes qui doivent fonder la république en France (1979), 160.

  Absolutism, Representation, Constitution

  75

  events, Louis XVI had no alternative but to concede. His fate was now in the hands

  of those who claimed to lead the Revolution.35

  As was so often the case, it was the Abbé Sieyès who most clearly articulated the

  logic that informed the new situation. His pamphlet, Qu’est-
ce que le Tiers Etat?,

  published in January 1789, clearly set out the grounds for this transfer of sover-

  eignty. For Sieyès, the only legitimate source of power derived from the nation: all

  other forms were contrary to the ‘common interest’. ‘The nation’, he proclaimed,

  ‘existed before everything else; it is the origin of everything. Its will is always legal; it

  is the law itself.’36 And for Sieyès the nation was constituted by the Third Estate

  alone, for the simple reason that it, rather than the aristocracy and the clergy,

  laboured to produce the wealth upon which the nation rested. To that extent, the

  Third Estate was ‘Everything’: it was ‘a complete nation’. It followed from this,

  Sieyès argued, that the ‘representatives’ of the Third Estate were the ‘rightful

  depositaries of the national will’ and that they could, therefore, ‘without error,

  speak in the name of the entire nation’.37

  These arguments were advanced before the Third Estate had established its

  political ascendancy. Once it had done so, the challenge became that of translating

  these claims into constitutional principles and practices.38 Most obviously, this was

  in part quickly achieved through the Déclaration des Droits de l’Homme et du

  Citoyen, Article 3 of which declared that sovereignty resided in the nation whilst

  Article 6 specified that the law was an expression of the general will. No mention

  was made of the king. If this much could be agreed upon relatively easily, there was

  markedly less unanimity when the deputies addressed the issue of the composition

  of the National Assembly and the related question of the legitimacy or otherwise of

  the royal veto.39

  In the first instance, the intellectual leadership of the Revolution fell to the

  group known as the monarchiens and loosely clustered around the figure of Jean-

  Joseph Mounier. Their dominance was short-lived (Mounier himself resigned

  his seat in October 1789 and returned home to Grenoble) but during the

  summer of that year the documents they produced as members of the constitu-

  tional committee provided the focus of debate.40 Starting from a definition of

  liberty as the absence of interference and its need for protection through law, the

  monarchiens not only dismissed the idea that the classical world could figure as a

 

‹ Prev