Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 43
Revolution and the Republic Page 43

by Jeremy Jennings

10 L’Idée républicaine en France (1982), 16–18.

  11 Patrick Weil, How to be French: Nationality in the Making since 1789 (Durham, NC, 2008),

  11–13.

  12 See Robert Shaver, ‘Paris and Patriotism’, History of Political Thought, 12 (1991), 627–46.

  13 See Michel Delon, ‘Nation’, in Pascal Ory (ed.), Nouvelle histoire des idées politiques (1987),

  127–35; Maurice Cranston, ‘Sovereignty of the Nation’, in Colin Lucas (ed.), The Political Culture of

  the French Revolution (Oxford, 1988), 97–104; Pierre Nora, ‘Nation’, in François Furet and Mona

  Ozouf (eds.), Dictionnaire critique de la Révolution française (1988), 801–11; J.-R. Suratteau, ‘Nation/

  Nationalité’, in Albert Soboul (ed.), Dictionnaire historique de la Révolution française (1989), 781–3.

  Universalism, the Nation, and Defeat

  201

  the conflict between Britain and France as a duel between two royal houses or

  between two different religions, presented it as ‘a battle between irreconcilable

  nations’. ‘[S]upporters of the French crown’, he writes, ‘sought to mobilize the

  nation as a whole against an enemy nation’. We cannot fully know the extent to

  which this induced spontaneous expressions of patriotic enthusiasm but we can

  accept Bell’s conclusion that through such propaganda the French came increas-

  ingly to see themselves as a nation and one ‘which could mobilize itself, instead of

  simply flocking behind a king’.14

  More influential still was what Bell characterizes as ‘the politics of patriotism’.15

  On this account there were three decisive moments in the development of national

  sentiment: the regency of Philippe d’Orléans (1715–22); the parlementaire crisis in

  the years 1748–54; and, finally, the so-called Maupeou revolution of 1771. By

  1760, Bell argues, the concept of the nation had become central to French political

  culture, but political competition still existed between rival claims to have originally

  embodied the nation, to be its modern descendants, and to speak in its name. The

  contenders are well known: the monarch (clothed increasingly in patriotic garb);

  the aristocracy (never slow to articulate the view that it was from them, and in the

  distant Frankish past, that kings derived their original legitimacy); and the parle-

  ments (once recalled by Turgot, more than ever determined to cast themselves in

  the role of the patriot party). Yet in each case the language spoken revealed a desire

  to return to earlier, less troubled, legal arrangements and to put an end to the

  growing political clamour. This could not be done, and increasingly therefore the

  concept of the nation acted as a vehicle for political claims and as a source of

  legitimacy. As Bell makes abundantly clear, the key moment came in September

  1788 when the parlement of Paris ruled that the Estates-General should meet in its

  traditional form, the three Estates sitting and voting separately. With this, aristoc-

  racy joined royal despotism as the enemy, and a new definition of the nation had

  quickly to be found.

  This definition was provided with breathtaking audacity by the Abbé Sieyès.16

  Henceforth, the Third Estate was taken to be ‘a complete nation’, with the

  aristocracy in particular cast out unceremoniously and without regret from the

  body politic. Next, the representatives of the Third Estate formalized their political

  ascendancy not merely by redescribing themselves as ‘the representatives of the

  French people’ but also by declaring themselves to be members of the National

  Assembly. The nation thus had been given unambiguous political expression and

  henceforth it was acknowledged that ‘the principle of all sovereignty resides in the

  nation’.

  14 David A. Bell, The Cult of the Nation: Inventing Nationalism 1680–1800 (Cambridge, Mass.,

  2001), 78–106.

  15 Ibid. 50–77.

  16 See above p. 75. See also Charles-Philippe-Toussaint Guiraudet, Qu’est-ce que la nation et qu’est-

  ce que la France? (1991). The emphasis in the text fell on overcoming the ‘imagined divisions’ which

  separated the French as individuals from one another.

  202

  Universalism, the Nation, and Defeat

  In this way were disclosed two ideas of immense significance and importance.17

  The first was that the nation was a self-conscious political construct, the fruit and

  product of an immense act of (revolutionary) will. The second, and one soon

  to be made graphically explicit, was that nations possessed the right to self-

  determination. The latter in particular denoted a complete break with traditional

  international practices, although it had been presaged by the slightly earlier Ameri-

  can example. Both were made manifest at the Fête de la Fédération, celebrated on

  the Champ de Mars a year to the day after the storming of the Bastille and

  orchestrated in such a way as to shroud the nation in a mystical halo. As Pierre

  Nora has written, ‘[t]he festival expressed the disappearance of internal frontiers,

  the abolition of regional disparities, the excitement associated with an act of mutual

  consent submitting a united France to an authority freely accepted’.18 Just as

  dramatically, these same ideas were applied to those parts of the territory that had

  been annexed to France under the monarchy. In the so-called serment de Strasbourg

  the delegates of the national guards of Alsace, Lorraine, and Franche-Comté

  affirmed the determination of these territories and their inhabitants to be a part

  of the French nation. In similar vein, in May 1790 it was declared that ‘the French

  nation renounces the intention to undertake any war whose goal is that of conquest

  and it will never employ its arms against the liberty of a people’.

  One of the most striking aspects of the Revolution of 1789 was that from the

  outset its participants believed that their actions were of international significance

  and that what was at stake was a set of universal values. One example of this

  universalistic mentality was the assumption that France was not born to follow the

  example of others but was rather the example that should be followed. As Tocque-

  ville was later to comment: ‘It was not a question of taking lessons, but of

  furnishing new examples.’19 Another feature was the manner in which it was

  assumed that the truths being proclaimed were applicable to the whole of human-

  kind. To cite Tocqueville again: ‘there was no Frenchman who did not believe he

  had in his hands, not the destiny of his country, but the very future of the

  species’.20 Seen from the political hothouses of Paris, the whole world was watching

  and listening as revolutionary events unfolded. So too, a reborn French nation,

  shorn of privilege, was thought capable of infinite enlargement and of embracing

  the inhabitants of the earth. France was ‘la patrie de l’humanité’.

  Given this, there are few more fascinating tales than the manner in which the

  universalistic aspirations of the Revolution were replaced by the denunciation

  of the foreigner and by what Mona Ozouf has termed a ‘fraternité xenophobe’.21

  If, at the outset, all those who accepted the principles of the Revolution were

  17 See Jacques Godechot, La Grande Nation: L’Expansion révolutionnaire de la France
dans le monde

  de 1789 à 1799 (1956).

  18 Nora, ‘Nation’, 806.

  19 Alexis de Tocqueville, The Old Regime and the Revolution (Chicago, 2001), ii. 67.

  20 Ibid.

  21 Mona Ozouf, ‘L’Idée républicain et l’interprétation du passé national’, Annales, 53 (1998),

  1074–87. See also Sophie Wahnich, L’Impossible citoyen: L’Étranger dans le discours de la Révolution

  française (1997).

  Universalism, the Nation, and Defeat

  203

  welcomed as citizens, the rhetoric of fraternity and hospitality quickly changed

  into that of enmity as these very same foreigners—seven of whom, including

  Joseph Priestley and Thomas Paine, were elected to the Convention—were recast

  as traitors and false friends. In part this can be explained by the yawning gap that

  existed between the dream of national unity and the reality of a deeply divided

  and heterogeneous country. The foreigner was no more—and no less—an object

  of suspicion than the aristocrat and the priest. Next, the very logic of universalism

  played its part. To harbour doubts about the claims of French liberty was to place

  oneself in the position of being an enemy of the French nation and therefore, by

  extension, of humanity. The foreigner could thus very easily be equated with

  tyranny. To this could then be added the demands of political necessity. From

  1792 onwards France, and the Revolution, was at war with her neighbours and

  this perilous situation, in an atmosphere where rumours of plots and conspiracies

  were rife, called for no half measures.

  Most importantly, the retreat from the idealistic posture of universal embrace

  followed inevitably from the realization that the nation as envisaged by the

  revolutionaries had still to be made. From Sieyès onwards, the very definition of

  the nation had a logic of inclusion and exclusion written into it and the boundaries

  of the nation were drawn within and not beyond French territory. But it was

  undoubtedly the discourse of political virtue voiced so enthusiastically by the

  Jacobins that did most to separate the foreigner from the erstwhile country of

  humanity. If Louis XVI, in the words of Saint-Just, could be cast (fatally) as ‘a

  foreigner living among us’,22 the same could be said all too easily of the non-French

  nationals who became the subject of relentless rebuke and attack in Robespierre’s

  speeches. As Sophie Wahnich comments: for the Jacobins, ‘the victory of liberty

  would be signified by the perfect transparency of the public space . . . the struggle

  engaged upon was a struggle against all forms of opacity which might act as an

  obstacle to the actions of revolutionary government’.23 The foreigner was necessar-

  ily opaque, the mask-wearer par excellence, and therefore, unwittingly or not, a

  traitor, a plotter, and an enemy of the patrie.24 As will be readily surmised, of these

  foreign enemies the English were given pride of place as the enemies of the entire

  human race (a sentiment later continued by Jules Michelet amongst many others).

  Echoing the royalist propaganda of the Seven Years War almost word for word, ‘the

  people of this debased island’ were again compared to the brigands and thieves of

  Carthage.

  Why France, having made known its pacific intentions, actually went to war is a

  question not easily answered. The Girondins seem mistakenly to have believed that

  this was their best way of keeping hold of the reins of power. Robespierre for one

  opposed this policy, fearing that it would lead to military despotism and the

  22 ‘Discours sur le jugement de Louis XVI’, in Saint-Just, Œuvres complètes (2004), 475–84.

  23 Wahnich, L’Impossible citoyen, 155.

  24 The concept of patrie is closely related to that of nation. It was, if anything, even vaguer in

  meaning, both before and during the Revolution. In the Furet and Ozouf Dictionnaire critique de la

  Révolution there is no separate entry for patrie.

  204

  Universalism, the Nation, and Defeat

  overthrow of the constitution.25 Military success, however, brought its own pro-

  blems. What was to be done with the newly conquered territories? If the annexa-

  tions of Nice, Avignon, and even Savoy (each of which formally requested

  incorporation into France) were relatively straightforward, the same could not be

  said of Belgium. Here there was deep unease and indecision, not least amongst the

  members of the Convention. Help however was at hand from the exiled Prussian

  noble and (soon to be guillotined) apostle of universal fraternity, Anacharsis Cloots,

  who justified the annexation of the left bank of the Rhine on the grounds that ‘this

  river is the natural boundary of the Gauls’. It was this theme that was taken up and

  given clear expression in the famous remarks of Danton before the Convention on

  30 January 1793. The limits of the French republic, he announced, were ‘indicated

  by nature. We will reach them at the four corners of the horizon: at the Rhine, the

  Oceans and the Alps.’26 Two weeks later Carnot added the Pyrenees to the list. Was

  this a novel doctrine or was it, as the nineteenth-century historians Augustin

  Thierry and Henri Martin were to argue, a reworking of the traditional policy of

  the French monarchy from Richelieu onwards?27 It matters relatively little because,

  whatever the truth of the matter, it was now accepted that the principle of

  geographical determinism could supplement or even supersede that of the right

  to self-determination.

  Appeals to local consent continued to be made and were duly met by the

  minority determined to lend their support to the principles of the Revolution,

  but henceforth the notion that peoples were being liberated from oppression served

  only as a fiction and a pretext for national self-interest. What, moreover, was to be

  done when French arms brought victories beyond even these natural boundaries?

  Could these territories too not be brought within the confines of the universal

  republic or did such geographical expansion (as the frequently cited example of

  classical Rome appeared to show) entail the grave risk of subverting the Republic

  itself? Prudence alone dictated that the first course should not be followed, and

  thus, under the guise of respect for the sovereignty of other peoples, an additional

  variety of annexation was invented: that of ‘sister republics’.28 All countries con-

  quered by France were to be given new republican constitutions, and were in effect

  to exist as French protectorates.29 This was the fate that first befell Holland in 1795

  and much of the Italian peninsula in the next two to three years. ‘The system of

  “sister republics”’, Jacques Godechot writes, ‘had the advantage, not merely of

  flattering the national pride as well as the revolutionary pride of the French by

  extending the influence of the new France, but it afforded undeniable strategic

  benefits . . . and economic advantages.’30

  25 See Robespierre, Œuvres complètes, iv. Le Défenseur de la Constitution (1939).

  26 Quoted in Wahnich, L’Impossible citoyen, 340.

  27 See Daniel Nordman, ‘La Frontière’, in Vincent Duclert and Christophe Prochasson (eds.),

  Dictionnaire critique de la République (2002), 499–505.

 
; 28 See Jean-Louis Harouel, Les Républiques sœurs (1997).

  29 See Lucien Jaume (ed.), Les Déclarations des droits de l’homme (1989), 313–18.

  30 Godechot, La Grande nation, 83.

  Universalism, the Nation, and Defeat

  205

  The last remnants of universalistic fervour were removed following the fall of the

  Jacobins and the installation of the Thermidorian republic. This continued under

  the Directory, when for the first time the notion of the ‘constitutional limits’ of

  France was invoked in order to justify French expansion beyond its pre-revolution-

  ary borders. Indeed, to the objectives of attaining natural frontiers and establishing

  sister republics, the Directory added one new priority: economic and maritime

  expansion in the Mediterranean. This was a policy that would shortly see the

  departure of Napoleon Bonaparte for Egypt.

  Bonaparte’s oriental adventure was very far from being a complete success but

  one crushing military victory at Aboukir over disorganized Ottoman opponents

  and some astute propaganda turned it into a personal triumph for the young

  general. It was soldiers, rather than civilians, who were now the heroes of the

  new Republic. From 1792 onwards, in fact, the levée en masse, conscription by

  another name, had produced an army numbering as many as 800,000 men and this

  not only turned the aristocratic army of the past into an anachronism, but also

  changed the very way that war was fought, putting the entire resources of the nation

  at the army’s disposal. From this it appeared to follow naturally that, when

  politicians proved themselves incapable of managing affairs, recourse should be

  made to one of those who had led the national army to glory. In this way the First

  Republic came to an end.

  Gone now was to be any reference to the right of nations to self-determination.

  Far from granting them independence, whenever practicable, Napoleon integrated

  conquered territories into metropolitan France, producing at its most extensive in

  1811 a France consisting of 130 départements, stretching from the mouth of the

  Elbe and Flanders in the north and to Rome and Tuscany in the south. Where

  integration was not feasible, Napoleon set up what amounted to vassal states,

  frequently headed by some undistinguished member of his own extended family

 

‹ Prev