Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 58
Revolution and the Republic Page 58

by Jeremy Jennings


  the new Second Republic,181 but he quickly came to view the resurgence of neo-

  Jacobinism with apprehension. The election of Louis Napoleon as president

  diminished his hopes further and following the coup d’état of December 1851 he,

  like many fellow republicans, was forced to flee the country. In his often lonely exile

  his obsession now became that of reversing the dishonour inflicted upon his

  country and of understanding the failure of democracy in France.182 This, for

  example, was evident in such diverse works as his verse drama Les Esclaves (1853)

  and his anti-Napoleonic Histoire de la campagne de 1815 (1862). However, it was

  most clearly and controversially visible in La Révolution, first published in 1865.183

  In contrast to the earlier Le Christianisme et la Révolution française, this was a full-

  blown history of the Revolution, taking its reader from the collapse of the ancien

  régime to the rise to power of Napoleon Bonaparte: but, in essence, it built upon the

  themes of the earlier volume. The question posed was the following: why had so

  many immense efforts and sacrifices produced such meagre results?184 The answer

  again was that France, unlike England, had not preceded its political revolution

  with a religious revolution.185 ‘With regard to the moral order’, Quinet wrote, ‘the

  success of this Revolution was absolutely impossible, since its leaders, while

  completely overturning the Middle Ages, preserved the ideal of the Middle Ages

  with regard to ideas.’ ‘In the midst of massive upheaval’, he went on, ‘everything

  changed except the mind of man, which was systematically left a captive of the

  past.’186 From its very first step, therefore, the Revolution revealed that it had feet

  of clay.

  178 Quinet’s mother was a Protestant and he himself acknowledged the beneficial consequences of

  the Reformation.

  179 Ibid. 406.

  180 Ibid. 385.

  181 See the speech made by Quinet on 8 Mar. 1848 before the students of the Sorbonne: Hermione

  Quinet, Cinquante Ans d’amitié, 158–60.

  182 See e.g. Edgar Quinet, Le Réveil d’un grand peuple (1869).

  183 Quinet, La Révolution (1865; references to the 1987 edn.).

  184 Ibid. 65.

  185 Ibid. 168.

  186 Ibid. 186.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  273

  What followed was a very different account of the Revolution from anything that

  had been penned before. Quinet’s view was that the people had risen up in

  rebellion against what he termed the ‘byzantine and imperial’ traditions of the

  absolutist monarchy but that these had been preserved by the Revolution. ‘The

  classical, official, disciplined, literary republic of Robespierre’, Quinet wrote, ‘could

  understand nothing of this popular movement, since no model for it could be

  found in either Rousseau or Lycurgus.’187 So, Quinet disapproved of the Revolu-

  tion’s destruction of provincial liberties, arguing that this had left the entire country

  at the mercy of the capital.188 This led ineluctably to the central question explored

  by Quinet: what was the nature of the Terror and how could it be explained? His

  answer provoked the eruption of one of the most bitter controversies among

  republicans during the nineteenth century.

  Quinet’s political sympathies clearly lay with the Girondins.189 ‘Because they

  wanted to arrive at liberty through liberty’, he wrote, ‘they rejected the heritage of

  old France in its entirety.’190 With their arrest, he postulated, it was resolved that

  henceforth the ‘regeneration of France’ would not be attained by a new route but

  ‘by the method of the ancien régime: tyranny’. ‘To abolish liberty under the pretext

  that it would be established much later’, Quinet wrote, ‘is the guiding thread of

  French history. It was also that of the Revolution.’191 The Jacobins, on this view,

  set out to force the people to be free and, to that end, all opposition, all dissent, all

  disagreement, became a crime punishable by death. They believed that there was

  virtue in the spilling of an enemy’s blood and that a golden age would arise from the

  scaffold. But only the goal pursued by the Jacobins was new. ‘As for the means of

  constraint and authority’, Quinet argued, ‘it is what we have always had for

  centuries.’192 So, circumstances did not explain the Terror, nor could success

  legitimize it. The Terror was rooted in historical precedent and was but ‘the fatal

  legacy’ of France’s absolutist tradition and, as such, was a product of the Revolution

  itself. In no other revolution, Quinet contended, had leaders acted in a manner so

  contrary to the goals they pursued.

  According to Quinet, therefore, the Terror had its initial cause in the ‘irrecon-

  cilable’ clash between old and new France. This sentiment of ‘absolute incompati-

  bility’ pushed people towards a state of frenzy, leading both sides to intensify and

  heighten their actions. Threatened and provoked, with each day the Revolution

  gained in audacity, engendering ‘a state of exaltation’ among the French nation.

  Robespierre and his colleagues simply changed what was a passing ‘accident’ into

  ‘a permanent state of affairs’. Coldly and impassively, they transformed a condition

  of anger and despair into a principle and system of government and turned sponta-

  neous fury into a cold and calculated instrument of salvation. The whole edifice

  rested upon another ‘sad’ legacy of earlier oppression: contempt for the individual.193

  Moreover, the exercise of absolute power during the Revolution had exactly the

  187 Ibid. 475.

  188 Ibid. 140.

  189 Ibid. 426–8.

  190 Ibid. 373.

  191 Ibid. 389.

  192 Ibid. 373.

  193 Ibid. 497–501.

  274

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  same impact as it had had under the monarchy. Fear corrupted and abased people.

  Night descended upon their intellects.

  Quinet’s conclusion was that in each of the barbarities of 1793 could be seen a

  reappearance of the mentality of the Middle Ages. Salvation, according to this logic,

  would be attained if only a few perfidious and malign individuals were eradicated

  and this was as true for the Revolution as it had been when Louis XIV had sent out

  troops against the Huguenots. Similarly, Quinet saw that, if it was easy to inaugu-

  rate government by terror, it was immeasurably more difficult to bring it to an end.

  Driven forward by the illusion of necessity it would march on until only the

  executioners themselves remained. The circle would then be closed and we

  would have returned to our point of departure: servitude.194

  This, in Quinet’s view, was precisely what had occurred. In 1789, the French

  had risen up against three forms of oppression: absolute power, Roman Catholi-

  cism, and administrative centralization. Once the storm had passed, all three

  reappeared: absolute power with Napoleon as First Consul; Roman Catholicism

  with the signing of the Concordat in 1801; and administrative centralization in the

  shape of the Napoleonic state. Rephrased by Quinet in the idiom of nineteenth-

  century French historiography, this meant that, if the French Revolution h
ad freed

  the nation from its original conquest by the Franks, the Gauls remained enslaved to

  the Romans and to the Caesarean traditions of emperor and pope.195

  What sense could be made of this ‘bloody labyrinth’? The Revolution, Quinet

  concluded, had bequeathed a ‘disastrous heritage’ to France and to French democracy.

  At its heart was a belief in ‘the necessity of dictatorship’ as the indispensable step

  towards the establishment of liberty. The revolutionaries, he observed, were past

  masters in the art of death. The result was that all that remained of the Revolution

  was ‘an ideal, a flag and a few words about justice which float above the abyss’.196

  Whoever wished to live freely therefore had to renounce the joys of exacting vengeance

  and to dare to acknowledge that the proper response to tyranny was not more tyranny.

  Yet, as Quinet sadly recognized, whether openly or in disguise, ‘this has not ceased to

  reappear as the supreme expedient’.197

  It was a mark of the originality and power of Quinet’s La Révolution that, not

  only did its first edition sell out in six days, but that it was met by howls of protest

  from those associated with the ‘democratic party’.198 The tone of these protests was

  best captured in the series of articles written by Alphonse Peyrat, editor of L’Avenir

  national. Quinet’s two volumes, Peyrat argued, were a ‘satire’ of the Revolution:

  they were ‘anti-historical and anti-revolutionary’, a mixture of prejudice and

  philosophical pretension, bizarre comparisons and surprising banalities. Taken as

  a whole, they dishonoured the Revolution. More substantially, Peyrat unapologet-

  ically reaffirmed the pro-Jacobin orthodoxy. The Jacobins had not sought to raise

  terror into a system of government. Dictatorship had been imposed upon

  the Revolution by necessity and circumstance. Through their prodigious efforts,

  194 Quinet, La Révolution (1865; references to the 1987 edn.), 534.

  195 Ibid. 729.

  196 Ibid. 730.

  197 Ibid. 599.

  198 Key texts are republ. in Furet, La Gauche et la révolution au XIXe siècle, 134–383.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  275

  the Jacobins had saved the Revolution. For good measure, Peyrat condemned the

  Girondins for being a bunch of unprincipled chancers and pointed out that

  Quinet’s book had been taken up by royalists.199

  The polemic rumbled on over the winter of 1865, with liberals and moderate

  republicans, including Jules Ferry and Emile Ollivier, voicing their support for

  Quinet. But it came to a head in February 1866 when the exiled Louis Blanc

  published a long article in Le Temps effectively charging Quinet with giving succour

  to the forces of counter-revolution.200 After ‘eighteen years of research, study and

  meditation’,201 Blanc had finished his own twelve-volume history of the Revolu-

  tion in 1862 and could not but take offence at what he saw as a summary dismissal

  of all that he had long believed in and cherished. Above all, he took exception to

  Quinet’s allegation that the Jacobins had raised terror into a system of government.

  ‘The Terror’, he responded, ‘was not a system; it was something very different, an

  immense misfortune born out of extraordinary dangers.’202 Nor was it true that the

  Terror had its origins in the minds of a few individuals. ‘Prepared by centuries of

  oppression, provoked by frightful attacks and spurred on by the dangers of a titanic

  struggle’, Blanc continued, ‘the Terror came out of the bowels of history.’203 No

  one had wanted dictatorship less than Robespierre. Moreover, the killing had not

  stopped with his fall. It had simply been replaced by the ‘white Terror’.

  Blanc’s argument was that the ‘idea of dictatorship’ was ‘directly opposed to the

  spirit of the Revolution’. ‘Let us not say’, he concluded, ‘that the results were

  disproportionate to the sacrifices made when the results were the intellectual conquests

  that have made us what we are and a France saved.’204 At first Quinet did not respond.

  Then, for the fifth edition of La Révolution published in 1867, he wrote a lengthy

  new preface, lambasting his detractors for presuming to dictate what could be

  said about the Revolution and contrasting this with his own ‘scientific’ method.205

  On the substantive point of disagreement he was not prepared to compromise. It

  was not necessity that had produced ‘the system’ of the Terror but ‘false ideas’.206

  Furthermore, critics such as Blanc failed to appreciate what was distinctive about

  the violence of the Terror. ‘Do you not see’, he asked, ‘that one of the special

  characteristics of the French Revolution is that the revolutionaries were put to death

  by revolutionaries, the Jacobins by Jacobins, the Montagnards by Montagnards?’207

  To accept the logic of the Terror was to accept the logic of ‘eradication’ and such

  a logic, Quinet affirmed, was ‘illogical, illusory and necessarily sterile’. From this,

  he wrote, ‘I have been able to conclude that there was a complete incompatibility

  between the means of 93 and the end pursued, between the barbarities of the Jacobins

  and the philosophy of the eighteenth century, between theory and practice.’208

  One casualty of the publication of Quinet’s La Révolution was his close friend-

  ship with Michelet. This might appear odd, given that Michelet had shown little

  199 Ibid. 139–230. These essays were subsequently republ. in Peyrat, La Révolution et le livre de

  M. Quinet (1866).

  200 Furet, La Gauche et la révolution, 289–305.

  201 Ibid. 289.

  202 Ibid. 291.

  203 Ibid. 293.

  204 Ibid. 305.

  205 Ibid. 308–37.

  206 Ibid. 332.

  207 Ibid. 327.

  208 Ibid. 321.

  276

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  sympathy for the priestly Robespierre and even less liking for the Jacobin ‘machine’.

  Indeed, for the 1869 edition of his Histoire de la Révolution française he added a new

  preface to volume v entitled simply ‘The Tyrant’.209 Similarly, in his preface to the

  1868 edition he directed his fire primarily at Louis Blanc, referring to him as ‘half-

  Christian in the manner of Rousseau and Robespierre’.210 Yet Michelet had

  counselled against mistaking the Terror for the Revolution, never quite stating

  the dichotomy between 1789 and 1793 in such stark terms, and he had no respect

  whatsoever for the Girondins. Importantly, Michelet and Quinet differed funda-

  mentally about the place and role of religion in the Revolution. Hurt pride and

  professional jealousy also played a part. If only briefly, everyone was reading Quinet

  and Michelet was out of the limelight. Whatever the cause, the two men were never

  to regain the intellectual intimacy they had shared in the past.

  I V

  In 1862 Quinet took up his copy of Alexis de Tocqueville’s L’Ancien Régime et la

  Révolution for a second time and began to annotate it line by line.211 Despite their

  political and personal differences, the two men shared one central intellectual

  preoccupation. Both believed passionately in liberty and both understood that

  the durability of French traditions of despotism worked against it
s realization. If

  this meant that each of them was resolute in his opposition to the Second Empire, it

  likewise demanded an explanation of the causes of what was indubitably the failure

  of the Revolution to effect a real break with the past. Tocqueville’s answer to this

  conundrum might have had less rhetorical force than that provided by Quinet but

  it was no less compelling and many have subsequently found it to be extremely

  convincing. When published in 1856 L’Ancien Régime et la Révolution proved to be

  at least as successful with the reading public as De la Démocratie en Amérique had

  been and, to Tocqueville’s evident delight, quickly went through several editions. It

  was however a text suffused with pessimism.

  The precise moment at which Tocqueville resolved to write a study of the

  Revolution can be dated to December 1850 when he was in Sorrento recuperating

  from a bout of illness, but it took him several more years before he decided upon

  the form and content of his inquiry.212 As his correspondence with Gustave de

  Beaumont reveals, it was only at the point of publication and after much discussion

  209 Michelet, Histoire de la Révolution française, ii. 349–65.

  210 Ibid. i. 47.

  211 See Furet, La Gauche et la révolution, 41–58.

  212 On the writing of L’Ancien Régime et la Révolution see Gannett, Tocqueville Unveiled. Among

  the other texts that might be consulted see François Furet and Françoise Mélonio, ‘Introduction’, to

  Alexis de Tocqueville, The Old Regime and the Revolution, i. The Complete Text (Chicago: 1998), 1–79;

  André Jardin, Tocqueville: A Biography (Baltimore, Md., 1998), 481–507; Robert T. Gannett, jun.,

  ‘The Shifting Puzzles of Tocqueville’s the Old Regime and the Revolution’, in Cheryl Welch (ed.), The

  Cambridge Companion to Tocqueville (Cambridge, 2006), 188–215; Brogan, Alexis de Tocqueville

  (2006), 525–84.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  277

  that an appropriate title was decided upon.213 These hesitations are easy to

  understand. Unlike Michelet and Quinet, Tocqueville was a man who had spent

  most of his adult life as a politician and journalist. If he had attended the famous

  lectures on European civilization given by Guizot in the 1820s and now counted

  François Mignet among his personal acquaintances, he was not an academic

 

‹ Prev