Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 87
Revolution and the Republic Page 87

by Jeremy Jennings


  Histoire des gauches en France (2004), ii. 207.

  410

  Insurrection, Utopianism, and Socialism

  programme’ of reforms to be pursued by socialists,90 but the broader question

  raised by these developments was whether the socialist movement could be indif-

  ferent to the fate of the Republic. Those who answered in the negative did so in the

  belief that the Republic remained the most favourable institutional structure within

  which socialists could pursue their desired reforms. In Millerand’s formulation this

  meant that the Republic was the political form of socialism, whilst socialism was the

  economic and social expression of the Republic. For others, the entry of a socialist

  into government meant accepting that, for all their doubts about the bourgeois

  republic, socialism was an offspring of the traditions of republican democracy. The

  harder part of the equation was that of embracing the daily reality of reformism and

  of cooperation with the bourgeoisie. Worst of all, and as the most astute observers

  saw clearly, the yawning divide between revolutionary rhetoric and reformist

  practice ran the risk of reducing socialism to nothing more than meaningless

  gestures and verbalism.

  These divisions and debates were not without an important international di-

  mension.91 From the late 1860s onwards, the congresses of both the First and

  Second Internationals frequently revealed the deep schism that existed over the

  respective claims of political and economic action and these tensions were only to

  be accentuated by the rise to prominence (above all, in Germany) of Marxism

  during the final decades of the century. Matters came to a head when Eduard

  Bernstein began to challenge the very foundations of historical materialism. Begin-

  ning with a series of articles published in Die Neue Zeit in 1896, he plunged

  German Marxism into the crisis of revisionism, arguing that the historical necessity

  of socialism could not be derived from the evolution of capitalism. At bottom, this

  was a difference of opinion about the process and mechanics of revolution. If

  democracy was the end, Bernstein believed, so also it should be the means. The

  strategy of the dictatorship of the proletariat had to be abandoned. In the French

  case, it also denoted a deep-seated disagreement about the nature of the Revolution.

  The fractured heritage of 1789 was again to come into play.

  I I I

  To begin our analysis of what is often referred to as the ‘second left’,92 we might

  turn our attention to Charles Fourier’s Théorie des Quatre Mouvements, first

  published in 1808.93 With its accounts of copulating planets, the sea tasting of

  lemonade, and the nine degrees of cuckoldry, this is undoubtedly one of the

  90 See Millerand, Le Socialisme réformiste français (1903), 19–35.

  91 See Emmanuel Jousse, Réviser le marxisme? D’Edouard Bernstein à Albert Thomas, 1896–1914

  (2007).

  92 See Vincent Duclert, ‘La Deuxième gauche’, in Becker and Candar, Histoire des gauches, ii.

  175–89.

  93 See Œuvres Complètes de Charles Fourier (1846), i. This text is available in English tr. as The

  Theory of the Four Movements (Cambridge, 1996). See Jonathan Beecher, Charles Fourier: The Visionary

  and his World (Berkeley, Calif., 1986).

  Insurrection, Utopianism, and Socialism

  411

  strangest books ever written. Beneath these numerous oddities, however, lay an

  audacious attempt to refashion the principles of social organization following what

  Fourier described unequivocally as ‘the catastrophe of 1793’. The Revolution,

  according to Fourier, was a direct consequence of the ‘systematic thoughtlessness’

  of the moral and political sciences. The philosophes, he wrote, had been like

  ‘children playing with fireworks amidst barrels of gunpowder’.94 They had for-

  gotten that ‘liberty is illusory if the common people lack wealth’, that equality was a

  ‘chimera’ where the right to work did not exist, and that there could be no

  ‘fraternity between sybarites steeped in refinements and our coarse, hungry peasants

  covered in rags’.95 The result had been ‘civilized chaos, barbarism, and savagery’.

  In response, Fourier’s ambition was to sketch out the details of an ‘Ordre

  Sociétaire’ that would permit the transition ‘from incoherence to social combina-

  tion’, ‘universal harmony’, and ‘a state of great happiness’. This he did through the

  formulation of a highly complex theory of ‘passionate attraction and repulsion’.

  Hitherto, Fourier argued, the passions had been seen as sources of discord: his

  theory, in contrast, would ‘appeal to the passions common to everybody’ and its

  success would be guaranteed through ‘the allurements of profit and sensual plea-

  sure’.96 There is no need to analyse Fourier’s taxonomy of what he took to be

  our ‘luxurious’, ‘affective’, and ‘distributive’ passions, nor to dissect his classifica-

  tion of the 810 personality types which derived from it: the point was that Fourier

  believed that it was a mistake to repress the passions. This explains why he allotted

  such a central place to ‘amorous freedom’ and what he termed ‘combined gastron-

  omy’. If, as Fourier believed, sensual pleasure was the primary and immutable

  source of human activity, the trick was so to arrange society that it should be

  maximized. Exquisite food and a rich diet of sexual partners would secure social

  harmony.

  Fourier was not much read until around 1829, the year in which he published Le

  Nouveau Monde industriel et sociétaire.97 If the basic principle of Fourier’s argument

  remained unchanged—‘it will be proven’, he wrote, ‘that true happiness consists in

  the enjoyment of great riches and an infinite variety of pleasures’98—the emphasis

  upon ‘amorous corporation’ was much less evident. ‘The vice of our so-called

  regenerators’, Fourier wrote, ‘is to condemn this or that abuse instead of condemn-

  ing civilization in its entirety, for the latter is nothing but a vicious circle of

  abuses.’99 The remedy to these vices, he continued, lay ‘in the discovery of a

  mechanism of industrial attraction’ which would transform work into a pleasure

  and guarantee a minimum income to all members of the community. Labour was

  no longer to be regarded as a duty but as an enjoyable and satisfying activity

  structured in such a way as to ensure that all necessary tasks would be accomplished

  without coercion.

  94 Œuvres Complètes de Charles Fourier, 284.

  95 Jonathan Beecher and Richard Bienvenu (eds.), The Utopian Vision of Charles Fourier (London,

  1972), 160–2.

  96 Œuvres Complètes de Charles Fourier, 8.

  97 Ibid. vi.

  98 Ibid., p. xiv.

  99 Ibid., p. xv.

  412

  Insurrection, Utopianism, and Socialism

  Needless to say, Fourier provided a detailed breakdown of how this would be

  done—work was to be of infinite variety, of short duration, and carried out in clean

  surroundings, for example—but the fundamental principle underlying the whole

  operation was arguably best discerned in the proposal that children—the ‘little

  hordes’—should perform such unsavoury tasks as
cleaning the drains and shifting

  manure.100 The trick, in other words, was to align the job with the natural

  propensities of those involved (in this case, the ‘love of dirt’ dear to so many pre-

  adolescents). Crucially, such work was to be undertaken in the new material

  conditions provided by the phalange, an association of approximately 1,600 in-

  dividuals—twice the number of identified personality types—the physical and

  organizational arrangements of which Fourier planned down to the last detail.

  For the most part these aspects of Fourier’s argument, intriguing as they are, can be

  passed over but we should perhaps note that members were to live in a condition of

  what was described as ‘graduated inequality’ and that remuneration was to be made

  according to a complicated formula taking into account labour performed, capital

  invested, and talent displayed. Placed in a rural setting, at the centre of the phalange

  would be a vast Palace of Harmony or phalanstère. The architectural drawings used

  to adorn various Fourierist publications indicate that this magnificent edifice,

  replete with dining rooms, libraries, workshops, ballrooms, private apartments,

  and street gallery, would bear a marked resemblance to the palaces of Versailles and

  the Louvre.

  The organizational difficulties arising from such arrangements are presumably

  self-evident. It is, therefore, all the more important to understand that Fourier

  believed his proposals to be far from utopian. Indeed, he insisted that he had

  revealed the principles of a new ‘social science’ and that his discoveries bore

  comparison with Newton’s theory of gravitational attraction. By the same token

  he was unfailingly critical of what he saw as the impractical schemes put forward by

  Robert Owen and the various Saint-Simonian sects.101 Moreover, it was as a

  doctrine which located society’s ills within the social system that Fourier’s ideas

  were taken up by his growing number of followers.102

  Fourier’s big breakthrough came in 1831 when the schism within the Saint-

  Simonian movement led to the conversion of sizeable numbers of its members to

  Fourierism. The following year saw the creation of a weekly journal, Le Phalanstère,

  edited jointly by Jules Lechevalier, Victor Considérant, and Fourier himself. That

  year also saw the first concerted attempt to create a model community, located not

  far from Paris. Early optimism quickly gave way to personal acrimony and the

  disciples distanced themselves more and more from their troublesome master. As a

  consequence Fourierism was gradually purged of many of its wilder eccentricities.

  This was especially so after Fourier’s death in 1837. Le Phalanstère was superseded

  by Considérant’s La Phalange: Journal de la Science Sociale and by the daily La

  100 Œuvres Complètes de Charles Fourier, 207.

  101 See e.g. Fourier’s Pièges et charlatanisme des sectes Saint-Simon et Owen (1831).

  102 See Jonathan Beecher, Victor Considerant and the Rise and Fall of French Romantic Socialism

  (Berkeley, Calif., 2001).

  Insurrection, Utopianism, and Socialism

  413

  Démocratie pacifique in 1843. Although never as large as that achieved by Cabet’s Le

  Populaire, their audience was substantial, and the École Sociétaire (as Fourierism

  was now known) secured a sizeable following across France into the 1840s.

  Ultimately what emerged from this process of transition was a vague form of

  democratic socialism much removed from Fourier’s original intentions. A place was

  found for the State—in the form of a Ministry of Progress—and Considérant’s

  vision of the future was noticeably more egalitarian than that of his former master.

  It was, moreover, a socialism which (echoing the familiar refrain of the time) saw

  itself as ‘the social realization of Christianity’. The commitment to a ‘peaceful

  democracy’ also entailed a willingness to engage in electoral politics.103 Here it was

  Considérant, now the effective leader of the movement, who led the way. Having

  first stood for election in 1839, he became a member of the National Assembly in

  1848 and there championed both the right to work and female suffrage. Although

  deeply unsettled by the popular violence of 1848–9, he was arrested in June 1849

  and, like so many other radicals, went into Belgian exile. Four years later, following

  a visit to the United States in 1852, Considérant published Au Texas,104 a detailed

  report and programme for the establishment of an experimental colony on Ameri-

  can soil. Buoyed up by the enthusiastic reception his ideas received, on 15 January

  1855 he set sail again for the New World, from whence he did not return until

  1869. Predictably, the new settlement on the banks of the Trinity River near Dallas

  was rapidly to fall prey to feuds and factions, with the result that a discouraged and

  disenchanted Considérant spent the remainder of his American sojourn as a farmer

  near San Antonio.

  This sorry end to a tale fuelled by such exalted expectations should not blind

  us to what was of intellectual significance in the Fourierist movement. Fourier

  and those who followed him saw that the profound ills afflicting society derived

  not from any defects intrinsic to human beings or from causes that had political

  solutions but from evils inherent to a system of industrial organization char-

  acterized by disorder, oppression, and deceit. They concluded that abstract

  political rights were of little import when placed beside claims to a right to

  work and to a basic minimum subsistence and that violent revolution and

  insurrection was the route least likely to engender a ‘perfect social state’ resting

  upon the ‘sacred principles of justice, liberty, and humanity’. Rather than relying

  upon what Considérant portrayed as ‘the eruption of a popular volcano’, they

  saw themselves as ‘social engineers’ intent on securing ‘universal union’ through

  the progressive application of the principles of voluntary association. From

  this standpoint, it became possible to conceive of a new set of social arrange-

  ments where everyone would work ‘freely and passionately’ for the general

  good and where everyone would identify that good with his or her own personal

  103 In addition to the various Fourierist journals already cited, see Victor Considérant, Bases de la

  Politique Positive (1842); Exposition abrégée du système phalanstérien de Fourier (1845); Principes du

  socialisme: manifeste de la démocratie au XIXe siècle (1847); and Le Socialisme devant le vieux monde

  (1848).

  104 Considérant, Au Texas (1854).

  414

  Insurrection, Utopianism, and Socialism

  well-being. It was these truths that were repeated incessantly in Fourierist tracts

  and periodicals, in lectures and in speeches, and in the press, but which also

  resolutely escaped practical application.

  Considérant was prepared to accept that his conception of socialism was anti-

  revolutionary, if not counter-revolutionary, and he went to great lengths to dem-

  onstrate that socialism should not seek to imitate the bloody and destructive

  example provided by the emancipation of the bourgeoisie in 1789. The violent,

  subversive, and conspiratorial socia
lism of Babeuf, he wrote, would ‘immolate’

  liberty and destroy all personal spontaneity, putting in its place ‘the absolute

  despotism of the law’. The communism of Cabet, he likewise argued, drew

  inspiration from the ‘democratic and political tradition’ of the Revolution and

  accordingly paid little attention to the immense difficulties posed by the organiza-

  tion of society and of collective labour. ‘To invoke fraternity’, Considérant wrote,

  ‘is to resolve nothing.’ As for the ‘errors’ of Louis Blanc, Considérant was of the

  opinion that his distinguished colleague had no other idea than that of ‘imposing

  his egalitarian socialism through the exercise of authority and by surprise’. Relying

  solely upon the instrument of the State, Blanc intended to bring socialism into

  existence by decree.105

  Another fellow socialist for whom Considérant had few kind words was Pierre-

  Joseph Proudhon.106 His ‘portrait of the beast’ revealed a man of paradox who

  delighted in self-contradiction and argument and this, with some justification, has

  remained the view of almost all those who have subsequently read his work.

  ‘I distrust an author’, Proudhon wrote, ‘who pretends to be consistent with himself

  after an interval of twenty-five years.’107 Something of an autodidact, Proudhon

  possessed a capacity to arouse controversy—it was in his Qu’est-ce que la propriété?

  of 1840 that he launched his famous slogan that ‘property is theft’—and he

  continued in this vein until the end of his life in 1865. Never a supporter of

  feminism, it was Proudhon’s opinion that the choice facing women was that of

  being either housewives or courtesans. Like many a radical of his day, he published

  a series of newspapers, of which the most successful was Le Représentant du

  peuple, launched in February 1848. He also spent three years in prison (where he

  both married and fathered a child) and a further four years in exile. He was a man

  of notoriously poor political judgement—believing, for a short time, that Louis

  Napoleon Bonaparte might serve the cause of revolution—and frequent ill-humour.

  Nevertheless, in the hydra-headed world of the socialism of the 1840s not only

  did Proudhon achieve sufficient prominence as to attract the attention (and briefly

 

‹ Prev