Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 111
Revolution and the Republic Page 111

by Jeremy Jennings


  spoke of the need ‘to invent a plurality of ways of being French’. French society,

  in other words, was not on the point of disintegration but it was diverse and what

  threatened it most was ‘the refusal to accord a place to these differences and its

  forced homogenization’. Restated in a later work entitled La Démocratie des

  individus, Roman’s claim was that his ‘moderate multiculturalism’ amounted to a

  move away from a ‘democracy of emancipation’ to a ‘democracy of recognition’.73

  Citizenship, he argued, had to be reconceived as a series of lateral relationships

  70 See Joël Roman, La Démocratie des individus (1998), 17, and Dominique Schnapper and Joël

  Roman, ‘De l’idée républicaine’, Les Cahiers du radicalisme, 1 (1998), 13–28.

  71 Hommes et migrations, 1197 (1996), 18–22.

  72 Esprit, 212 (1995), 145–60.

  73 Roman, La Démocratie, 193–220.

  Conclusion

  525

  between individuals and groups rather than as a vertical relationship between the

  individual and the State.

  What such a républicanisme élargi would look like is not as yet easy to discern but

  there is an acknowledgement that it might entail a substantial recasting of some

  hallowed republican principles. There is in particular an awareness that a tension

  exists between the republican values of liberty and equality and the multicultural

  values of difference and equity.74 The argument of some of the Republic’s more

  severe critics, however, has been that such an accommodation is hardly likely to

  occur. On this view, the ‘abstract universalism’ of French republicanism now serves

  less to integrate than to dehumanize the excluded. Republicanism, it is argued, has

  become only more intransigent and mono-cultural as its capacity to secure adher-

  ence has weakened.

  One of the more bizarre examples of this followed the triumph of France’s

  football team in the 1998 World Cup. The talk was both of a brilliant victory and

  of les bleus as a symbol of la France plurielle and of une France métissée. For many

  political commentators, the triumph of the national team denoted nothing less than

  the success of France’s republican model of integration and a confirmation of its

  continued relevance. For Alain Peyrefitte, editor of the right-wing Le Figaro, it

  showed that, if France was ‘multiracial’, she was certainly not pluriculturelle or

  pluriethnique.75 The left-of-centre Nouvel Observateur pursued a similar line,

  arguing that ‘the team has given back meaning to the French melting-pot’.76 Of

  France’s star player and ‘man of the year’, Zinedine Zidane, it was later to comment

  that he was ‘Algerian by origin, Kabyle by spirit, and 100% French’.77 Nowhere

  was this argument in praise of the French republican model pushed further than

  in the pages of the left-wing newspaper, Libération. Casting Zidane as ‘the icon of

  integration’, immigration specialist Michèle Tribalet could not resist reworking

  the old Franco-German comparison, contrasting a French squad drawn from the

  sons of immigrants to ‘the German team, with their fair complexion and blond

  hair, which did not contain a single young player of Turkish origin’. Best of all was

  Laurent Joffrin’s editorial in the same issue. Ernest Renan, he told his readers, had

  been right: the nation was truly ‘un referendum de tous les matchs’!78

  Six weeks later Le Monde published an article entitled ‘Républicains, n’ayons plus

  peur!’. It was signed by the elite of France’s left-intelligentsia: Régis Debray, Max

  Gallo, Jacques Julliard, Blandine Kriegel, Olivier Mongin, Mona Ozouf, Anicet Le

  Pors, and Paul Thibaud.79 Here the republican credo was deployed in precisely the

  74 See e.g. Françoise Gaspard and Farhad Khosrokhavar, Le Foulard et la République (1995); Michel

  Wieviorka (ed.), Une société fragmentée: Le Multiculturalisme à l’épreuve (1995); Jean-Loup Amselle,

  Vers un multiculturalisme français: L’Empire de la coutume (1996); Khosrokhavar, L’Islam des jeunes

  (1997); Alain Touraine, Pourrons-nous vivre ensemble? Égaux et différents (1997); Wieviorka, ‘Le

  Multiculturalisme’, Les Cahiers du Cevipof, 20 (1998), 104–29; Wieviorka, ‘Le Multiculturalisme,

  est-il la réponse?’, Cahiers internationaux de sociologie, 105 (1998), 113–51.

  75 Le Figaro (13 July 1998).

  76 Le Nouvel Observateur (16 July 1998).

  77 Le Nouvel Observateur (24 Dec. 1998).

  78 Libération (10 July 1998).

  79 Le Monde (4 Sept. 1998).

  526

  Conclusion

  fashion most feared by its critics: as a threat used to intimidate those indecent

  enough not to adhere to the canons of republican citizenship. All the old republican

  shibboleths were repackaged and recast in a forthright attack upon what was taken

  to be the prevailing incivisme of daily life in France. The latent anger was easily seen

  in such statements as the following: ‘“Violence at school” begins with the use of

  familiar speech (tutoiement) towards teachers, listening to Walkmans in the school

  yard, and the wearing of deliberately provocative clothing in the classroom.’ The

  authors therefore demanded a re-establishment of ‘discipline’ and a reawakening of

  ‘responsibility’. Among whom? France’s politicians for sure; her public servants too;

  but principally the young who engaged in criminal activity, badly behaved pupils

  who did not take their studies seriously, France’s international partners who did

  nothing to stop the influx of illegal immigrants, and, of course, the immigrants

  themselves who failed to ‘adhere to the minimum of republican values (in plain

  language: learning to speak and read French); respecting the secularism (laïcité) of

  public spaces’. As critics of the article immediately responded, the Republic now

  appeared to stand for a renewed call to ‘moral order’.

  I V

  One of the central questions of political debate over the last ten years or more,

  therefore, has been whether one can be a good French citizen and clothe oneself in

  the Muslim headscarf or hijab.80 That the answer was in the negative appeared to

  be confirmed when, in March 2004, the French parliament passed a law banning

  the wearing of all religious signs in French schools. Since then France has created a

  minister for immigration and national identity and (at the time of writing) is

  engaged in a government-led debate about what it means to be French. Censure

  has turned away from wearing of the hijab in the school towards those very few

  Muslim women in France who clothe themselves in the burqa. Seen in this light,

  citizenship of the French Republic is tied to a specific culture and to a specific

  national past. To be a citizen is to share a common inheritance and patrimony and

  to feel a strong sense of social solidarity with one’s fellow citizens. The concern is

  that France’s recent immigrants have not been (or cannot be) integrated into the

  values and duties of French citizenship.

  But this in turn begs the question of whether the republican ideal of citizenship,

  forged in the cauldron of the Revolution and consolidated during the nineteenth

  century, is still relevant or workable when faced with the realities of an increasingly
/>   differentiated and diverse society? This issue itself has evoked a variety of responses

  and it needs to be acknowledged that the French state has responded to these

  matters in a far more pragmatic manner than is often recognized. The same can be

  said of the exponents of republican doctrine. Few are those who believe that the

  80 For two recent discussions of these themes see Jeanne-Hélène Kaltenback and Michèle Tribalet,

  La République et l’islam: Entre criante et aveuglement (2002) and Patrick Weil, La République et sa

  diversité: Immigration, intégration, discriminations (2005).

  Conclusion

  527

  republican model, with its emphasis on the free and equal participation of all of

  France’s citizens, needs to be completely abandoned but, putting aside ‘les répub-

  licains purs et durs’, there is evidence to suggest that republicanism can respond to

  the challenge of ethnic and religious diversity in a constructive and innovative way.

  As the recent book by Cécile Laborde amply shows, the question would be that of

  just how far republicanism and the Republic should go on the road to compromise.

  Nevertheless, this unhappy experience has raised some fundamental questions

  that cannot be easily sidestepped by the defenders of republican principles. Is

  French republicanism a non-liberal or even a fundamentally illiberal doctrine?

  Should it be seen as a perverse form of communitarianism where a unitary

  conception of the common good is imposed upon the plurality of national or

  ethnic subgroups? To what extent does the republican conception of citizenship

  embody a truly universalist commitment to justice and emancipation as opposed to

  a particularist articulation of national values? Is the commitment to freedom of

  thought and conscience in a neutral public space sufficient to support and embrace

  cultural diversity or does it amount to a form of discrimination and oppression

  directed against all religious believers? Is it plausible to uphold a strong version of

  the duties of citizenship in a de facto multicultural society? To its critics, the answers

  to these questions suggest that there is little that can be saved from the republican

  project and that, as a political form, the Republic has entered its twilight years.

  And yet republicanism remains the dominant language of politics in today’s

  France and it seems to have lost little of its intellectual potency. Indeed, the vacuum

  created by the demise of more conventional ideologies (most notably Marxism) has

  been filled by a renewed enthusiasm for the republican tradition. Moreover, there is

  little that is substantially new in these criticisms of republican thinking. The long-

  standing and far from uncontroversial charge has been that the aspiration towards

  social unity and equality born of the Revolution of 1789 produced a democracy

  that was unresponsive to the demands of political, religious, and cultural pluralism.

  Likewise the allegation has been that the republican preoccupation with the

  sovereignty of the people has entailed an inability properly to conceptualize the

  nature of representative democracy and, indeed, to understand the activity of

  politics itself. Failing to see (unlike their wiser Anglo-Saxon counterparts) that

  questions about who gets what, when, and how are intrinsic to the politics of

  modern pluralistic societies, the republican tradition, it has been argued, simply

  imagined that that these questions could be deliberated or decreed out of existence.

  The result, according to this negative view, has been a succession of rather

  spectacular political and institutional failures and well-nigh two centuries of insta-

  bility and ideological conflict.

  If this exploration of political ideas in France since the eighteenth century has

  taken a critical eye to these developments, its primary purpose has been to explain

  rather than to criticize or praise. Above all, it has sought to explore the astonishing

  complexity of political thought in this period and to show how political problems

  have been repeatedly addressed through the prisms provided by both the Revolu-

  tion and the Republic. Rather than consensus, there has been continuous debate

  and controversy, with both the events following 1789 and the institutional form of

  528

  Conclusion

  the Republic being subject to unremitting re-examination and redefinition. Nor

  does this analysis always confirm the Jacobin caricature of legend. If France has had

  its believers in the one and indivisible Republic, she has also had those within

  the republican camp who have been acutely aware of the need for her political

  institutions to be in tune with the complex socio-economic and cultural realities

  of the day. For these people in particular, there were no easy answers or solutions to

  the tensions and ambiguities within republican thinking.

  So too we can see that many have stood outside this multifarious republican

  tradition, either as critical observers or as outright critics. To this end, they have

  often clung to an alternative vision of French history and of the French nation. This

  was especially so of Catholic writers in the nineteenth century, but again there

  is need to recognize that this pattern of thinking was by no means exclusively a

  story of religious intransigence before a sinful republic (although this undoubtedly

  existed) nor, for that matter, of republican aggression before an unyielding and

  obdurate Catholic Church.

  Intriguingly, many of those who stood outside the republican tradition or who

  felt that the Republic had failed to fulfil its emancipatory promise turned their gaze

  (often longingly) towards the political traditions and institutions of other countries.

  If one, all-too-familiar, example of this in the twentieth century was an admiration

  for the achievements of the Soviet bloc and other points east, another altogether

  more enduring fascination has been with the ‘Anglo-Saxon’ world. Whether it has

  been England or the United States of America, this preoccupation has run like a

  subterranean current in French political thinking for well over two hundred years.

  Of especial note is the fact that even the most ardent Anglophiles rarely believed

  that France either could or should engage in the wholesale copying of English or

  American institutions. At most there were lessons to be learnt.

  This latter point is worth making because, of recent years, there has been a

  tendency to disparage the achievements of those Walter Bagehot well over a century

  ago described as the ‘poor French’.81 The French republican model has for long

  seemed on the verge of collapse and the French state, ground down by debt and

  budget deficits, has looked perilously close to bankruptcy. In those circumstances,

  France has appeared ill-equipped to meet the challenges of the day, be they those

  associated with the reform of the welfare state, the future development and

  construction of the European Union, or the adaptation of her economy to an age

  of global capitalism. If these difficulties were cruelly exemplified by the presence of

  the Front national’s Jean-Marie Le Pen in the second ballot of the 2002 presidential

  elections, they were only further confirmed in May 2005 when the French

  electorate decis
ively rejected the proposed European constitution in a popular

  referendum. The very public humiliation of losing the 2012 Olympic bid to a

  self-consciously multicultural and market-driven London did little to discourage

  the view that France’s republican culture was decidedly past its sell-by date. France,

  her critics across the Channel averred, needed a good dose of Anglo-American

  81 Quoted in Georgios Varouxakis, Victorian Political Thought on France and the French

  (Houndmills, 2002), 57.

  Conclusion

  529

  market reform and free market liberalism. Indeed, this was a view that France’s new

  president, Nicolas Sarkozy, appeared to accept. In comparison to the grandiose

  designs of his predecessors, his vision of France’s future seemed to be one where

  every Frenchman and Frenchwoman could aspire to ownership of a Rolex watch.

  Of course, all of this looked far more appealing before the world banking crisis

  exposed the frailties of the global economy and plunged Britain and America in

  particular into severe recession. In these difficult and uncertain circumstances, it is

  not easy to assess the resources available to the French republican tradition to

  respond to these new challenges and it would be a mistake to underestimate the

  difficulties involved in the reformulation of republican principles that will un-

  doubtedly be required in the near future and beyond. There is however little reason

  to believe that a republican tradition that has sustained and galvanized political

  thinking in France for over two centuries will not respond. For all the predictions of

  its impending death, it still moves.

  This page intentionally left blank

  Chronology of Modern French History

  1598 Edict of Nantes: issued by King Henri IV, brings an end to the Wars of Religion by

  granting freedom of conscience to Protestants

  1610 Murder of Henri IV

  1643 Accession to the throne of Louis XIV, aged five

  1695 Revocation of the Edict of Nantes by Louis XIV, declaring Protestantism illegal

  1713 The Treaty of Utrecht brings an effective end to the War of the Spanish Succession

  and forbids the union of the French and Spanish thrones

  1598 Accession to the throne of Louis XV

  1756 Beginning of the Seven Years’ War

 

‹ Prev