Nordic Ideology

Home > Other > Nordic Ideology > Page 56
Nordic Ideology Page 56

by Hanzi Freinacht


  I am simplifying to a semi-violent extent, but please bear with me; we are looking at some of the basic principles.

  And from there on, the legal system spirals out of control and begins punishing people very severely and rather arbit­rarily, and from there on the incentives for everyone are to be very careful and suspicious and to collect as much political power as possible. And the way to do that is spying on others, and informing, so that you have more information, more juicy thr­eats to make, and more favors to call. All of these things become more impor­tant for your personal survival (and prosperity) than being an efficient office clerk or entre­preneur. Gain power, don’t rock the boat.

  And from there on, the incentive of the political leadership becomes to hide some of the bad stuff that is going on, because you need the legiti­macy of the system to justify your power; your power being the only protection from being swallowed as the revolution begins to eat its own children in a spying-reporting slugfest. So you need to control the press and other media, which means people receive even less reliable informa­tion to make decisions and regulate their behaviors correctly—which mes­ses up decision-making even more, across the board. And people thus fail to coordinate their actions at a large scale and over longer stretches of time, which means more shortages and errors; which means more incen­tives for corrup­tion.

  And in order to defend the false positive image conjured up by the con­trolled media that people no longer trust, you have to make parades and celebrations and fake display villages—lots of them—so that people will bel­ieve that things are alright and keep up the enthusiasm. And peo­ple will need to show up and be enthused at such occasions in order not to seem suspect, which in turn makes them start to genuinely insist they live in a fantastic society since the least convinced ones will be view­ed with the most suspicion. It is a kind of Stockholm syndrome, by which hostages begin to love and admire their captors.

  This is classical cognitive dissonance: People will genuinely believe things are awesome because it’s too dangerous not to. And this again interferes with any hope of self-corrective feedback cycles. As the histori­an Anne Apple­baum and many other for­eign travelers in the USSR noted, Sov­iet citizens would often—ami­dst obvious drud­ge­ries—em­pha­tically insist that theirs was a superb soc­iety. Gulag survivor Solzhenit­syn descri­bed in his books how people would come to the labor camps and insist upon keeping their beliefs in the benevolence of the Soviet Union, even as they were being beaten, starved and degraded.

  The social dyn­amics of religious cults come to mind. It is as though the comm­unist pro­ject, by its inherent dynamics, drew people into a nation­wide cult: a dyn­amic followed even down to gory details like “cult of per­sonality” and the cult-like, or at least extremely sectarian, organi­zation of Trot­skyist groups arou­nd the world.

  And indeed, what would a society run by, let’s say, the Scientologists look like? We may have an example in present-day North Korea; a surviv­ing spawn of the Soviet Union. The similarities between Scientology and North Korea are strik­ing, even down to the level of com­portments and de­mean­ors displayed by those who harass deviants from the dogma.

  However, once the spell is broken and society collapses, traumas sur­face and abound. Today’s happ­iness research lays its verdict: Post-com­munist soc­ieties are the least hap­py (relative to their levels of econo­mic pros­perity), and the longer a coun­try stayed under communist rule, the less happy the pop­ula­tion.

  Other measures also suffer a special “communist penalty”: lower inter­personal trust, loneliness, cor­r­­uption and poor public health lingering on for dec­ades. In terms of cultural and political prog­ressivity, these soc­ieties also relapse dra­m­at­ically: Poland turns to tradition and Catholicism, East Ger­many gene­rates more than its fair share of neo-nazis, Russia becomes chauv­inist (and born-again Orthodox) and forgets its former communist cosmo­politanism and dreamy gaze at space colonization, China’s new open­ness is only skin deep, still being pro­foundly author­itarian and natio­n­alist—and North Korea becomes a down­right patriarch­al, racist caste syst­em on sur­veill­ance steroids, literally worse than any­thing Or­well could have dreamt up.

  Phew. Where were we? So communism is bad, which has to do with a vicious spiral that grows from an inefficient way of organizing the mar­ket, a case of jammed real-time information processing —rather than any rom­antic notion of a violated “human freedom” or vague general spe­c­ul­ations about the nature of humanity. The violations of human rights flow from this jamming of the information system, from a chronic failure to successfully coor­dinate human behavior in the millions. See you in The Hague, comrade.

  The non-moralistic point is important here—and obvious, in a way. We all have a tendency of casting our beliefs about humanity and society in moral terms. And we tend to flatter ourselves: If only people “realize” that our own beliefs are the correct ones, if they could only bring them­selves to see the true beauty of what we see, then life would be so much better. But sustainable, fair and dynamic societies are not created by the purity of your soul and its habits of self-flattery. Good societies are crea­ted by A) corr­ect analysis, B) smooth inform­ation pro­cessing for the coordina­tion of human agency, C) the dynamic bal­an­­cing of differ­ent powers—and D) the dialectical conflict and mutual interdepen­dence bet­ween diff­erent political interests and ideas.

  These features of a good society can be brought about more or less deli­berately; they emer­­­ge either as the result of planned act­ions, or throu­gh blind processes that occur beyond our understandings (but for which we often like to snatch the credit)—and most often as a strange dance be­tween these two: the deliberate and the stumbled-upon.

  There was really nothing morally “lower” about the communist experi­ment, compared to the ideas of the American Revolution, (or the French Revolution for that matter). If you look at the “foun­ding fathers”, Thomas Jefferson kept slaves, even got one of them pre­g­nant, and Benjamin Fran­k­lin fabricated juicy lies about British atro­ci­ties—writing in the pa­pers under several false names and claiming to have witnessed colorful barb­aric acts committed by Indians, pur­portedly orchestrated by the British, in effect relying on racism. Most of the Declar­ation of Indep­endence is not about human rights and equality, but raging against the cri­mes of the British “tyrant”. After all, this was the writing of fiery revo­lu­tionaries, not human rights activists.

  These guys weren’t necess­arily any “nicer” than Lenin and Trotsky; and certainly not nicer than people like Emma Gold­man or Rosa Luxemburg. They just happened to be on the beat with some ideas and societal devel­op­ments that turned out to be highly competitive, hence leading to relati­vely sus­tainable societal structures. The American ideas of 1776 were sim­ply better aligned with the long-term attractors than the Russian ones in 1917.

  Marx Had the Wrong Meta-Ideology

  Both vers­ions of modern­ity, capitalism and communism, brought great good and great evil. Communism enriches and modernizes society, and it kills lots of people. So does capitalism. But one version still turned out to be preferable to the other and thus won out: capitalism allied with a multi-party system.

  A lot of the weaknesses of the purportedly Marxian societies can be ex­plained by the fact that there weren’t several parties (with minor excep­tions, such as the con­tem­porary Chinese tolerance of small oppos­ition parties). This is a major diff­er­ence to liberal democracy. Even in disord­erly and corrupt Italy, one gov­ernment can always be exchanged for ano­ther. This guarantees rudimentary acc­ount­ability.

  So why were the comm­unist societies one-party systems? Bec­ause the Marxists believed that they alone embodied the meta-ideology ; that they embod­ied the actual, deep structures of how societies evolve and operate. As such you can legitimize the self-organization of society as a whole : The meta-ideo­logy is not any one position within soc­iety, but it con­stitut
es over­arching ideas about the very fabric of society. So Marxism does not compete with liberalism, but with liberal parliamentary demo­cracy itself. It is not just an ideology, but an attempt at a meta-ideology—like liberal democracy. If communism reaches a certain level of influence, it thus wipes out all competing parties.

  If Marxism is a meta-ideology, it makes sense to organize society as a whole within the frame­work of what is viewed as anal­ytically true either way to the comm­unist mind. As such, communism was prone to be built on top of formerly autocratic, pre-democratic societies where it could simply super­sede the earlier form of governance, inheriting the strong state institutions that were not balanced by a strong parliament and divi­sion of powers.

  But this is not unique to communism. When the Am­er­ican Revol­ution took hold, the elites of the early days also worked to keep a one-party syst­em. This however broke down during the early 19th cen­tury when the vote was extended to non-elite groups and there was a rise of populist politics under President Andrew Jackson, with an electoral base in the southern states. All meta-ideologies set the frame­work for soc­iety as a whole, for its very definition of what society is.

  As mentioned, the words “holistic” and “totalita­rian” are in effect the same word . When you have a theory about the whole of soc­iety, it makes sense to relate to it in a way that tries to grasp, and change, the whole of it. To relate to the “whole”, we must relate to the “totality”, even try to steer and navigate it. A challenge presents itself: How can we be hol­istic without falling into the traps of 20th century totali­tarianism?

  In truth, of course, the meta-ideology of modernity turned out to be not communism but rather what I have called Green Social Liberalism, the attractor point modern societies gravitate towards. Not comm­un­­ism, not fas­cism, not the night watchman liber­tarian mini­malist state, not anar­chist communes, not even social demo­cracy (nice try, thou­gh)—but Green Social Liberalism.

  The more modernized a society becomes, the more clearly it manifests Green Social Liberalism, something the Nordic countries have become prime examples of. In countries like Swe­den, all parties in effect have more or less become one version or another of “green social-liberals”.

  Much can be said in the analytical (and moral) defense of Marx, but after all, he did not claim that a huge middle class would grow up through the dynamic inter­relation between private enterprise and public welfare, or that these populations would increasingly adopt individualism and cos­mo­politanism, identity politics and eco­logical awareness as the ecological limitations of soc­iety’s grow­th be­came apparent. That’s just not what he wrote, I’m sorry.

  Marx tried to identify the meta-ideology, to formulate it clearly, so peo­ple could create political movements around it or otherwise navigate the world with its help. He made some important contributions, but he got some of the funda­mental dynamics wrong. Analytical—not moral—mis­takes that nevertheless cost many mill­ions of lives. Oops.

  But still, the very fact that communism was an attempt at a meta-ideo­logy, and that Marx got some important dynamics right (that capitalism is crisis-prone, for example), gave the organization of “The Communist Par­ty” some nearly tran­­­scen­dental qualities in the eyes of its followers; attrac­ting large parts of the 20th century intell­ectuals, most noticeably per­haps in Fran­ce. The party was seen not only as “a party” with some “opin­ions”, but, not unlike the American creed, a kind of manifest dest­iny, of history’s dial­ectics made flesh. That’s of course also what made it so danger­ously seductive, so blinding.

  What we tend to forget, however, is that our current political status quo was created by a similar kind of meta-ideology; that of liberal democracy and the Enlightenment. Its structures were brought about by abrupt turns, and the carefully engineered ideas of leading thinkers were instituted under political struggles for mono­polies of violence (we mentioned Mont­esquieu, but there were of course many others). A jerky ride of revolution, counter-revolution, conservation and reformation produced the current meta-ideology and its supremacy.

  Why then am I saying all this? I want to draw your attention to the fact that communism failed to change the games of everyday life , whereas other meta-ideologies have been successful in doing so, and future meta-ideologies can do the same.

  The conclusion, then, is not to avoid all holistic visions of society, to avoid all meta-ideologies, but to make damn certain you get them right from the beginning.

  Again, so if Marx ended up non-linearly killing a hundred million—how many did Mont­es­quieu save? How many instances of torture has he pre­vented? It’s a fair question.

  Communism Is “Game Denial”

  The cen­tral issue of communism’s failure was not that of some eternal, God-given “essence of human­ity” be­ing viol­ated, but something far more mundane: that the games of every­­­­­day life were misunderstood and/or denied .

  This led to a serious glitch in the self-organization of society, which—over a period of decades—led to a painful form of social disintegration and resulting opp­ression. Amidst all their atrocities, communist societies were rel­ati­vely functional for a while, but their social sustainability was limited—much more so than lib­eral democracy with capitalism and wel­fare (the sustain­ability of which is, of course, also limited in time, as all things under the sun). And hence they lasted for shorter periods of time.

  From this viewpoint, two conclusions become appar­ent. The first one is, again, that the relative failure of the communist experi­ments does not per­manently discredit all attempts to change the games of every­day life, to evolve the dynamics by which we live, love, trade, compete and coop­erate. If anything, the victory of liberal demo­cracy, and its grav­itation towards Green Social Liberalism, shows us that such dev­elopments are in­deed pos­s­ible.

  Rather, the failure of communism serves to underscore that you must make correct assessments of people’s behaviors—in these particu­lar times and places in history—in order to create a sustainable social order. If you make un­realistic assessments regarding how people func­tion, you set in mo­tion vicious cycles that lead to truly terrible results. But on the other hand, if you fail to understand what attractors lie ahead, you stall hist­orical progress, taking the losing side in history, which in the long run causes even more abrupt chan­ges and catastrophic outcomes—for in­st­ance, that we might have global ecological catastrophes.

  The second conclusion is that “game change” already has occurred throughout history, and that it is a measure of society’s progress: If, and only if, the games of everyday life become fairer and more forgiving, can “progress” be said to have materialized .

  So this leaves us with the under­standing that the rules of the game—in markets, in work life, in governance, in family life, in love and sex and friendship—can and will change and develop. The question is only how , when, and under the auspices of which meta-ideol­ogy.

  The basic idea is that the meta-ideology of liberal capitalism is becom­ing less viable in the global­ized information age; and that we should look for a new one: My sugg­estion for which is political meta­modernism, a.k.a. the Nordic ideology, leading us towards a listening society and a Green Social Liberalism 2.0—through the method of “co-development”.

  The Marxist critique and the failure of communism serve as fruitful starting points for seeing how a metamodern society can evolve from the modern one.

  But to be very clear: the Nordic ideology and its metamodern politics is not communism. It’s much smarter than that.

  Appendix B:

  THE FOUR FIELDS

  If you still don’t feel entirely convinced why we should discard Marxism as a theoretical starting point for changing society, it is because I have saved the best for last.

  In this chapter I’ll guide you through the four fields of development and show you how Marxism is utterly inadequate since it only addresses one of these equal
ly crucial fields. And when you have acquainted yourself with these, you will find that it not only helps to further understand the failures of communism, but also how we can achieve a metamodern soci­ety.

  However, before we go on to the four fields, a brief recap of one of the main points from Book One should be helpful.

  Value Memes in Populations

  Of all the ideas presented in Book One, this is the most important one: The average effective value meme of a population is the single most important factor determining whether it is possible for a society to progress to a new stage of development or not. If you don’t get it, then you haven’t understood this book or its prequel.

  You may recall six such value memes, each of which builds upon the former, being a “later” or even “higher” stage of development:

  Animistic

  Faustian

  Postfaustian (or traditional)

  Modern

  Postmodern

  Metamodern

  It is hard to overstate how crucial it is to raise the average effective value meme. The most brilliantly designed constitution and all the best democratic institutions in the world are null and void if the majority of the population subscribe to a Viking warrior ethos; e.g. gravitating tow­ards the Faustian value meme. Likewise a listening society cannot fully materialize as long as the vast majority remains firmly imbedded within a modern, rationalistic worldview.

 

‹ Prev