The most resounding of all the requiem’s variations today are those of radical skepticism, on the one hand, and, on the other, avowed scientists. Both of these share their origins in analytic philosophy. So I will begin with one of the most prominent skeptical positions in the postanalytic movement of the last twenty years—that of Richard Rorty. Indeed, for Rorty, without the least ambiguity or nostalgic equivocation, “there is no longer any reason to defend philosophy as an autonomous discipline.”3 Rather, a “post-philosophical culture”4 must arise in which philosophy will no longer constitute a Fach, “an autonomous cultural zone,” which is to say that it would no longer be the discipline investigating truth (which the post-philosophical culture knows to be an empty, futile notion, a mere “compliment”5 paid to our colleagues’ assertions, “rhetorical pats on the back”6 still employed in the academic world but destined to disappear). Let’s try to more precisely characterize the moment that follows analytic philosophy.
The “Postanalytic” Moment
Its Three Characteristics
This moment, whose contours have been sketched by John Rajchman in his preface to Post-Analytic Philosophy,7 can be defined by a certain number of traits, the most immediately salient of which is a desire to break with analytic philosophy. This break, or rupture, is distinct in that it is carried out internally, starting from an effective practice of analytic philosophy, not externally, like a critique posed by a Continental phenomenologist or a Persian philosopher. If, as François Récanati says, analytic philosophy has had two waves—first, logical positivism (Russell and the Vienna Circle), and second, pragmatics (Austin and the later Wittgenstein) 8—then what we are witnessing now in the United States is not the emergence of a third wave but a movement whose watchword is the abandonment of the analytic paradigm.9
This break occurs through a reestablishment of or a return to the American tradition that existed before the massive emigration of philosophers fleeing Nazi persecution. This motif of “return” is the second characteristic trait of a movement meant to revolutionize10 thinking. It is simultaneously a break with analysis and a “return” to the fathers of “American pragmatism”—this is Rorty’s claim in his introduction to Consequences of Pragmatism.11 As Vincent Descombes notes, “His guiding idea is clearly to restore the pragmatic school, that is, the American philosophical school, to its initial splendor.”12 To anticipate readers’ legitimate worries upon hearing this vocabulary of a “restoration” of a “tradition” unspoiled by any foreign contamination, Rorty specifies that this return to American thought before the analytic emigration does not signify a desire to extol a healthy, pure, and authentic tradition, at least as far as he is concerned.13 Indeed, despite his political habitus, which does not at all tend to echo an American “restoration” that is “founded” on the most radical grounds, despite the slightly humorous character of a discourse that would portray American culture as colonized, annexed, and martyred by a dominating, hegemonic, and warlike European culture, in fact, Rorty has, further and better than anyone, studied “Continental” thought—putting Heidegger (unquestionably Continental) at the summit of philosophy alongside Dewey (American, before the Franco-German emigration) and Wittgenstein (Austrian, of Cambridge).
So if a restoration of American thought is needed, for Rorty, this is because thinkers like John Dewey or William James had wanted to be done with “all” philosophy, not to propose a different philosophy. The pragmatist “views science as one genre of literature—or, put the other way around, literature and the arts as inquiries, on the same footing as scientific inquiries,”14 and puts William Blake and Fichte in the same category.15 Putting disciplines into the same framework in this manner is not to be understood in the obvious way, in the sense that different domains of competence (Fächer) would be of equal intellectual dignity, but in a fundamental way as “eradication”16 of the very notion of truth. This notion of truth, which gives philosophy its structure and unites ideas as opposed as those of Plato, Kant, Frege, and Russell, must be forgotten in the post-philosophical era that Rorty calls for. This is why Rorty finds a connection between “Dewey and Foucault, James and Nietzsche,”17 in that all call for “the end of philosophy.” Like French deconstruction, but earlier, “Dewey [thought] of philosophy, as a discipline or even as a distinct human activity, as obsolete”18 and “found what he wanted [going beyond philosophy] in turning away from philosophy as a distinctive activity altogether, and towards the ordinary world.”19 The disappearance of any notion of truth is thus the third characteristic trait of this postanalytic thought. Pragmatism is both a total skepticism that “eradicates” any notion of truth and a historicism that recognizes its own thought is a convention accepted “by the standards of our culture.”20 This idea could clearly be different tomorrow, and we wouldn’t be able to say that a parallel situation will be better, because the notion of “good” has disappeared as well as that of truth, with which it has been so often correlated. To be sure, the terms “skepticism” or even “relativism”21 appear less frequently in Rorty’s texts than “historicism,” which he constantly proclaims.22 Instead, the syntagmas that clarify the term “pragmatism” are “antiphilosophical,” “post-philosophical,” and especially the three “antis”—“antiessentialism,” “antifoundationalism,” and “antirepresentationalism.” The absence of the term “skepticism” can be explained, I think, by the fact that the skeptic still finds himself in a universe where truth is a value, whereas in the “post-philosophical” universe of pragmatism, this problem will become just as obsolete as are “the problems about Patripassianism, Arianism, etc., discussed by certain Fathers of the Church”23 for us today. Nevertheless, I will use the phrase “total skepticism” to characterize Rorty’s thought in order to avoid a constant repetition of the overly long phrase “the one who refuses any notion of truth, whether absolute, regulatory, relative or partial.” Rorty’s stance is tantamount to saying that absolutely no proposition, argument, position, or idea is “true” anymore, nor is it “better” than another—as was also the case with Nietzsche and Derrida, this radicality renders futile the characterization of his position with any term that is still a part of the philosophical universe and with which distinctions could be drawn. The genuine pragmatist “refuses to make a move in any of the games in which he is invited to take part.”24 This is undoubtedly the reason why he most often puts his positions in negative terms, such as “antirepresentationalism,” “antiessentialism,” or “antifoundationalism,” negatives that constitute so many specifications of “pragmatism”25 in its refusal of any truth.
Negative Specifications: Antirepresentationalism, Antifoundationalism, Antiessentialism
By the term “representationalism,” which constitutes the framework of his first major work,26 Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Rorty means any perspective that holds that our propositions, or representations, correspond to an assignable exterior referent. Philosophy as a whole, and Western culture more generally, is haunted by this notion of representation, in which “to know is to represent accurately what is outside the mind.”27 This definition of representation and of the “mythic entity” that accompanies it—namely, truth—allows Rorty to comprehend within a single category both analytic philosophy and the Continental tradition, Platonism and “the Cartesian-Kantian tradition.”28 Beyond the more-or-less virulent29 criticisms that Rorty makes against the analytic trend, his most characteristic theme consists in showing that the “linguistic turn,”30 far from having broken with past philosophy and inaugurated a new way of thinking, has only refashioned the old notions of “the mirror of nature” and “correspondence-truth,” of which the semantic theory (“‘p’ is true if and only if p”) is the most refined expression and of which the doctrine of reference is the zenith. The second wave of analysis (if there is such a thing) cannot abandon this fantasy of truth, even if it claims to distance itself from classical “absolutism” with phrases like “redundancy theory of truth” or “simple ‘falsi
fiability’” or even with “Searle’s reformulations.”31 The “scientific” pretention or aim, so prevalent in analytic philosophy, is nothing but the expression of a myth that has structured the West and nourished its symptom, philosophy. It is perhaps in these theses of Rortyian pragmatism that we can most clearly see the nature of his break with the analytic schema, for if that schema is constituted by an idea, it is surely the idea of a “science” as an ensemble of true propositions.
The two other specifications—antiessentialism and antifoundationalism—follow logically from this “antirepresentationalism.” The Platonic question, “Ti esti?” becomes off-limits because there is no possible response. There is no human nature nor any essence of art that individuals (humans or artworks) would exemplify. Neither the good, nor the true, nor the beautiful are essences; nor are the common genera of which species are particularizations, nor even the general species of which individuals are the expression. In short, postanalyticism must simultaneously abandon Platonic essences (the Good, the True, the Beautiful, inscribed in the heaven of Forms) as well as Enlightenment abstractions such as “man,” “nature,” and “morality,” which are only unconfessed echoes of the former. The atomized individual no longer embodies anything if this is a historic moment destined to disappear, an ideology proper to the contingent society in which he finds himself by chance, a behavior that he shares with his “neighbors,” not because it would be better than another but because it forms a part of the “standards of the moment.” At the heart of this radicalism, antifoundationalism goes without saying, even if it is sometimes difficult to determine precisely what Rorty includes in this category. A study of his most recent texts shows that it is initially and quite clearly a question of foundations in the sense of a supreme being (God), the basis of classical onto-theology. In this sense, antifoundationalism is a position that can be claimed by any Enlightenment philosopher, from Diderot to Kant. In the same vein, the foundation as ego, the supposed authority for the theory of knowledge, is likewise stigmatized as fiction. But beyond these classic critiques, which can be found just as easily in Hume, Fichte, Hegel, or Heidegger, the foundation also designates a point of view that would allow us to speak of science and of knowledge in general. Apparently targeted here are not only neo-Kantian theoreticians of knowledge like Hermann Cohen and Paul Natorp but presumably also epistemologists like Karl Popper who indeed adopt a point of view considered to be, if not better, at the very least neutral, from which they can speak of “scientific knowledge.” Rorty’s antifoundationalism, thus defined, would connect with Quine’s, who denounced the very idea of a “theory of knowledge” in his famous article “Epistemology Naturalized.”32 Science must be done, not interpreted or explained from an exterior discourse. No reflexive point of view is possible, even in the minimal and first sense of “questions about.” The difference between this kind of antifoundationalism and Quine’s probably proceeds from the sources for their respective critiques of foundationalism: for Quine, critique of foundationalism is done in the name of nature (I shall return to this point); for Rorty, in the name of the course of history. Because no point of view can escape the limited, finite, situated perspective of a mortal individual, every position from which one could speak of science or knowledge, or morality, art, philosophy, etc., is, for Rorty, impossible. Antifoundationalism is thus not merely the critique of some traditional foundation (God, the ego, nature in a Spinozistic sense) but also the critique of every point of view that would be reflexive (as, for example, “to do the theory of such and such theory” or even “to say something about what we are saying”). This radical character makes it clear that the only viable solution would be to escape from philosophy. In this sense, Rorty is coherent, because antifoundationalism thus conceived leaves no room for an even minimal philosophical posture, even one understood as the possibility for reflection upon a given practice, usage, or discourse. Rorty goes very far in this direction because he recognizes that, despite his political engagement (he stands for democracy rather than dictatorship, courtesy rather than violence, conversation rather than force), no point of view permits him to justify this choice. “Pragmatism and Philosophy,” which introduces Consequences of Pragmatism, leaves no doubt on this question, even if numerous interpreters impute to him a less radical, but also less consistent position, one more in conformity with our belief in the intrinsic superiority of democracy.33 I shall cite a somewhat long passage, which nevertheless has the virtue of being unambiguous. With respect to post-philosophy, Rorty tells us that what is “most difficult to acknowledge” but which nonetheless must be admitted is that none of our attitudes, even political and practical ones, can be said to be better than any other:
The most powerful reason for thinking that no such culture is possible is that seeing all criteria as no more than temporary resting-places, constructed by a community to facilitate its inquiries, seems morally humiliating. Suppose that Socrates was wrong, that we have not once seen the Truth, and so will not, intuitively, recognize it when we see it again. This means that when the secret police come, when the torturers violate the innocent, there is nothing to be said to them of the form “There is something within you which you are betraying. Though you embody the practices of a totalitarian society which will endure forever, there is something beyond those practices which condemns you.” This thought is hard to live with, as is Sartre’s remark: “Tomorrow, after my death, certain people may decide to establish fascism, and the others may be cowardly or miserable enough to let them get away with it. At that moment, fascism will be the truth of man, and so much the worse for us.”34
Rorty concludes, after having insisted one more time on the kinship between James and Nietzsche, that this “tough language” shows us that there are “no criteria,” no “standards of rationality,” and no “rigorous argumentation” that allow the legitimation of a point of view, for example, democracy rather than fascism. The comparison with Sartre is instructive here, for, in the context of Existentialism Is a Humanism, Sartre brought up this point to say that history will be what human freedom makes it and that there is thus no historical or natural necessity beyond this supreme value—freedom. But Rorty does not retain this point at all (since such an attitude would oblige him to say that there is a supreme value)—instead, he maintains that we cannot even justify the superiority of our point of view when confronting others who would advocate dictatorship, because no standard of rationality can be said to be better than another. Thus we have on the one hand a relatively classic humanism (even if it is not essentialist), which does not wish to break with philosophy at all, and on the other, a stance that would like to be done with all philosophy, regardless of its content.
The Nature of the Problem: Self-refutation
Can we find in the position thus characterized anything equivalent to the “cuttlefish bone” in the painting The Ambassadors? Is it a form of painting that would say the opposite of what the artist paints and the observer first sees? Is there, in its design, a motif that would invalidate it from within? Definitely, and the argument against Rorty has been employed numerous times: self-refutation, destruction of the self by the self. As Hilary Putnam notes,35 and as Rorty himself recognizes,36 any position of total skepticism is self-refuting. This self-refutation almost always takes the form of what François Récanati, following others, has termed performative or pragmatic contradiction. The most obvious example of this type of proposition is the statement “I am not speaking,” which must assume the opposite of what is being said in order to be able to say it (I must speak in order to say, “I am not speaking”). Put differently, the contradiction here is located between a discourse’s contents and its status: on this point, as Aristotle said against the Sophists, every direct challenge to the notion of truth lays itself open to this type of contradiction, because to deny the notion of truth is to posit at least the truth of the statement of denial, etc. Now, it is clear that Rorty’s position sinks into paradoxes of this type. Let’s delineate t
he most important:
Rorty never ceases to argue, bringing in proofs, objecting to reasons, refuting some and criticizing others. Thus, he sees “contradictions” in one argument, “weaknesses” in another; he finds one thesis to be “hardly reasonable,” while another is “untenable.” One could easily multiply the examples of this kind of evaluation because all Rorty’s books are based on them. But, if no argument is really better than another, why argue? Why criticize a given position—say, that of recent analytic philosophy—if one claims that, in the final analysis, it is just one viewpoint among many? How can Rorty refute a given position, and defend his own with grounds, reasons, and arguments, if all arguments are the same, that is, if, in the end, none have value? We have here a good candidate to be considered as the epitome of a contradiction between the contents of a statement (“No argument is better than another.”) and a discursive practice (“I will make arguments to demonstrate this claim to you.”).
Likewise, if we took up again the classic example of truth, Rorty’s discursive attitude can be well characterized as that of one who claims to say something true in opposition to another such position that he views as false. As soon as he writes, for example, “Pragmatism, by contrast, does not erect Science as an idol … It views science as one genre of literature,”37 he claims the rightness of this position. The rightness that he claims, moreover, presupposes a definition of literature. Rorty presupposes, finally, that this definition of literature is the right one and that his equation “science = literature” is correct. In brief, Rorty claims the truth of this statement, as he had claimed that his arguments for Dewey over Kant were correct. His practice of writing presupposes a particular stance: a claim to truth that the contents of his discourse denies. This “claim to” is intrinsic to his mode of writing. Certainly, there are many human activities (playing the piano, writing poetry, arranging a bouquet of flowers in the Japanese style, praying, etc.) that do not depend upon this sort of claim, but those are not what Rorty has chosen to do in his books. He falls back upon the activity that consists in justifying the value of his own point of view with the aid of arguments, and as a corollary, attempting to convince others that their view, if it contradicts the first, is false. Rorty claims and indeed states that, in his view, the Critique of Pure Reason is wrong, that analytic philosophy is a network of countertruths, that Putnam is wrong in objecting to his theses, that representation is a myth—a characterization as myth indeed that assumes an exterior viewpoint or perspective on this myth, from which this characterization is possible, etc.
The Death of Philosophy Page 3