The Great Degeneration: How Institutions Decay and Economies Die

Home > Other > The Great Degeneration: How Institutions Decay and Economies Die > Page 6
The Great Degeneration: How Institutions Decay and Economies Die Page 6

by Niall Ferguson


  Another and related way of thinking about the financial system is as a highly complex system, made up of a very large number of interacting components that are asymmetrically organized in a network.21 This network operates somewhere between order and disorder – on ‘the edge of chaos’. Such complex systems can appear to operate quite smoothly for some time, apparently in equilibrium, in reality constantly adapting as positive feedback loops operate. But there comes a moment when they ‘go critical’. A slight perturbation can set off a ‘phase transition’ from a benign equilibrium to a crisis. This is especially common where the network nodes are ‘tightly coupled’. When the interrelatedness of a network increases, conflicting constraints can quickly produce a ‘complexity catastrophe’.

  All complex systems in the natural world – from termite hills to large forests to the human nervous system – share certain characteristics. A small input to such a system can produce huge, unanticipated changes. Causal relationships are often non-linear. Indeed, some theorists would go so far as to say that certain complex systems are wholly non-deterministic, meaning that it is next to impossible to make predictions about their future behaviour based on past data. Will the next forest fire be tiny or huge, a bonfire or a conflagration? We can’t be sure. The same ‘power law’ relationship seems to apply to earthquakes and epidemics.22

  It turns out that financial crises are much the same. And this should not surprise us. As heterodox economists like W. Brian Arthur have been arguing for years, a complex economy is characterized by the interaction of dispersed agents, a lack of any central control, multiple levels of organization, continual adaptation, incessant creation of new market niches and no general equilibrium. Viewed in this light, as Andrew Haldane of the Bank of England has argued, Wall Street and the City of London are parts of one of the most complex systems that human beings have ever made (see Figure 2.1).23 And the combination of concentration, interbank lending, financial innovation and technological acceleration makes it a system especially prone to crash. Once again, however, the difference between the natural world and the financial world is the role of regulation. Regulation is supposed to reduce the number and size of financial forest fires. And yet, as we have seen, it can quite easily have the opposite effect. This is because the political process is itself somewhat complex. Regulatory bodies can be captured by those whom they are supposed to be regulating, not least by the prospect of well-paid jobs should the gamekeeper turn poacher. They can also be captured in other ways – for example, by their reliance on the entities they regulate for the very data they need to do their work.

  Figure 2.1 Network connectivity balloons for the international financial system

  Source: Andrew Haldane, Bank of England (see note 23 for full reference).

  In his book Antifragile, the statistician and options trader turned philosopher Nassim Taleb asks a wonderful question: what is the opposite of fragile? The answer is not ‘robust’ or ‘strong’, because those words simply mean less fragile. The true opposite of fragile is ‘anti-fragile’. A system that becomes stronger when subjected to perturbation is anti-fragile.24 The point is that regulation should be designed to heighten anti-fragility. But the regulation we are contemplating today does the opposite: because of its very complexity – and often contradictory objectives – it is pro-fragile.

  Lessons from Lombard Street

  Over-complicated regulation can indeed be the disease of which it purports to be the cure. Just as the planners of the old Soviet system could never hope to direct a modern economy in all its complexity, for reasons long ago explained by Friedrich Hayek and Janos Kornai,25 so the regulators of the post-crisis world are doomed to fail in their efforts to make the global financial system crisis-free. They can never know enough to manage such a complex system. They will only ever learn from the last crisis how to make the next one.

  Is there an alternative? I believe there is. But we need to go back to the time of Darwin to find it. In Lombard Street, published in 1873, Walter Bagehot described with great skill the way in which the City of London had evolved in his time. Bagehot understood that, for all its Darwinian vigour, the British financial system was complex and fragile. ‘In exact proportion to the power of this system’, he observed, ‘is its delicacy – I should hardly say too much if I said its danger . . . even at the last instant of prosperity, the whole structure is delicate. The peculiar essence of our financial system is an unprecedented trust between man and man; and when that trust is much weakened by hidden causes, a small accident may greatly hurt it, and a great accident for a moment may almost destroy it.’26

  No one has ever given a better description of how a bank run happens than Bagehot; those unfamiliar with Lombard Street had to find out for themselves in 2007, at the time of the runs on Northern Rock and Countrywide, and again in 2012, when it was the turn of the Spanish Bankia to lose the confidence of its depositors. One of the great beauties of Lombard Street is the way it surveys all the key institutions of the London money market – the ascendant joint-stock banks, the waning private banks, the bill brokers, the new savings banks – and exposes the weakness in the position of each. In theory, Bagehot would have preferred a system in which each institution had to look to itself by maintaining a reserve against contingencies. But in practice the London market had evolved in such a way that there was only one ultimate reserve for the entire City and that was the Bank of England’s: ‘the sole considerable unoccupied mass of cash in the country’.27 As in our time, in other words, the central bank (and, behind it, the government that called it into being) constituted the last line of resistance in time of panic.

  By reviewing half a century of financial crises, Bagehot brilliantly showed how the Bank of England’s role as custodian of the nation’s cash reserve was quite different from its role as defined by statute or, indeed, as understood by the men running it. In the 1825 panic the Bank had done the right thing, but much too late in the day, and without knowing quite why it was the right thing. In each of the three panics that followed the passage of the Bank Charter Act of 1844 – a piece of legislation which was largely concerned with the Bank’s note-issuing function – the Act had been suspended. There was, as in our time, uncertainty about which securities it would accept as collateral in a crisis. The Bank’s governance structure was opaque. Its governor and directors were themselves not bankers. (In those days they chose merchants; nowadays we prefer academics – which not everyone would regard as an improvement.) They barely coped when a SIFI called Overend Gurney blew up in 1866.

  Bagehot’s remedies were clear-cut, though I believe they are very often misinterpreted. The famous recommendation was that in a crisis the central bank should lend freely at a penalty rate: ‘Very large loans at very high rates are the best remedy . . .’28 Nowadays we follow only the first half of his advice, in the belief that our system is so leveraged that high rates would kill it. Bagehot’s rationale was to ‘prevent the greatest number of applications by persons who do not require it’.29 Watching all banks, strong and weak alike, gorge themselves on today’s seemingly limitless supply of loans at near-zero rates, I see what he meant.

  We also neglect the rest of what Bagehot said, and in particular the emphasis he laid on discretion as opposed to set rules. In the first place, he stressed the importance of having Bank directors with considerable market experience. ‘Steady merchants’, he wrote, ‘always know the questionable standing of dangerous persons; they are quick to note the smallest signs of corrupt transactions.’ Executive power should be conferred on a new, full-time deputy governor acting as a kind of permanent under-secretary. And the advisory Court should be selected so as ‘to introduce . . . a wise apprehensiveness’.30

  Secondly, Bagehot repeatedly stressed, as he put it, ‘the cardinal importance of [the Bank of England’s] always retaining a great banking reserve’. But he was emphatic that the size of the reserve should not be specified by some automatic rule, the wa
y the banknote circulation was under the 1844 Bank Charter Act: ‘No certain or fixed proportion of its liabilities can in the present times be laid down as that which the Bank ought to keep in reserve.’ The ideal central bank would target nothing more precise than an ‘apprehension minimum’, which ‘no abstract argument, and no mathematical computation will teach to us’:

  And we cannot expect that they should [he went on]. Credit is an opinion generated by circumstances and varying with those circumstances. The state of credit . . . can only be known by trial and inquiry. And in the same way, nothing can tell us what amount of ‘reserve’ will create a diffused confidence; on such a subject there is no way of arriving at a just conclusion except by incessantly watching the public mind, and seeing at each juncture how it is affected.31

  Nor should there be predictability in the Bank’s discount rate, the rate at which it lent against good-quality commercial paper. The rule ‘that the Bank of England should look to the market rate and make its own rate conform to that . . . was . . . always erroneous’, according to Bagehot. The ‘first duty’ of the Bank was to use the discount rate to ‘protect the ultimate cash of the country’.32 This too of course implied a discretionary power, since the desirable size of the reserve was not specified by any rule.

  There are some today, like Larry Kotlikoff and John Kay, who see the only salvation in a root-and-branch structural reform of our financial system: ‘narrow banking’ of some sort, if not the replacement of banks altogether.33 I can see the intellectual appeal of such arguments. In theory, perhaps it would be much better if big banks were chopped up, leverage ratios were drastically reduced and the interconnections between deposit-takers and risk-takers were reduced.34 But, like Bagehot, I take the world as I find it, and I do not expect to see in my lifetime a wholesale abandonment of the current model of ‘too big to fail’ institutions backstopped by the central bank and, if necessary, by the public purse. Our task, like Bagehot’s, is ‘to make the best of our banking system, and to work it in the best way that it is capable of. We can only use palliatives, and the point is to get the best palliative we can.’35

  How to Encourage Bankers

  ‘The problem is delicate,’ as Bagehot candidly concluded his great work, and ‘the solution is varying and difficult.’36 It remains so today. But I believe a return to Bagehot’s first principles would not be a bad starting point. First, strengthen the central bank as the ultimate authority in both the monetary and supervisory systems. Second, ensure that those in charge at the central bank are ‘apprehensive’ as well as experienced, so that they will act when they see excessive credit growth and asset-price inflation. Third, give them considerable latitude in their use of the principal central banking tools of reserve requirements, interest rate changes and open-market securities purchases and sales. Fourth, teach them some financial history, as Bagehot taught his readers.

  Finally – a point Bagehot did not need to make because in his time it was a matter of course – we must ensure that those who fall foul of the regulatory authority pay dearly for their transgressions. Those who believe this crisis was caused by deregulation have misunderstood the problem in more than one way. Not only was misconceived regulation a large part of the cause. There was also the feeling of impunity that came not from deregulation but from non-punishment.

  There will always be greedy people in and around banks. After all, they are where the money is – or is supposed to be. But greedy people will commit fraud or negligence only if they feel that their misdemeanour is unlikely to be noticed or severely punished. The failure to apply regulation – to apply the law – is one of the most troubling aspects of the years since 2007. In the United States, the list of those who have been sent to jail for their part in the housing bubble, and all that followed from it, is risibly short. In the United Kingdom, the harshest punishment meted out to a banker was the ‘cancellation and annulment’ of the former Royal Bank of Scotland CEO Fred Goodwin’s knighthood.

  Bagehot never got the powerful and permanent deputy governor that he proposed; instead the governor himself became both less powerful and less permanent. Since being deprived of his regulatory role, which was handed to the Financial Services Authority by Gordon Brown, the governor has been in the unenviable position of running a monetary policy research department (combined recently with an emergency money-printing works). The Federal Reserve System, too, has no real teeth. The agencies supposed to prosecute fraud have performed miserably. The result is that very few malefactors have been brought to justice in a meaningful way.

  I will cite just one of many possible examples. In October 2010 Angelo Mozilo reached a settlement with the Securities and Exchange Commission in which he agreed to pay $67.5 million in penalties and ‘disgorgements’ to settle civil fraud and insider-trading charges relating to his time as CEO of Countrywide, the failed mortgage lender. At least part of this fine was paid not by Mozilo himself but by Bank of America, which acquired Countrywide in the depths of the financial crisis, and by insurers. Between 2000 and 2008 Mozilo received nearly $522 million in total compensation, including sales of Countrywide stock: nearly ten times more than the fine.37 If there was nothing criminal in his conduct, it is surely only because the criminal law is defective in this area.

  Voltaire famously said that the British periodically executed an admiral pour encourager les autres. All the detailed regulation in the world will do less to avert a future financial crisis than the clear and present danger in the minds of today’s bankers that, if they transgress in the eyes of the authority on whom their business ultimately depends, then they could go to prison. Instead of exhausting ourselves drawing up hopelessly complex codes of ‘macro-prudential’ or ‘counter-cyclical’ regulation, let us go back to Bagehot’s world, where individual prudence – rather than mere compliance – was the advisable course, precisely because the authorities were powerful and the crucial rules unwritten.

  I began this chapter by contradicting the proponents of stricter regulation, only to end it by advocating the exemplary incarceration of bad bankers. I hope it is now clear why these positions are not contradictory but complementary. A complex financial world will be made less fragile only by simplicity of regulation and strength of enforcement.

  To repeat: among the most deadly enemies of the rule of law is bad law. The next chapter will consider at a more general level the ways in which the rule of law itself, broadly defined, has degenerated in Western societies – and especially in the United States – in our time. In the realm of regulation, as I have said, we ought to be going back to Bagehot. But has the legal system in the English-speaking world inadvertently gone back to Dickens? Has the rule of law degenerated into the rule of lawyers?

  3. The Landscape of Law

  The Lure of Law

  The fundamental question the Chinese government must face is lawlessness. China does not lack laws, but the rule of law . . . This issue of lawlessness may be the greatest challenge facing the new leaders who will be installed this autumn [of 2012] . . . Indeed, China’s political stability may depend on its ability to develop the rule of law in a system where it barely exists.1

  These are the words of Chen Guangcheng, the blind lawyer who was allowed to leave China to study in the United States after successfully escaping from his Communist Party persecutors in April 2012. Less well known in the West, but more influential in China, is the legal scholar He Weifang. In an essay entitled ‘China’s First Steps towards Constitutionalism’, published in 2003, He rather more tactfully observed: ‘The Western legal landscape does make an interesting and illuminating contrast to China’s legal situation, revealing many discrepancies and inconsistencies between the two . . . Although China’s modern system was borrowed from the West . . . things often proceed in different ways between China and the West.’2

  The theme of this chapter is the landscape of law. I want to ask what, if anything, developing countries like China can learn from the W
est about the rule of law. And I want to cast some doubt on the widespread assumption that our Western legal systems are in such good health that all the Chinese need to do is replicate our best practice – whatever that may be.

  The English Way of Law

  What exactly do we mean by the rule of law? In his book of that name,3 the late Lord Chief Justice, Tom Bingham, specified seven criteria by which we should assess a legal system:

  the law must be accessible and so far as possible intelligible, clear and predictable;

  questions of legal right and liability should ordinarily be resolved by application of the law and not by the exercise of discretion;

  the laws of the land should apply equally to all, save to the extent that objective differences [such as mental incapacity] justify differentiation;

  ministers and public officers at all levels must exercise the powers conferred on them in good faith, fairly, for the purpose for which the powers were conferred, without exceeding the limits of such powers;

  the law must afford adequate protection of fundamental human rights;

  means must be provided for resolving, without prohibitive cost or inordinate delay, bona fide civil disputes which the parties themselves are unable to resolve; and

  adjudicative procedures provided by the state should be fair.

  Under heading 5, Bingham lists no fewer than fourteen different rights that the rule of law should be expected to protect: the right to life, protection from torture, protection from slavery and forced labour, the right to liberty and security, the right to a fair trial, protection from punishment without law, the right to respect for private/family life, freedom of thought/conscience/religion, freedom of expression, freedom of assembly/association, the right to marry, freedom from discrimination, protection of property and the right to education. (He might have gone further, since some countries today explicitly acknowledge rights to housing, healthcare, education and a clean environment. Why not a right to drinkable wine, too?)

 

‹ Prev