Bayesian Statistics (4th ed)

Home > Other > Bayesian Statistics (4th ed) > Page 2
Bayesian Statistics (4th ed) Page 2

by Peter M Lee


  I am indebted to Professor RA Cooper for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this book, although of course he cannot be held responsible for any errors in the final version.

  Peter M. Lee

  30 March 1988

  1. Further information is now available in Bellhouse (2003) and Dale (2003). Useful information can also be found in Bellhouse et al. (1988–1992), Dale (1999), Edwards (1993, 2004) and Hald (1986, 1998, 2007).

  1

  Preliminaries

  1.1 Probability and Bayes’ Theorem

  1.1.1 Notation

  The notation will be kept simple as possible, but it is useful to express statements about probability in the language of set theory. You probably know most of the symbols undermentioned, but if you do not you will find it easy enough to get the hang of this useful shorthand. We consider sets of elements and we use the word ‘iff’ to mean ‘if and only if’. Then we write

  iff x is a member of A;

  x ∉ A iff x is not a member of A;

  iff A is the set whose only members are x, y and z (and similarly for larger or smaller sets);

  iff A is the set of elements for which the statement S(x) is true;

  for the null set, that is the set with no elements;

  for all x;

  (i.e. A is a subset of B) iff implies ;

  (i.e. A is a superset of B) iff is implied by ;

  , and for all A;

  (where ‘P or Q’ means ‘P or Q or both’) (referred to as the union of A and B or as A union B);

  (referred to as the intersection of A and B or as A intersect B);

  A and B are disjoint iff ;

  (referred to as the difference set A less B).

  Let (An) be a sequence of sets. Then

  for one or more n};

  for all n};

  (An) exhausts B if ;

  (An) consists of exclusive sets if for ;

  (An) consists of exclusive sets given B if for ;

  (An) is non-decreasing if , that is for all n;

  (An) is non-increasing if , that is for all n.

  We sometimes need a notation for intervals on the real line, namely

  where a and b are real numbers or or .

  1.1.2 Axioms for probability

  In the study of probability and statistics, we refer to as complete a description of the situation as we need in a particular context as an elementary event.

  Thus, if we are concerned with the tossing of a red die and a blue die, then a typical elementary event is ‘red three, blue five’, or if we are concerned with the numbers of Labour and Conservative MPs in the next parliament, a typical elementary event is ‘Labour 350, Conservative 250’. Often, however, we want to talk about one aspect of the situation. Thus, in the case of the first example, we might be interested in whether or not we get a red three, which possibility includes ‘red three, blue one’, ‘red three, blue two’, etc. Similarly, in the other example, we could be interested in whether there is a Labour majority of at least 100, which can also be analyzed into elementary events. With this in mind, an event is defined as a set of elementary events (this has the slightly curious consequence that, if you are very pedantic, an elementary event is not an event since it is an element rather than a set). We find it useful to say that one event E implies another event F if E is contained in F. Sometimes it is useful to generalize this by saying that, given H, E implies F if EH is contained in F. For example, given a red three has been thrown, throwing a blue three implies throwing an even total.

  Note that the definition of an elementary event depends on the context. If we were never going to consider the blue die, then we could perfectly well treat events such as ‘red three’ as elementary events. In a particular context, the elementary events in terms of which it is sensible to work are usually clear enough.

  Events are referred to above as possible future occurrences, but they can also describe present circumstances, known or unknown. Indeed, the relationship which probability attempts to describe is one between what you currently know and something else about which you are uncertain, both of them being referred to as events. In other words, for at least some pairs of events E and H there is a number defined which is called the probability of the event E given the hypothesis H. I might, for example, talk of the probability of the event E that I throw a red three given the hypothesis H that I have rolled two fair dice once, or the probability of the event E of a Labour majority of at least 100 given the hypothesis H which consists of my knowledge of the political situation to date. Note that in this context, the term ‘hypothesis’ can be applied to a large class of events, although later on we will find that in statistical arguments, we are usually concerned with hypotheses which are more like the hypotheses in the ordinary meaning of the word.

  Various attempts have been made to define the notion of probability. Many early writers claimed that was m/n where there were n symmetrical and so equally likely possibilities given H of which m resulted in the occurrence of E. Others have argued that should be taken as the long run frequency with which E happens when H holds. These notions can help your intuition in some cases, but I think they are impossible to turn into precise, rigourous definitions. The difficulty with the first lies in finding genuinely ‘symmetrical’ possibilities – for example, real dice are only approximately symmetrical. In any case, there is a danger of circularity in the definitions of symmetry and probability. The difficulty with the second is that we never know how long we have to go on trying before we are within, say, 1% of the true value of the probability. Of course, we may be able to give a value for the number of trials we need to be within 1% of the true value with, say, probability 0.99, but this is leading to another vicious circle of definitions. Another difficulty is that sometimes we talk of the probability of events (e.g. nuclear war in the next 5 years) about which it is hard to believe in a large numbers of trials, some resulting in ‘success’ and some in ‘failure’. A good, brief discussion is to be found in Nagel (1939) and a fuller, more up-to-date one in Chatterjee (2003).

  It seems to me, and to an increasing number of statisticians, that the only satisfactory way of thinking of is as a measure of my degree of belief in E given that I know that H is true. It seems reasonable that this measure should abide by the following axioms:

  P1 for all E, H.

  P2 = 1 for all H.

  P3 when .

  P4

  By taking in P3 and using P1 and P2, it easily follows that

  so that is always between 0 and 1. Also by taking in P3 it follows that

  Now intuitive notions about probability always seem to agree that it should be a quantity between 0 and 1 which falls to 0 when we talk of the probability of something we are certain will not happen and rises to 1 when we are certain it will happen (and we are certain that H is true given H is true). Further, the additive property in P3 seems highly reasonable – we would, for example, expect the probability that the red die lands three or four should be the sum of the probability that it lands three and the probability that it lands four.

  Axiom P4 may seem less familiar. It is sometimes written as

  although, of course, this form cannot be used if the denominator (and hence the numerator) on the right-hand side vanishes. To see that it is a reasonable thing to assume, consider the following data on criminality among the twin brothers or sisters of criminals [quoted in his famous book by Fisher (1925b)]. The twins were classified according as they had a criminal conviction (C) or not (N) and according as they were monozygotic (M) (which is more or less the same as identical – we will return to this in Section 1.2) or dizygotic (D), resulting in the following table:

  If we denote by H the knowledge that an individual has been picked at random from this population, then it seems reasonable to say that

  If on the other hand, we consider an individual picked at random from among the twins with a criminal conviction in the population, we see that

  and hence

  so that P4
holds in this case. It is easy to see that this relationship does not depend on the particular numbers that happen to appear in the data.

  In many ways, the argument in the preceding paragraph is related to derivations of probabilities from symmetry considerations, so perhaps it should be stressed that while in certain circumstances we may believe in symmetries or in equally probable cases, we cannot base a general definition of probability on such arguments.

  It is convenient to use a stronger form of axiom P3 in many contexts, namely,

  whenever the (En) are exclusive events given H. There is no doubt of the mathematical simplifications that result from this assumption, but we are supposed to be modelling our degrees of belief and it is questionable whether these have to obey this form of the axiom. Indeed, one of the greatest advocates of Bayesian theory, Bruno de Finetti, was strongly against the use of P3*. His views can be found in de Finetti (1972, Section 5.32) or in de Finetti (1974–1975, Section 3.11.3).

  There is certainly some arbitrariness about P3*, which is sometimes referred to as an assumption of σ-additivity, in that it allows additivity over some but not all infinite collections of events (technically over countable but not over uncountable collections). However, it is impossible in a lot of contexts to allow additivity over any (arbitrary) collection of events. Thus, if we want a model for picking a point ‘completely at random’ from the unit interval

  it seems reasonable that the probability that the point picked is in any particular sub-interval of the unit interval should equal the length of that sub-interval. However, this clearly implies that the probability of picking any one particular x is zero (since any such x belongs to intervals of arbitrarily small lengths). But the probability that some x is picked is unity, and it is impossible to get one by adding a lot of zeroes.

  Mainly because of its mathematical convenience, we shall assume P3* while being aware of the problems.

  1.1.3 ‘Unconditional’ probability

  Strictly speaking, there is, in my view, no such thing as an unconditional probability. However, it often happens that many probability statements are made conditional on everything that is part of an individual’s knowledge at a particular time, and when many statements are to be made conditional on the same event, it makes for cumbersome notation to refer to this same conditioning event every time. There are also cases where we have so much experimental data in circumstances judged to be relevant to a particular situation that there is a fairly general agreement as to the probability of an event. Thus, in tossing a coin, you and I both have experience of tossing similar coins many times and so are likely to believe that ‘heads’ is approximately as likely as not, so that the probability of ‘heads’ is approximately given your knowledge or mine.

  In these cases we write

  where Ω is the set of possibilities consistent with the sum total of data available to the individual or individuals concerned. We usually consider sets F for which , so that . It easily follows from the axioms that

  whenever the (En) are exclusive events (or more properly whenever they are exclusive events given Ω), and

  Many books begin by asserting that unconditional probability is an intuitive notion and use the latter formula in the form

  to define conditional probability.

  1.1.4 Odds

  It is sometimes convenient to use a language more familiar to bookmakers to express probabilistic statements. We define the odds on E against F given H as the ratio

  or equivalently

  A reference to the odds on E against F with no mention of H is to be interpreted as a reference to the odds on E against F given Ω, where Ω is some set of background knowledge as above.

  Odds do not usually have properties as simple as probabilities, but sometimes, for example, in connection with Bayesian tests of hypotheses, they are more natural to consider than separate probabilities.

  1.1.5 Independence

  Two events E and F are said to be independent given H if

  From axiom P4, it follows that if this condition is equivalent to

  so that if E is independent of F given H then the extra information that F is true does not alter the probability of E from that given H alone, and this gives the best intuitive idea as to what independence means. However, the restriction of this interpretation to the case where makes the original equation slightly more general.

  More generally, a sequence (En) of events is said to be pairwise independent given H if

  and is said to consist of mutually independent events given H if for every finite subset of them

  You should be warned that pairwise independence does not imply mutual independence and that

  is not enough to ensure that the finite sequence consists of mutually independent events given H.

  Naturally, if no conditioning event is explicitly mentioned, the probabilities concerned are conditional on Ω as defined above.

  1.1.6 Some simple consequences of the axioms; Bayes’ Theorem

  We have already noted a few consequences of the axioms, but it is useful at this point to note a few more. We first note that it follows simply from P4 and P2 and the fact that HH=H that

  and in particular

  Next note that if, given H, E implies F, that is and so EFH=EH, then by P4 and the aforementioned equation

  From this and the fact that it follows that if, given H, E implies F, then

  In particular, if E implies F then

  For the rest of this subsection, we can work in terms of ‘unconditional’ probabilities, although the results are easily generalized. Let (Hn) be a sequence of exclusive and exhaustive events, and let E be any event. Then

  since by P4 the terms on the right-hand side are , allowing us to deduce the result from P3*. This result is sometimes called the generalized addition law or the law of the extension of the conversation.

  The key result in the whole book is Bayes’ Theorem. This is simply deduced as follows. Let (Hn) be a sequence of events. Then by P4

  so that provided

  This relationship is one of several ways of stating Bayes’ Theorem, and is probably the best way in which to remember it. When we need the constant of proportionality, we can easily see from the above that it is .

  It should be clearly understood that there is nothing controversial about Bayes’ Theorem as such. It is frequently used by probabilists and statisticians, whether or not they are Bayesians. The distinctive feature of Bayesian statistics is the application of the theorem in a wider range of circumstances than is usual in classical statistics. In particular, Bayesian statisticians are always willing to talk of the probability of a hypothesis, both unconditionally (its prior probability) and given some evidence (its posterior probability), whereas other statisticians will only talk of the probability of a hypothesis in restricted circumstances.

  When (Hn) consists of exclusive and exhaustive events, we can combine the last two results to see that

  A final result that we will find useful from time to time is the generalized multiplication law, which runs as follows. If are any events then

  provided all the requisite conditional probabilities are defined, which in practice they will be provided . This result is easily proved by repeated application of P4.

  1.2 Examples on Bayes’ Theorem

  1.2.1 The Biology of Twins

  Twins can be either monozygotic (M) (i.e. developed from a single egg) or dizygotic (D). Monozygotic twins often look very similar and then are referred to as identical twins, but it is not always the case that one finds very striking similarities between monozygotic twins, while some dizygotic twins can show marked resemblances. Whether twins are monozygotic or dizygotic is not, therefore, a matter which can be settled simply by inspection. However, it is always the case that monozygotic twins are of the same sex, whereas dizygotic twins can be of opposite sex. Hence, assuming that the two sexes are equally probable, if the sexes of a pair of twins are denoted GG, BB or GB (note GB is indistinguishable from BG)
/>   It follows that

  from which it can be seen that

  so that although it is not easy to be certain whether a particular pair are monozygotic or not, it is easy to discover the proportion of monozygotic twins in the whole population of twins simply by observing the sex distribution among all twins.

  1.2.2 A political example

  The following example is a simplified version of the situation just before the time of the British national referendum as to whether the United Kingdom should remain part of the European Economic Community which was held in 1975. Suppose that at that date, which was shortly after an election which the Labour Party had won, the proportion of the electorate supporting Labour (L) stood at 52%, while the proportion supporting the Conservatives (C) stood at 48% (it being assumed for simplicity that support for all other parties was negligible, although this was far from being the case). There were many opinion polls taken at the time, so we can take it as known that 55% of Labour supporters and 85% of Conservative voters intended to vote ‘Yes’ (Y) and the remainder intended to vote ‘No’ (N). Suppose that knowing all this you met someone at the time who said that she intended to vote ‘Yes’, and you were interested in knowing which political party she supported. If this information were all you had available, you could reason as follows:

 

‹ Prev