Book Read Free

Lovers of Sophia

Page 21

by Jason Reza Jorjani


  of cold, pure and unconcerned logical argumentation, whereas the

  latter are usual y marshaled after the fact in order to give form to

  a mystical inspiration or filter and make abstract “a desire of the

  heart.” Nietzsche is not denying that he and Spinoza might share

  an essential y similar “desire of the heart”, he is simply criticizing Spinoza for demanding that everyon e should recognize the ‘truth’ of his values. To the contrary, on the grounds of the metaphysics of

  power (first proposed by Spinoza), Nietzsche believes that his values

  are his own, even though they are also the highest. Spinoza does not have the strength for this. However, in addition to accusing Spinoza

  of “personal timidity and vulnerability”, Nietzsche ends by calling

  him a “sick hermit”. An interesting accusation, given that Nietzsche

  spent most of his own life ill and in profound solitude.

  In section 25 of Beyond Good and Evil, in addition to reiterating his description of Spinoza as one of “the compulsory recluses”, he

  levels a more serious accusation against Spinoza, namely that the

  latter had become one of the “sophisticated vengeance-seekers

  and poison-brewers”, calling on us to “lay bare the foundation of

  Spinoza’s ethics and theology.” The comments come in the course

  of a warning to philosophers not to be deluded into believing that

  their struggles and persecution in the world are sacrifices in the

  name of defending truth. Their inability to openly and forceful y

  confront and defeat their enemies breeds a poisonous craftiness

  in them and robs them of the playful innocence and good humor

  that characterizes a truly free spirit. If they ultimately go from

  being outcasts to being “martyrs”, then they have ceased to be

  165

  lovers of sophia

  tragic philosophers and have instead become farcical “stage-and

  platform-bawlers.” In the following section Nietzsche elaborates

  on this idea in a way that makes clearer his criticism of Spinoza in

  particular. Nietzsche acknowledges that choice human beings strive

  to create “a citadel and a secrecy” of solitude that saves them from

  the disgusting masses. Spinoza, the recluse, is certainly the kind of

  figure that he has in mind here. However, Nietzsche claims that it is

  even more exceptional to “go down” and live amongst men, to study

  them, but also to test oneself and become a more inward (more

  ‘spiritual’) person, for the lack of an external fortress. Those who

  lack the strength for this, such as Spinoza, were “not made… not

  predestined, for knowledge.”

  It should be noted that in his preface to Human, all-too-Human, Nietzsche describes a “great separation” as the most decisive event

  in the life of a man who is to one day become a genuinely free spirit.

  He describes this need to “go off into some desert” as symptomatic

  of spiritual illness. Here, as in many other passages throughout his

  works, Nietzsche speaks of the uncanny state of mind brought about

  by such an illness as a womb of creativity and a path to liberation.

  An especial y vivid example of this is in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, when after returning to his hermetic solitude, Zarathustra fal s ill

  only to realize that the common man or ‘last man’ must also be

  affirmed as necessary and that he must descend once again amongst

  men to learn from them. Thus it is clear that Nietzsche suffered

  from the same hermetic illness that he identifies in Spinoza, so

  that even Nietzsche’s most vitriolic criticisms of Spinoza appear on

  closer examination to be another example of Nietzsche’s painful y

  intimate relationship to his predecessor. He chastises himself by way

  of chastising Spinoza, because he suffers from the same wounds,

  from having followed the same perilous and solitary mountain path

  to spiritual freedom. Nietzsche concludes his July 30, 1881 letter

  describing his ‘discovery of Spinoza’ with these telling words: “In summa: my solitariness which, as on very high mountains, has often made me gasp for breath and lose blood, is now at least a solitude for two. Strange!”

  166

  ALIENS AND THE MORAL LAW

  Beginning in the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals,

  Immanuel Kant attempts to fashion a genuinely universal

  ethics – a moral law which would apply to all the types of

  alien intelligence that he was convinced fill the heavens.

  To this end, namely in order to ground a moral law relevant to all

  rational beings, Kant needs to first define what it is that all and only rational beings share in common. He claims that this is the existence of a rational being as “an end in itself.” However, in the relevant

  passages it is unclear who or what is the “end in itself”. Is it the rational being(s) as entities that Nature ultimately aims to produce,

  or the “own” existence of each and every rational being? The first section sets out this problem and ventures a provisional solution to

  it.

  However, in order to address this question in the most

  interpretively charitable way, the second section considers

  innovations of Kant’s later moral philosophy, in the Critique of

  Practical Reason and the Metaphysics of Morals, which affect the meaning of key concepts in the Groundwork and modify certain

  of its central claims. Among these is the transformation that Kant’s

  concept of “wil ” ( wille) undergoes with the later development of the concept of the “power of choice” ( willküre). Such a transformation of the concept of will has significant consequences for the Groundwork’s notion of freedom, a notion which Kant claims is somehow

  inseparably connected with his definition of a rational being as

  a being whose existence is an end in itself. There is also a related

  167

  lovers of sophia

  change in Kant’s view of whether the moral law can allow for (or

  indeed, requires) the happiness of others and one’s own perfection to

  be objects of the faculty of desire and material determining grounds

  of the wil .

  In the third and final section, after having ascertained how we

  are to understand an end in itself with respect to the existence of

  beings, its relationship to Kant’s single innate Right of freedom is determined. An attempt is made to draw out the empirical claims

  about the nature of extraterrestrial intelligence that are implicated

  by Kant’s apriori attempt to develop a universal moral philosophy

  – both an ethics and political principle of Natural Right that would apply to any and all non-human rational beings. To this end the

  reader is asked to patiently immerse himself for a time in a world

  of truly alien intelligence, without which it is not possible to be

  struck by the boldness of Kant’s claim that all extraterrestrials would be persons whose power of free choice renders them individual y responsible to one another under the moral law.

  I.

  Kant refers to non-human intelligence no less than eleven times

  in the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, and he draws an explicit distinction between human beings and rational beings in

  general on six of these occasions (see 4:389, 4:408, 4:425, 4:428-4:29, 4:447-448, and 4:449). When we view these references through the

  lens of the third part of Kant’s 1755 astronomical work Universal

 
Natural History and Theory of the Heavens, it begins to become clear that applicability to extraterrestrial intelligence was the key

  motivation behind Kant’s attempt to develop an apriori moral philosophy.

  Kant’s Universal Natural History is famous for two novel

  astronomical theories that more or less proved to be true: the disc

  shape of the Milky Way and the idea that distant nebula are actual y

  other ‘universes’ (real y, other galaxies). However, in the long

  168

  jason reza jorjani

  suppressed third section of this work, Kant develops a theory of

  aliens of varying degrees of rationality, depending on the empirical

  conditions of their development (with distance from the sun being

  the key factor). There are some beings so perfect in their physical

  and spiritual constitution that they adhere to the moral law virtual y flawlessly, while there are others so malformed and pathological y

  driven that they are incapable of sin only because they lack the

  capacity for responsible actions. Between these extremes, there are

  beings out there like ourselves – fallible, but capable of resisting our sensuous inclinations and obeying the single moral law within us

  all.1

  This core insight remains a background for the development

  of Kant’s moral philosophy, even if he eventual y dismissed the

  specificities of his theory of extraterrestrial intelligence in the third part of this speculative work and consented to its suppression within

  his own lifetime. In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant writes: I should not hesitate to stake my all on the truth of the

  proposition – that, at least, some one of the planets, which we

  see, is inhabited. Hence I say that I have not merely the opinion,

  but the strong belief, on the correctness of which I would stake

  even many of the advantages of life, that there are inhabitants in

  other worlds.2

  We also have a passage towards the end of the Critique of Practical Reason, where Kant suggests that were it not for the moral law within each man, his perishable physical being as an animal creature

  alone would render him insignificant in the face of the vastness of

  the cosmos. It is the fact that the heavens are populated by beings

  capable of acting on the moral law that renders contemplation of

  the vastness of the heavens edifying, rather than cause for a sense of 1 Michael J. Crowe, The Extraterrestrial Life Debate: Antiquity to 1915 (University of Notre Dame, 2009), 149.

  2 Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998), A 825 / B 853.

  169

  lovers of sophia

  terrifying absurdity. Significantly, the first lines of this passage from the Second Critique, are quoted on Kant’s tombstone:3

  Two things fill the mind with ever new and increasing admiration

  and awe, the oftener and more steadily they are reflected on: the

  starry heavens above me and the moral law within me... The former...

  broadens the connection in which I stand into an unbounded

  magnitude of worlds beyond worlds and systems of systems... The

  former view of a countless multitude of worlds annihilates, as it

  were, my importance as an animal creature, which must give back

  to the planet (a mere speck in the universe) the matter from which

  it came.4

  Now, bearing in mind Kant’s firm belief in a plurality of worlds,

  let us return to the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals and trace the line of argument that leads to his definition of rational

  beings as beings the existence of which is in an end in itself. Kant

  begins by arguing that it is inherent to the idea of duty, and of moral law, that it holds not only for human beings, but for all rational

  beings. Consequently, whatever the ground of ethical obligation

  may be, it cannot be sought in empirical y conditioned human

  nature. Anthropology is only useful in humans’ application of moral

  rules effectively in the conduct of their daily lives.5 Thus an action from duty must set aside or even run against all inclinations, or

  habitual sensual desires. The will of rational beings must be able

  to be determined objectively solely by the law and subjectively by

  pure respect for the law.6 This law must not be derived from any

  special tendency of human reason. This point is emphasized by

  characterizing it as an objective principle on which we would be

  directed to act even if it went against the grain of “every propensity, inclination, and natural tendency of ours (i.e. of we homo sapiens)”.7

  3 Crowe,

  The Extraterrestrial Life Debate, 151.

  4 Immanuel Kant, “Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals” in Practical Philosophy (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 5:161.

  5 Ibid., 4:389.

  6 Ibid., 4:400-401.

  7 Ibid., 4:425, my emphasis.

  170

  jason reza jorjani

  For it to do so would only render the command in a duty more

  sublime and dignified, according to Kant, while taking nothing away

  from its validity. After having stripped away all inclinations and or

  motives relevant only to human sensibility, nothing can be left other

  than action in conformity with the universal law itself – a law whose

  representation must determine the will without regard for any effect that could be the object of desire.8 It is at this point that Kant first introduces the Categorical Imperative: I ought never to act except in such a way that I could also will that my maxim should become a

  universal law.

  Kant goes on to claim that this requires us to accept that no

  possible experience could be grounds for inferring an apodictic,

  universal law of this kind. Given his reiteration that such a law must hold for all rational beings, the implication here is probably that the conditions for subjective experience could be radical y different for

  non-human rational beings. Kant also makes reference to a passage

  from the Gospels, Matthew 9:17, in which Jesus asserts that even

  the example of his life is not sufficient for inferring the goodness of God. Kant claims that reason frames apriori the idea of God as the

  supreme good, and that it is real y an idea of moral perfection.9

  All moral concepts grounded in reason apriori are as present

  in the most common reason as they are in the highest degree of

  speculative reason.10 This further circumscribes the idea of a rational being as such, by asserting that one cannot be a rational being by

  degrees. One either is or is not a rational being capable of adhering to the moral law. This prepares us for the following claim, namely that,

  not only is the moral law unconditioned by any human sensibilities,

  but in order to hold for all rational beings, moral laws must not

  be derived from any empirical y contingent cognitions pertaining

  to the special nature of human reason. Whether by the latter Kant means a generic rational faculty geared to function in the context of

  human sensibilities, or some distinctly human cognitive faculty that

  8 Ibid., 4:402.

  9 Ibid., 4:408-409.

  10 Ibid., 4:11.

  171

  lovers of sophia

  is a variation on the theme of rational faculties in general, either way this further criterion requires Kant to seek “the universal concept of a rational being as such”.11 Only then can we real y understand what

  a Categorical Imperative is, or wherein its ground lies.

  Ever
ything in nature works according to laws. What is unique

  about those beings that are rational, is that they have the capacity to act in accordance with their representation of these laws. If the will of a rational being were perfectly determined by reason, then that

  being would have a perfectly good – or “holy” – wil . However, in a

  being whose will is not perfectly determined by reason, actions that

  are cognized as objectively necessary are imperatives, or commands of reason – they indicate an “ought”. (There would be no “ought” for

  a “holy” being.) Imperatives are either hypothetical or categorical.

  Hypothetical imperatives are those that command actions

  undertaken toward some other end, actions which are means toward some end beyond themselves, whereas the Categorical Imperative would be an action represented as objectively necessary in-itself.12

  We cannot know in advance what the content of a hypothetical

  imperative may be, but we always already know what a Categorical

  Imperative will contain, since it cannot be limited by any empirical

  condition, the maxim of action under the Categorical Imperative

  conforms solely to the universality of law as such. This universal

  lawgiving is what the Categorical Imperative represents as necessary.

  Kant argues that this means that there is, strictly speaking, only a single Categorical Imperative: act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can also will that it become a universal law.13

  Now we are very close to Kant’s definition of a rational being as

  a being the existence of which is an end in itself. The move towards

  that definition comes through consideration of the type of ends

  at which the two kinds of imperative aim. Subjective ends rest on incentives. They are material ends in the sense that they can be

  effects of one’s actions. These are consequently only the grounds

  11 Ibid., 4:412.

  12 Ibid., 4:412-14.

  13 Ibid., 4:420-21.

  172

  jason reza jorjani

  of hypothetical imperatives. All of these are only relative. On the other hand, objective ends hold for every rational being. It is at this point that, in order to define an objective end, Kant rhetorical y asks whether there could be something: “the existence of which in itself has an absolute worth, something which as an end in itself could be a ground of determinate laws.”14 He claims that the ground of a

 

‹ Prev