Lovers of Sophia

Home > Other > Lovers of Sophia > Page 23
Lovers of Sophia Page 23

by Jason Reza Jorjani


  happiness are empirical and derived from experience. Kant claims

  that “for the idea of happiness there is required an absolute whole,

  a maximum of well being in my present condition and in every

  future condition.”44 He argues that nothing short of an omniscient

  and omnipotent being could form a determinate concept of what he

  real y wil s here. He criticizes various ideas of happiness, showing

  why each of them is subject to unintended negative consequences

  that would call into question whether to will this would be to will true happiness. Kant goes on to assert that “the human being claims for

  himself a wil ” only in so far as he disregards all desires and sensible incitements.45 The rest of this passage makes a thoroughly confused

  argument, which lapses into something close to antinomian Gnostic

  dualism:

  ...reason alone, and indeed pure reason independent of

  sensibility, gives the law, and, in addition... since it is... as

  intelligence only, that [the rational being] is his proper self (as

  a human being he is only the appearance of himself), those

  laws apply to him immediately and categorical y, so that what

  inclinations and impulses (hence the whole nature of the world of

  sense) incite him to cannot infringe upon the laws of his volition

  as intelligence; indeed, he does not hold himself accountable for

  the former or ascribe them to his proper self, that is, to his wil ,

  though he does ascribe to it the indulgence he would show them

  if he allowed them to influence his maxims to the detriment of

  the rational laws of his wil .

  If the “wil ” is nothing other than law-giving reason itself – which,

  as we can see, Kant is already tacitly asserting at least in this passage of the Groundwork – then based upon what ground can the rational 44 Kant, “Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals” in Practical Philosophy, 4:418.

  45 Ibid., 4:457.

  181

  lovers of sophia

  subject show indulgence to sensible inclinations and impulses? The

  problem is that, in the Groundwork, Kant also wants to maintain that this will is “his”, i.e. the rational subject’s, whereas it is, in fact, a generic Will and not one that can be the causal source of actions

  for which persons may be held individual y responsible. Although

  Kant claims that “freedom... signifies only a ‘something’ that is left over when I have excluded from the determining grounds of my will

  everything belonging to the world of sense”, the preceding passage

  demonstrates that this exclusion leaves the subject with no grounds

  to be responsible for his failure to adhere to the moral law.46

  In the Critique of Practical Reason Kant maintains this opposition to any object of the faculty of desire, and its attendant “intervening feeling of pleasure or displeasure”, as mediating reason’s lawgiving.47

  Reason, which is to say Wil , gives the law directly. Of course, as we have seen this is incoherent, because there would be no way to hold

  a person responsible for not abiding by the moral law, since Will/

  Law either determines his action or brute sensible inclinations do.

  Nevertheless, not realizing this, and continuing to refer to action

  determined directly by Will as “free wil ”,48 Kant makes an argument

  that a principle, any principle, in which one may take “pleasure or

  displeasure (which can always be cognized only empirical y and

  cannot be valid in the same way for all rational beings)” cannot serve as a practical law, but only as a subjective maxim.49 [In the language of the Groundwork, it is fit for a hypothetical but not a Categorical Imperative.] He further claims that all material practical principles

  of this kind are real y variations on the general principle of self-love or concern with one’s own happiness – which is obviously not fit for

  universal law-giving, because the “own happiness” of each person

  can only ever be his own.50 Most significantly, according to the

  Kant of the Second Critique, this includes the desire for “universal 46 Ibid., 4:462.

  47 Kant, “Critique of Practical Reason” in Practical Philosophy, 5:21; 5:25.

  48 Ibid., 5:29.

  49 Ibid., 5:21-22.

  50 Ibid., 5:22.

  182

  jason reza jorjani

  happiness”.51 Although “the happiness of other beings” can be the

  object of the will of a rational being following the moral law, and

  although “every volition must also have an object and hence a

  matter”, even universal happiness cannot act “as a condition of

  its possibility” – in other words as what furnishes a maxim fit for

  universal law-giving.52

  What seems to change in the Metaphysics of Morals, is that the matter of the desire for the happiness of others (and for one’s own

  perfection) is no longer only allowed to be added to the mere form

  of law, but is in fact presupposed in any ethical action of a rational being adhering to moral law. What allows for this change is Kant’s

  realization that unlike other objects of the faculty of desire, the

  ends of the happiness of others and one’s own perfection are not

  incentives to some other end, they are incentives to their pursuit as

  ends in themselves shared by all and only rational beings.53 These

  ends that are in themselves duties54 and that provide a matter of

  the power of choice55 fit for universal law-giving because they are

  shared by everyone,56 are another instance of “an end in itself” of

  rational beings that we encounter in Kant. Are the happiness of

  others and one’s own perfection different ends in themselves, or

  are they somehow the same as the Groundwork idea of “an end in itself” with respect to the existence of beings? How is it that what, in the Groundwork, would have been a “subjective end” that is merely a means to be used by a rational being as a matter of preference57

  has now become an – or the – “objective end”? In the Groundwork, the only “objective ends” are rational beings themselves, qua their

  51 Ibid., 5:26.

  52 Ibid., 5:33-34.

  53 Kant, “Metaphysics of Morals” in Practical Philosophy, 6:222.

  54 Ibid., 6:381.

  55 Ibid., 6:380-81; 6:389.

  56 Ibid., 6:395.

  57 Kant, “Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals” in Practical Philosophy, 4:427-28.

  183

  lovers of sophia

  existence.58 Kant was emphatic there that no other end, to which they would serve merely as a means, could ever be put in their place.

  So have the happiness of others and one’s own perfection replaced

  rational beings as the ends in themselves?

  There is a passage at 4:430 in the Groundwork that suggests

  that Kant conceived of the pursuit of one’s own perfection and the

  happiness of others (which in turn allows them to pursue their

  own perfection) as already inherent in his original concept of

  the rational being existing as an end in itself. In this passage Kant claims that there is a predisposition towards attainment of greater

  perfection in humanity (by which he means universal humanitas, not homo sapiens), and that while humanity would be preserved

  if this were neglected, adherence to the Categorical Imperative

  respecting rational beings (including oneself) as ends in themselves

  requires one to actively further one’s own perfection. He also

  claims that, while humanity would
subsist if no one sought the

  happiness of others, but did not intentional y compromise their

  happiness, treating others as ends in themselves demands also

  furthering the ends of others to the extent possible. The problem is

  that the universal law formula, as it appears in the Groundwork, is insufficient for this ethical acceptance of the well being of others as one’s own end. It would allow for no distinction between juridical

  duties enforced through state coercion and ethical duties that ought

  not to be coerced and that are ethical only insofar as one performs them for their own sake.59 Distinguishing the will from the power of

  choice and allowing for one’s own perfection and the happiness of

  others to be a material determining ground, not of the wil , but of

  the power of choice, allows for this distinction to be drawn between

  ius and ethica.

  58 Ibid., 4:428.

  59 Kant, “Metaphysics of Morals” in Practical Philosophy, 6:220.

  184

  jason reza jorjani

  III.

  Kant’s jurisprudential Doctrine of Right may consist almost entirely

  of acquired rights, but it is nonetheless grounded on a single inherent Natural Right: “the sum of the conditions under which the choice of

  one can be united with the choice of another in accordance with a

  universal law of freedom.”60 Or put otherwise: “Any action is right if... on its maxim, the freedom of choice of each can coexist with

  everyone’s freedom in accordance with a universal law.”61 On this

  definition of the Natural Right to reciprocal y respected Freedom,

  coercion is justified if it aims to prevent one person from coercing

  another person who is not doing anything that would interfere with

  his own freedom:

  If then my action or condition general y can coexist with the

  freedom of everyone in accordance with a universal law, whoever

  hinders me in it does me wrong... if a certain use of freedom is itself a hindrance to freedom in accordance with universal laws,

  coercion that is opposed to this (as a hindering of a hindrance of freedom) is... right.62

  Note the word “coexist” here. A case could be made that it is referring to the same “existence” at issue in rational beings existing as ends in themselves, that it is their coexistence as a “kingdom of ends”. The Natural Right to Freedom, as an inherent right, should apply to the

  coexistence of all rational beings. In other words, it is the basis of a political system that could rightly govern both terrestrial humans

  and any possible types of extraterrestrial intelligence.

  What is more significant though, is the following. We have just

  established that allowance of furthering the happiness of others and,

  by this means (indirectly), their perfection as well as one’s own,

  as objects of the faculty of desire, is necessary in order to prevent

  60 Ibid., 6:230.

  61 Ibid., 6:231.

  62 Ibid.

  185

  lovers of sophia

  a political system from being a totalitarian one that would destroy

  ethical duties by making all of them legal obligations to the state. The reason that Kant did not original y want to allow for this is because

  he believed that any material objects of the faculty of desire, such

  as desiring the happiness of others, presumed certain sympathetic

  sensibilities that not all rational beings may share with humans.63

  He was concerned that “a principle that is based on the subjective

  condition of receptivity to a pleasure or displeasure...can always be

  cognized only empirical y and cannot be valid in the same way for

  all rational beings”.64 Kant comes around to asserting that it would

  indeed be valid in the same way for all rational beings. In order for

  extraterrestrials to be able to have my happiness as their end, and

  indirectly to further my perfection while directly furthering their

  own, we have to presume an empirical commonality of sensory

  capabilities and physical and mental faculties capable of infinitely

  approximating themselves to, or converging on, some common

  standard of perfection. In fact, this is exactly what Kant does

  presume in the theory of extraterrestrial intelligence that he sets

  forth in the third part of his Universal Natural History and Theory of the Heavens, discussed at the outset. In sum, Kant’s apriori universal ethics requires that there be an empirical convergent evolution of

  intelligent life, not only in this universe, but in all logical y possible universes that could have been. The world of understanding does not

  just ground the world of sense,65 it is an attractor that draws rational beings initial y differentiated by their contingent encumbrances in

  the world of sense towards an increasingly refined realization of an

  underlying archetype.

  Suppose a person is born so severely handicapped and mental y

  retarded that he will never be able to use any rational faculty; i.e.

  physical y speaking, he has none. According to Kant, this unfortunate

  creature would still be a ‘person’, with an innate Natural Right

  (although perhaps with no duties obligating him). This cannot be

  63 Kant, “Critique of Practical Reason” in Practical Philosophy, 5:26.

  64 Ibid., 5:21.

  65 Ibid., 5:121.

  186

  jason reza jorjani

  because certain instrumental interventions, surgery or technological

  augmentation, could provide such a being with the capacities that

  he presently lacks. For if this were to be Kant’s response, he would

  have to admit that the same would hold true for chimpanzees, so

  that prior to such augmentation a chimpanzee would have rights in the same measure as a human born severely retarded. We must,

  therefore, conclude that this retarded ‘person’, is a ‘person’ to be

  treated in accordance with the Categorical Imperative, because his

  biological formation was unsuccessful y aiming at realization of

  some archetype. This telos cannot be a species-specific “human”

  one either, since, as the entire line of Kant’s argument demonstrates, ethical and juridical obligations are grounded in a Categorical

  Imperative common to all rational beings. That the severely retarded

  person is a person, means that all intelligent extraterrestrials must also be individuated persons; that the retarded human has rights means that he shares with all intelligent aliens an archetype

  guiding their physical evolution towards a common structural goal

  determined apriori.

  Kant’s divine “model to which all finite rational beings can only

  approximate without end”66 can no longer be thought of as purely

  abstract, if common sensibilities are required insofar as we, together with all intelligent extraterrestrials, make each other’s happiness and perfection objects of our faculty of desire. A concrete discussion

  of the evolutionary biology of possible intelligent life forms will

  help clarify the enormity of this claim implicit in Kant’s attempt to

  construct a universal ethics. Imagine a fictitious, although plausible, natural history of an intelligent life form radical y different from

  mankind. What we are trying to imagine are intelligent beings whose

  distinction from homo sapiens would be of a different order than

  the variation between human cultures. Any primate-like life form

  would be too similar to offer an instructive contrast, since
according to Kantian anthropology any hominids that behave largely as we do

  would qualify as “human” (in the narrow sense) even if they were

  the products of convergent evolution halfway across the galaxy and

  66 Ibid., 5:32.

  187

  lovers of sophia

  we could not actual y interbreed with them (even if we were sexual y

  attracted to them).

  While dolphins, whales, and even octopuses have been proven to

  be strikingly intelligent (and in the case of bottle nose dolphins, more intelligent than chimpanzees), their viscous undersea environment

  is prohibitive of the development of technology. The size of the

  avian brain is constrained by the need to maintain a lightweight

  frame for flying. Even on a planet with lower gravity, there would

  still presumably be a local economy of weight distribution. So we

  need a land-based life form capable of manipulating its natural

  environment. Reptiles have neither the requisite intelligence nor

  the proper bodily structure for tool use. Moreover, they do not

  seem to compensate for their dull-wittedness by forming any kind

  of aggregate intelligence with other members of the same species;

  even canine packs are more coordinated. On Earth, social insects

  are the one type of land based non-simian life form that is well built for manipulating the environment and that does act as a highly

  coordinated group to accomplish feats utterly impossible to its

  individual members. Incredibly rapid and astonishingly complex

  collective activities have been observed in ant colonies, beehives,

  and hornet nests. Members of these species act as if they were parts

  of a single organism. Their group intelligence is qualitatively far greater than that of any of its components. (The opposite seems true

  of human beings. While there are some highly intelligent human

  individuals, large human groups are by comparison stupid to the

  point of being self-destructive.)

  To object that such creatures have not in fact developed a

  technological society is to lose sight of the fact that for hundreds of millions of years, the only mammals on Earth were scurrying little

  rodent-like critters that were in constant danger of being eaten by

  dinosaurs and birds. It is not beyond the pale to imagine that if we

  were to cause a mass extinction of ourselves and other large species,

 

‹ Prev