Book Read Free

Not Born Yesterday

Page 25

by Hugo Mercier


  sending £350 mil ion a week to Brussels that could be redirected

  to the health ser vices instead (in fact, the number is nowhere near

  that high, and most of the money goes back to the United King-

  dom anyway).9 But fake news, which has always existed in one

  form or another, was seen as particularly threatening this time

  around because social media had vastly expanded its reach.10 In

  the three months leading up to Donald Trump’s election, the

  twenty most popu lar fake news stories related to the election gar-

  nered more than eight mil ion shares, comments, and likes on

  Facebook.11 Among the most popu lar fake news were stories

  about Hil ary Clinton, Trump’s opponent, sel ing weapons to the

  terrorists of ISIS, or the pope endorsing Trump. Through the

  sharing of fake news, and of partisan news more generally, social

  media have been accused of creating echo chambers that amplify

  people’s prejudices and polarize the population, leading to ex-

  treme po liti cal views.12

  What do the humoral theory of disease, blood libels, and

  Trump’s endorsement by Pope Francis have in common? Obvi-

  ously, they are inaccurate pieces of information. They are also

  linked with outcomes ranging from the clearly terrible (ethnic

  attacks, the systematic mistreatment of patients) to the arguably

  suboptimal (Trump’s election, Brexit). It would be natu ral to

  think that these false beliefs led directly to the outcomes de-

  scribed: physicians practice bloodletting because they accept

  the humoral theory of disease; ethnic minorities are massacred

  because of the atrocities they are accused of committing; people

  vote the “wrong” way because they are misled by fake news.

  202 ch ap t er 13

  If this were the case, we would be dealing with very grave fail-

  ures of our open vigilance mechanisms, in which people would

  have been persuaded to accept the misleading ideas of influen-

  tial physicians, rumormongers, and fake news purveyors. Unlike

  some of the beliefs described in the previous chapters, these mis-

  leading ideas would have dramatic consequences not only for

  others but also for those who hold them: physicians who ask to

  be bled, perpetrators of ethnic vio lence who get hurt, and people

  who end up voting against their interests.

  In this chapter, I argue that this account gets the direction of

  causality wrong. By and large, it is not because the population

  hold false beliefs that they make misguided or evil decisions, but

  because the population seek to justify making misguided or evil

  decisions that they hold false beliefs. If Voltaire is often para-

  phrased as saying, “ Those who can make you believe absurdities

  can make you commit atrocities,” this is in fact rarely true.13 As

  a rule, it is wanting to commit atrocities that makes you believe

  absurdities.

  Every body Bleeds

  Reading David Wootton’s Bad Medicine was an eye- opening

  experience, revealing how until around a century ago doctors

  were not only useless but positively harmful, and arousing my

  interest in bloodletting.14 How could this practice have been

  accepted for so long? My initial reaction was to trace it back

  through the great physicians who had defended it, from Ben-

  jamin Rush in nineteenth- century Amer ica to the Hippocratic

  writers in ancient Greece. A specific link in this chain was

  fascinating: from the eleventh century onward, hundreds

  of thousands of people would be bled because a couple of

  Galenic manuscripts on the humoral theory of disease sur-

  f u t il e fa k e ne w s 203

  vived down the centuries to reach the first Eu ro pean medical

  schools.

  But as I started looking into the anthropological lit er a ture, I

  was quickly disabused of my Western- centric views. Far from

  being a historical anomaly, bloodletting was practiced all around

  the globe, by people who had never heard of Rush, Galen, or the

  Hippocratic writers. The Guna (Panama and Colombia) used a

  miniature bow to shoot a miniature arrow into the temple of

  those suffering from headaches. When someone complained of

  headaches, abscesses, or chest pain, the Bagisu (Uganda) sucked

  a bit of blood from the ailing area with a hollowed horn. The Iban

  (Malaysia) cut a small incision in the back when someone was

  afflicted with back pain. The Dayak (Borneo) relied on a heated

  bamboo to draw blood from any ailing part of the body. Blood-

  letting was also practiced by major non- Western civilizations,

  playing a role in ancient Indian and Chinese medicine.15

  All in all, at least a quarter of the world’s cultures likely prac-

  ticed some form of bloodletting at some point in their history.

  In some of them— ancient Greece, ancient China— the practice

  was accompanied by complex theoretical explanations. In most,

  however, people were content with a cursory “ We’ve got to let

  the bad stuff out.”16 If the humoral theory of disease can’t explain

  why bloodletting spread in 99 percent of cultures, which have

  never heard of humors, it does not explain either why it spread

  in the cultures that embraced the humoral theory. Galen devel-

  oped sophisticated theories to justify something people wanted

  to do anyway: when they are sick or in pain, let a bit of blood flow

  to evacuate hy po thet ical internal pollutants.

  If bloodletting can be found throughout the world without its

  Western trapping, the humoral theory, by contrast, rumors of

  atrocities seem to be a standard component of the ethnic riot,

  suggesting that these rumors play a significant causal role.17 In

  204 ch ap t er 13

  fact, the arrow of causality is unlikely to point in this direction,

  as there is little fit between the rumors and the vio lence. We find

  countless instances of rumors not followed by any vio lence, and

  when vio lence does happen, its nature is typically unrelated in

  form or degree to the content of the rumors.

  When the Jewish population of Kishinev was accused of the

  murder of a small boy, the lie took hold because people broadly

  believed this ritual to be “part and parcel of Jewish practice.”18

  Indeed, alarming rumors surfaced every year before Easter, with-

  out any attendant pogrom.19 Shouldn’t this strike us as bizarre?

  Who harbors in their midst people suspected of periodically kid-

  napping children to bleed them to death? That the same beliefs

  did not lead to vio lence most of the time suggests the beliefs

  themselves do not explain why the vio lence erupted when it did.

  If the local Christian population in Kishinev had genuinely

  believed in the blood libel, we might have expected some terri-

  ble reprisal, maybe the murdering of Jewish children, or of the

  adults thought to be guilty. The reprisal is terrible indeed, but it

  bears no relation to the accusations: How is pillaging liquor

  stores going to avenge the dead child? In other times and places,

  Jewish populations have been massacred, women molested,

  wealth plund
ered under vastly flimsier pretexts, such as accusa-

  tions of desecrating the host. Even in Kishinev, the allegations

  piled up with no sense of proportionality, from kil ing children

  to dishonest business practices: “ Those awful Jews. They bleed

  our children to death. And they cheat us on the change!” By and

  large, scholars of rumors and of ethnic riots concur that “partici-

  pants in a crowd seek justifications for a course of action that is

  already under way; rumors often provide the ‘facts’ that sanction

  what they want to do anyway.”20

  What about fake news, then? Can it sway momentous po liti-

  cal decisions? Here I focus on the election of Donald Trump, the

  f u t il e fa k e ne w s 205

  event for which the most data are available. At the individual

  level, there was a correlation between viewing fake news web-

  sites, which overwhelmingly supported Trump, and being a

  Trump supporter.21 At the state level, the more people visited

  fake news websites, the more likely the state was to vote for

  Trump.22 Does this mean that viewing fake news prompted

  people to vote for Trump? Not necessarily. The majority of

  people who visited fake news websites weren’t casual Republi-

  cans but “intense partisans,” “the 10% of people with the most

  conservative online information diets.”23 These people were very

  unlikely to have turned from Hil ary voters to Trump support-

  ers. Instead, they were scouting the web— not only fake news

  websites but also the traditional press— for ways of justifying

  their upcoming decision to vote for Trump, or of demonstrat-

  ing their support.24

  A study by Brendan Nyhan and his colleagues supports this

  interpretation.25 Trump supporters were provided with accurate

  information correcting some of Trump’s false statements (rather

  than fake news, but the princi ple is the same). Most of them ac-

  cepted the corrections. Yet the supporters didn’t waver in their

  support for Trump. This suggests that the initial ac cep tance of

  the false statements hadn’t caused their support for Trump.

  Rather, they had accepted the statements because they supported

  Trump.

  Po liti cal scientists Jin Woo Kim and Eunji Kim observed a

  similar pattern when they studied the rumors that Barack Obama

  is a Muslim, which circulated prior to the 2008 presidential elec-

  tion pitting Obama against John McCain.26 Kim and Kim com-

  pared the answers to two waves of po liti cal surveys: one taken

  before the rumors started to spread, and one after they had

  peaked. The researchers found that the rumors did have an ef-

  fect: they made people more likely to say Obama is a Muslim.

  206 ch ap t er 13

  However, this was only true for people who were already inclined

  to dislike Obama. As a result, the rumors had no effect on

  people’s general attitude toward Obama, or on the likelihood of

  voting for him: accepting the rumor didn’t make people dislike

  Obama; disliking Obama made people accept the rumor.

  A Reason for Every thing

  If people are going to do what ever they want anyway— from

  practicing bloodletting to attacking their neighbors— why would

  they bother with a variety of absurd and inert beliefs? Humans

  are an uber- social species, constantly evaluating each other to

  figure out who would make the best cooperation partners: who

  is competent, who is nice, who is reliable. As a result, we’re keen

  to look our best, at least to people whose opinions we value.

  Unfortunately, we’re bound to do things that look stupid or

  morally dubious. When this happens, we attempt to justify our

  actions and explain why they weren’t, in fact, stupid or mor-

  ally dubious. This lets us correct negative judgments, and it

  helps observers better understand our motives, thus judging us

  more accurately.

  We not only spontaneously justify ourselves when our be hav-

  ior is questioned but also learn to anticipate when justifications

  might be needed, before we have to actually offer them.27 This

  creates a market for justifications. But such a market arises only

  when we anticipate that some decisions are likely to be perceived

  as problematic.

  As mentioned previously, the small- scale socie ties that prac-

  tice bloodletting typically do not elaborate complex theories

  to justify the practice; it is simply seen as the obvious option

  when someone is suffering from a par tic u lar ailment. By con-

  trast, in larger or more diverse communities, alternative treat-

  f u t il e fa k e ne w s 207

  ments are sure to be in competition, and physicians as well as

  patients have an incentive to justify their decisions. This com-

  petition and the attendant debates were certainly impor tant in

  ancient Greece, where the humoral theory of disease was de-

  veloped by the Hippocratic writers.28 The same competition

  existed in Rome when Galen set up shop: it was only after his

  treatments were questioned by the local doctors that Galen

  developed a book- length defense of bloodletting, drawing

  on his Hippocratic pre de ces sors.29 In a small- scale society,

  you can practice bloodletting no questions asked, but in more

  sophisticated cultures, to go around bleeding sick people, you

  need a theory.

  As for fake news, it also flourishes, when needed, as a form of

  justification.30 In 2016, the year of the presidential election, six

  of the top ten most shared fake news stories on Facebook were

  po liti cal, from the pope’s endorsement of Trump to an ISIS lead-

  er’s endorsement of Clinton.31 By contrast, in 2017, only two of

  the top ten fake news stories were po liti cal (including a rather

  funny “Female Legislators Unveil ‘Male Ejaculation Bil ’ Forbid-

  ding the Disposal of Unused Semen”).32 Furthermore, more

  than 80 percent of fake news related to the 2016 elections was

  pro- Trump, and conservatives were more likely to share fake

  news on social media.33 The abundance of pro- Trump fake news

  is explained by the dearth of pro- Trump material to be found in

  the traditional media: not a single major newspaper endorsed his

  candidacy (although there was plenty of material critical of Clin-

  ton as well). At this point, I should stress that the extent to

  which fake news is shared is commonly exaggerated: during the

  2016 election campaign, fewer than one in ten Facebook users

  shared fake news, and 0.1 percent of Twitter users were respon-

  sible for sharing 80 percent of the fake news found on that

  platform.34

  208 ch ap t er 13

  Some po liti cal fake news— for instance, “WikiLeaks: Clinton

  Bribed 6 Republicans to ‘Destroy Trump’ ”— might sound plau-

  sible enough, at least to people with little knowledge of politics;

  that is, most of the electorate. But many stories would presum-

  ably sound quite absurd to almost every body (e.g., “[Evangeli-

  cal leader Franklin] Graham Says Christians Must Support

  Trump or Face Death Camps”). In this
re spect, po liti cal fake

  news resembles other fake news. In 2017, the biggest hit was “Baby-

  sitter Transported to Hospital after Inserting a Baby in Her Va-

  gina”; in 2016, the runner-up was “ Woman Arrested for Defecat-

  ing on Boss’ Desk after Winning the Lottery.”35 As suggested by

  cultural evolution researcher Alberto Acerbi, the most implau-

  sible fake news stories, whether or not they are po liti cal, spread

  largely because they are entertaining rather than because they

  offer justifications for anything.36 The most absurd po liti cal fake

  news stories might also owe their appeal precisely to their over-

  the- top nature, as they make for great burning-bridges material

  (see chapter 12).

  Whence Polarization?

  When a piece of information is seen as a justification, we can af-

  ford to evaluate it only superficially, as it will have little or no

  influence on what we believe or do—by virtue of being post hoc.

  This being the case, however, we should observe no changes at

  all, not even a strengthening of views. After all, a strengthening

  of our views is as much of a change as a weakening, and should

  require equally strong evidence. Yet it has been regularly ob-

  served that piling up justifications reinforces our views and in-

  creases polarization. In an experiment, people had to say how

  much they liked someone they had just listened to for two min-

  utes.37 This confederate appeared, by design, either pleasant or

  f u t il e fa k e ne w s 209

  unpleasant. Participants who had to wait a couple of minutes

  before rating the confederate provided more extreme evaluations

  than people who answered immediately after hearing the con-

  federate speak. During these extra minutes, participants had con-

  jured up justifications for their immediate reaction, making it

  more extreme.38

  A similar tendency toward polarization has been observed

  in discussion groups. In a study, American students were first

  asked their stance on foreign policy.39 Doves— people who gen-

  eral y oppose military intervention— were put together in small

  groups and asked to discuss foreign policy. When their attitudes

  were mea sured after the exchange, they had become more extreme

  in their opposition to military intervention. Experiments that

  look at the content of the discussions taking place in like- minded

  groups show that it is chiefly the accumulation of arguments on

 

‹ Prev