Book Read Free

Why Nationalism

Page 4

by Yael Tamir


  ing for their position in the front; the winning ones are on the

  defense. If there is a lesson to be learned from the last hundred

  years, it is that nothing ends or begins as abruptly as it seems.

  Ideologies don’t die out or disappear; they put on new garments,

  some makeup, adopt new slogans, and come back in a new

  guise. Ideological debates are, therefore, here to stay.

  It is for the reader to decide whether this is good or bad news.

  It certainly reassures political theorists that in the foreseeable

  future they will not be out of work. A time- worn Jewish story

  Never Say Never • 21

  summarizes their situation wel . A man comes to the rabbi look-

  ing for a job. The rabbi suggests he should sit at the nearest

  crossroads. “And what will I do?” asks the man. “You will wait

  for the Messiah, and when he comes make sure he doesn’t skip

  over our little town.” “And how much will I earn?” “The pay,” says

  the rabbi, “is modest but the job is permanent.”

  3

  Untidy Compromises

  The history of the last century teaches us that in the ideological

  world there are few victories and defeats; as circumstances

  change, ideas plunge and surface. A captivating image of this re-

  ality is offered by Michael Freeden,1 who uses the analogy of

  pieces of furniture arranged in a room, each time in a different

  order according to the owner’s taste. At times, freedom or au-

  tonomy occupy the central space, at others they are shoved to

  the background, replaced by other ideas like solidarity or com-

  munity. Some balance between the old and the new will save us

  from making the most dangerous mistake of all: taking ideas, at-

  tractive as they may be, to their logical ends, or, to carry on the

  analogy, emptying the room of all but one kind of furniture.

  One of the purposes of this book is to remind ourselves that

  one- sided political theories are bound to lead to moral and po-

  litical calamities and to encourage a search for a set of compro-

  mises that fit the needs of our age.2 We have a lot to learn from

  the failures and successes of the last century; the most impor-

  tant lesson of all is to be more critical of our own beliefs and more

  open to those of others. In what follows, two of the leading ide-

  ologies of the last century, liberal democracy and nationalism,

  are reviewed; from each of them, worthwhile human values and

  social strategies are exerted. Neither is dismissed by identifying

  it with its most extreme expressions: brutal neoliberalism on the

  one hand, Nazism and fascism on the other.

  Untidy

  Compromises • 23

  Balancing different ideas is a necessary moral and political

  skil . In the wise words of Sir Isaiah Berlin, given the variety of

  human needs that pull in different directions, the only way for-

  ward is by constantly searching for:

  some logically untidy, flexible, and even ambiguous compromise.

  Every situation calls for its own specific policy, since out of the

  crooked timber of humanity, as Kant once remarked, no straight

  thing was ever made. What the age calls for is not (as we are often

  told) more faith, or stronger leadership, or more scientific organi-

  zation. Rather it is the opposite— less Messianic ardor, more en-

  lightened skepticism, more toleration of idiosyncrasies, more

  frequent ad hoc measures to achieve aims in a foreseeable future,

  more room for attainment of their personal ends by individuals and

  by minorities whose tastes and beliefs find (whether rightly or

  wrongly must not matter) little response among the majority.3

  Political theory seeks bearable, livable concessions. This is

  why political deliberations are so important. They provide us

  with an opportunity to think and act, allowing for active social

  and political participation. If no one true answer could be revealed

  by either rational deliberation or religious epiphany, political free-

  dom is essential. We must therefore keep engaging with a wide

  range of worthwhile ideas drawn from different (sometimes con-

  flicting) political theories, borrowing from each of them valuable

  insights and words of caution, thus creating a sphere of common

  discourse from which a more balanced set of practices can emerge.

  Many may wonder: should nationalism be included in this

  balancing act? In order to answer this question I draw out some

  of the valuable and constructive aspects of nationalism, arguing

  that they reflect a scope of human needs and aspirations that

  should be considered. I do not attempt to beautify nationalism;

  I am well aware of its harmful aspects and destructive powers

  24 • Chapter

  3

  (much has been written on these issues, and readers can find a

  better analysis elsewhere). In this text I wish to present the case

  for nationalism, trying to highlight its importance in any future

  social construct.

  Like every other idea, nationalism can be pulled in different

  directions. At its worst it has a devastating and destructive power;

  at its best, it is one of the most constructive and creative political

  forces. We should then try and benefit, as much as possible,

  from the national experience while keeping our eyes wide open

  to the risks that lie ahead. My defense of nationalism is therefore

  conditional, but political theory misses a lot when out of fear of

  the extreme it ignores ideas essential for our collective future.

  Why nationalism now? In the developed world two related

  processes transformed the social and political landscape: the po-

  litical pendulum swung too far to the individualist pole, leaving

  behind generations suffering from social alienation and anonym-

  ity, while the economic balance tilted too far to the free- market

  side, leaving too many individuals vulnerable. These transforma-

  tions raise new challenges and call for new responses.

  Political theory asks eternal questions, but its answers are con-

  text related. As the great American philosopher John Rawls

  taught us, even behind the “veil of ignorance” individuals must

  know general facts about their society. They must:

  understand political affairs and the principles of economic theory;

  know the basis of social organization and the law of human psychol-

  ogy. Indeed the parties are presumed to know whatever general

  facts affect the choice of the principles of justice.4

  What are these facts? What are the basic organizing principles

  of our society? Was the last half decade one of progress or re-

  gress? There is no lack of facts, yet we look at these facts through

  an ideological and institutional prism. While many are now

  Untidy

  Compromises • 25

  captivated with the issue of “fake news” and “fact checking,” it is

  difficult to admit that some of the most basic social and economic

  facts remain contestable, and that some of the most firm political

  debates are grounded in our inability to agree on a description of

  the present state of affairs.
With this remark in mind it may be less

  obvious who is a reactionary and who is a social critic.

  The two kinds of nationalism presented in this book chal enge

  the present political paradigms and dare to demand that we re-

  visit the facts we know, as we have followed a one- sided inter-

  pretation of the social and economic developments. One of the

  chapters in Joseph E. Stiglitz’s book The Price of Inequality: How

  Today’s Divided Society Endangers Our Future 5 is captivatingly

  titled “1984 Is Upon Us.” In clear prose Stiglitz demonstrates

  how the 1 percent has used its advantages “to alter perceptions and

  achieve its aim— to make our inequality less than it is and more

  acceptable than it should be.” This is well known to anyone who

  ever read Marx or Gramsci; the ruling classes control not only

  the material means of production but also the intellectual ones,

  allowing them to present their positions as a universal truth. The

  social and political outcomes of intentional misrepresentation

  of facts are often devastating. Many of the recent events that took

  the world by surprise could have been prevented if the accumu-

  lating evidence refuting the ruling paradigm would have been

  more thoroughly evaluated.

  It takes disruptive moments like the one we live in to force

  individuals to examine the match between their social concep-

  tions and the present social and economic actualities and rethink

  their beliefs. It’s time for political theory to admit that reality

  developed in surprising ways, hence the terms of the social and

  political debate must be altered, justice lies no longer on one side

  of the theoretical fence, and different voices must be given a place

  around the discussion table.

  4

  The Two Faces of Janus

  Nationalism is a deceptive ideology; one of its faces looks to the

  past, the other looks to the future. Hence, the tendency to iden-

  tify nationalism solely with reactionary views, overlooking its

  modernizing and liberating powers, represents a deep misunder-

  standing of the modern world, or maybe it’s no more than a

  polemic stand meant to debunk nationalism, pushing it out of

  the political playing field.

  Negative descriptions of nationalism that emphasize its

  backward- looking face are very common: Karl Popper described

  nationalism as a regressive force, a revolt against the open soci-

  ety, an emotive power that “appeals to our tribal instincts, to pas-

  sion and to prejudice, and to our nostalgic desire to be relieved

  from the strain of individual responsibility which it attempts to

  replace by a collective or group responsibility.”1

  Indeed, nationalism often tries to revive (or invent) an image

  of a magnificent past. Seeing the past in all its splendor, Marc Lil a

  argues, places the reactionary “in a stronger position than his ad-

  versary because he believes he is the guardian of what actually

  happened, not the prophet of what might be. . . . And the reac-

  tionaries of our time have discovered that nostalgia can be a pow-

  erful political motivator perhaps even more powerful than

  hope. Hope can be disappointed. Nostalgia is irrefutable.”2

  While this may be a good definition of reactionaries, one must

  be careful not to conflate a criticism of the present with a desire to

  The Two Faces of Janus • 27

  go back to some imaginary glorious past. Criticizing the current

  social order, claiming that some things have gone fundamentally

  wrong or worked better in the past, isn’t necessarily nostalgia; it

  can be a mere fact. Describing a certain trend of social criticism

  as nostalgia is tantamount to dismissing it without ever examin-

  ing the content of its claims. This is particularly problematic

  when the dismissal is voiced by those who benefit from the pres-

  ent state of affairs rather than by those who are harmed by it.

  Despite its conservative image, when examining the history

  of nationalism, one of its most fascinating features is its modern-

  izing powers. The basic characteristic of the modern nation and

  everything connected with it, writes Eric Hobsbawm in the pref-

  ace to his seminal book on nationalism, “is its modernity.”3 He

  goes on to argue that at the end of the nineteenth century and

  the beginning of the twentieth the only historically justifiable

  nationalism was that which fitted with progress that “enlarged

  rather than restricted the scale on which human economies, so-

  cieties and cultures operated.”4

  Ernest Gellner, another highly regarded scholar of national-

  ism, makes a similar claim:

  Nationalism is not the awakening of an old, latent, dormant force,

  though that is how it does indeed present itself. It is in reality the

  consequence of a new form of social organization, based on deeply

  internalized, education- dependent high culture, each protected by

  its own state.5

  Despite its romantic and nostalgic appearance, he adds, nation-

  alism is integral to modernity and progress; it was born in the

  bosom of the industrial society, which is

  the only society ever to live by and rely on sustained and perpetual

  growth, on an expected and continuous improvement. Not

  28 • Chapter

  4

  surprisingly, it was the first society to invent the concept and ideal

  of progress. . . . Many societies in the past have on occasion discov-

  ered innovations and improved their lot, and sometimes it may even

  be true that improvements came not as single spies but in battal-

  ions. But the improvement was never perpetual, never expected to

  be so.6

  In her important book Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity,

  Liah Greenfeld makes the most radical claim regarding the con-

  nection between nationalism and modernity. The nation, she

  argues, is the constitutive element of modernity. “Rather than

  define nationalism by its modernity, I see modernity as defined

  by nationalism.”7

  It is therefore safe to conclude that despite the common per-

  ception of nationalism as identified with primordial, tribal feel-

  ings, the true power of nationalism in modern times is grounded

  in its ability to promote processes of modernization and indus-

  trialization that go hand in hand with the universalization of

  education, information, and technology. Although it was the

  most efficient agent of modernization, nationalism managed to

  present social and political change as an expression of fate and

  continuity. The move toward the future was to be seen as an ex-

  tension of the past, change and mobility as a stroll within the

  old family yard. Never was a mobilizing ideology marketed in

  such gentle and comforting tones, pleasing to the ears of those

  members of society for whom change and uncertainty seem a

  frightening prospect. Nationalism not only helped the process

  of political modernization, it also answered the needs of the

  modern mind. To begin with, it is grounded in concepts such as

  self- rule and self- expr
ession. Emperors and kings expect their

  subjects to be obedient; democrats demand that they become

  active political agents; nationalists aspire to induce in them the

  The Two Faces of Janus • 29

  will to use cultural and creative tools to express themselves in

  both the private and the public sphere. The modern nation- state

  thus invited individuals to partake in the political, ethical, and

  cultural sphere. Its goals were forward looking; when it looked

  back to the past, it did so in order to set goals for the future. In

  Nietzsche’s words, the vision of the past is used to kindle in in-

  dividuals “the hope that justice will yet come and happiness is

  behind the mountain they are climbing. They believe that the

  meaning of existence will become ever clearer in the course of

  its evolution, they only look backward at the process to under-

  stand the present and stimulate their longing for the future.”

  Nietzsche understood well the motivating power of a past

  constructed and made fit to produce a prototype for the

  future. History is an activating power, and nationalism made

  good use of this quality in harnessing individuals to its social and

  political goals. Identifying nationalism with a reactionary spirit

  is therefore a basic misunderstanding rather than a descriptive

  claim; it is a normative statement meant to conceal national-

  ism’s mobilizing powers.

  Another way of dismissing nationalism is by portraying it as

  an expression of a populist state of mind. Populism is such a

  vague term that it can be applied to a wide range of political

  movements. Despite their many differences, both the Tea Party

  and Occupy Wall Street are considered to be populist move-

  ments. No wonder that in 2017 the Cambridge Dictionary de-

  clared populism the word of the year, describing it as a set of

  “political ideas and activities that are intended to get the support

  of ordinary people by giving them what they want.”

  The dictionary further claims that people tend to use the term

  with reference to “the implied lack of critical thinking on the part

  of the populace, and the implied cynicism on the part of the lead-

  ers who exploit it.” In other words, populism is a political ploy

  30 • Chapter

  4

  to mobilize “ordinary people” by echoing their demands. In their

 

‹ Prev