Book Read Free

Henry Sidgwick- Eye of the Universe

Page 22

by Bart Schultz


  cb.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  perturbed by the Arnoldian tendency to drop “from the prophet of an ideal

  culture into a more or less prejudiced advocate of the actual.” Perfectionism

  of this sort could too easily become a counsel of complacency when it

  came to social reform, “always hinting at a convenient season, that rarely

  seems to arrive.” It remains effete and elite: “For what does action, social

  action, really mean? It means losing oneself in a mass of disagreeable,

  hard, mechanical details, and trying to influence many dull or careless or

  bigoted people for the sake of ends that were at first of doubtful brilliancy,

  and are continually being dimmed and dwarfed by the clouds of conflict.”

  (MEA , )

  When he returned to the subject in the nineties, his recollections of

  the old controversies were more seasoned and judicious. True, as the man

  himself admitted, Arnold was “not a systematic thinker with philosophical

  principles duly coherent and interdependent.” Consequently, “it is not

  surprising that he did not always mean the same thing by culture . . . his

  conception expanding and contracting elastically, as he passes from phase

  to phase of a long controversey.” Thus, from an earlier and more narrowly

  construed account of culture as literary culture – the “Greek and Roman

  learning” of Lord Chesterfield – Arnold had swung wildly, expanding his

  conception to cover religion and science as modes of inquiry, efforts at

  “seeing things as they really are” but inflated to deal with all dimensions

  of human perfection. And this is confusing.

  It was evident that Arnold had changed his idea; at the same time, he had not

  changed it altogether. For in subsequent essays, and even in the same essay, it is

  made clear that the method of culture is still, for Arnold, purely literary: it is

  attained by reading the best books. Now even in the latter half of the nineteenth

  century the desire to cultivate the intellect and taste by reading the best books,

  and the passion for social improvement, are not, if we look at actual facts, always

  found together; or even if we grant that the one can hardly exist without some

  degree of the others, at any rate they co-exist in different minds in very varying

  proportions. And when Arnold tells us that the Greeks had arrived, in theory at

  least, at a harmonious adjustment of the claims of both, we feel that his admiration

  for Hellenism has led him to idealise it; for we cannot but remember how Plato

  politely but firmly conducts the poets out of his republic, and how the Stoics

  sneered at Aristotle’s praises of pure speculation. In short, we might allow Arnold

  to define the aim of culture either as the pursuit of sweetness and light or, more

  comprehensively, as the pursuit of complete spiritual perfection, including the

  aim of making reason and the will of God prevail: but, in the name of culture

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  cb.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Unity

  

  itself, we must refuse to use the same word for two such different things; since

  the resulting confusion of thought will certainly impede our efforts to see things

  as they are.

  And when the alternatives are thus presented, it seems clear that usage is on the

  side of the narrower meaning. For what philanthropy is now increasingly eager

  to diffuse, under the name of culture, is something different from religion and

  morality; it is not these goods that have been withheld from the poor, nor of which

  the promotion excuses the luxurious expenditure of the rich. Poverty – except so

  far as it excludes even adequate moral instruction – is no bar to morality, as it is

  happily in men’s power to do their duty in all relations of life, under any pressure

  of outward circumstances; and it is the rich, not the poor, that the gospel warns of

  their special difficulty in entering the kingdom of heaven. Again, if the pursuit

  of culture is taken to transcend and include the aim of promoting religion and

  morality, these sublimer goods cannot but claim by far the larger share of attention.

  Indeed, Arnold himself told us, in a later essay, that at least three-fourths of human life belong to morality, and religion as supplying motive force to morality: art and

  science together can at most claim the remaining fourth. But if so, any discussion

  of the principles that should guide our effort after the improvement of the three-

  fourths of life that morality claims, of the difficulties that such effort encounters, of the methods which it has to apply – all this must inevitably lead us far away

  from the consideration of culture in the ordinary sense.

  The more encompassing vision of perfection was more in accord with

  Sidgwick’s own efforts to define “culture,” of course, but he thought that

  he was more in touch with the spirit of the age than Arnold, who, for all his

  elasticity, had never really managed the scientific attitude: “His method of

  ‘seeing things as they are’ is simply to read the best books of all ages and

  countries, and let the unimpeded play of his consciousness combine the

  results.” These were to be the “Great Books,” needless to say – the works

  of “Plato, Cicero, Machiavelli, Shakespeare, Voltaire, Goethe.” But

  imagine a man learning physical science in this way. . . . imagine a learner, desirious of seeing the starry universe as it is, set down to read the treatises of Ptoloemy,

  Copernicus, Galileo, Kepler, and so on, and let his consciousness play about them

  in an untrammelled manner; instead of learning astronomical theory from the

  latest books, and the actual method of astronomical observation in a modern

  observatory!

  Moreover,

  Man, whatever else he is, is part of the world of nature, and modern science is more

  and more resolutely claiming him as an object of investigation. . . . the intuitions

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  cb.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  of literary genius will not avail to reduce to scientific order the complicated facts of psychical experience, any more than the facts of the physical world. And this

  is no less true of those special branches of the study of social man which have

  attained a somewhat more advanced condition than the general science of society

  which, in idea, comprehends them – e.g., economics, political science, archaelogy,

  philology.

  Nor can literature of itself “establish a relation between the results of

  science and our sense of conduct and our sense of beauty,” important as

  that function is for it.

  For when we try to sati
sfy completely the demand I have just indicated, to bring

  into true and clear intellectual relations the fundamental notions of studies, so

  diverse as positive science, ethics, and the theory of the fine arts, order, coherence, system must be the special objects aimed at; and this result can only be attained by

  philosophy, whose peculiar task, indeed, it is to bring into clear, orderly, harmo-

  nious relations, the fundamental notions and methods of all special sciences and

  studies. But it is not a task which philosophy can as yet be said to have satisfactorily accomplished; the height from which all normal human aims and activities can

  be clearly and fully contemplated in true and harmonious relations, is a height

  not yet surmounted by the human mind – perhaps it never will be surmounted –

  perhaps (to change the metaphor) the face of this ideal

  “Is evermore unseen

  And fixed upon the far sea-line,”

  which changes with every advance in the endless voyaging of man’s intellect.

  Yet Sidgwick is willing to make

  a very substantial concession – that literature of the thoughtful kind, the poetry

  and eloquence that really deserves to be called a criticism of life, gives even to

  philosophers a most important part of the matter of philosophy, though it does

  not give philosophical form and order; and it gives a provisional substitute for

  philosophy to the many who do not philosophise. It gives, or helps to give, the kind

  of wide interest in, the versatile sympathy with, the whole complex manifestation

  of the human spirit in time, which is required – even if we are considering merely

  the intellectual element of culture – as a correction to the specialisation which the growth of science inexorably imposes.

  For Sidgwick, the specialist is not by virtue of expertise a person of culture;

  the “habit of taking delight in the best literature” is a crucial corrective,

  with the function of maintaining “our intellectual interests and sympathies

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  cb.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Unity

  

  in due breadth and versatility, while at the same time gratifying and exer-

  cising our sense of beauty.” In this respect, literature is special. In addition

  to being widely available – unlike Greek sculpture – it is “the most altruistic

  of the fine arts” in that “it is an important part of its function to develop

  the sensibility for other forms of beauty besides its own.”

  And Sidgwick takes the occasion to issue some very Apostolic words

  about how to acquire culture, understood as “the love of knowledge, the

  ardour of scientific curiosity,” and how “to acquire along with it the refine-

  ment of sensibility, the trained and developed taste for all manifestations

  of beauty which no less belongs to culture.” Culture, like virtue, can only

  be taught in a certain way:

  Virtue can be taught by a teacher who loves virtue, and so can culture, but not

  otherwise; since, as Goethe sings: – ‘Speech that is to stir the heart must from the

  heart have sprung.’ Experience shows that the love of knowledge and beauty can

  be communicated through intellectual sympathy: there is a beneficent contagion

  in the possession of it; but it must be admitted that its acquistion cannot be secured by any formal system of lessons. No recipe for it can be enclosed in a syllabus, nor

  can it be tested by the best regulated examinations.

  True education, in fine, has the personal touch. Nor is this necessarily

  a matter of the relationship between teacher and student, in the formal

  sense:

  So far I have spoken of culture as something to be communicated by teachers or

  acquired by solitary study. But when men of my age look back on their University

  life, and ask themselves from what sources they learnt such culture as they did

  learn, I think that most would give a high place – and some the chief place –

  to a third educational factor, the converse with fellow-students. Even if we did

  not learn most from this source, what we so learnt was learnt with most ease

  and delight; and especially the value of this converse in broadening intellectual

  interests, and keeping alive the flame of eager desire to know truth and feel beauty, is difficult to over-estimate. Indeed, this always appears to me one great reason

  why we have Universities at all, as at presented constituted.

  Perhaps many of these remarks did reflect Sidgwick’s more mature

  appreciation of what culture and education were all about. But surely

  many, many elements were consistent features of his Apostolic mind:

  the visions of inquiry, education, art, culture, and philosophy were in

  their essence the fixed points of his mental universe. There was a dis-

  tinct, continuous effort on his part to have it all – science and religion,

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  cb.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  

  Henry Sidgwick: Eye of the Universe

  self-sacrifice and self-development, philosophy and literature, aristocracy

  and democracy, quality of education and quantity of education.

  To be sure, the younger Sidgwick was more conflicted, less happily rec-

  onciled to the ongoing search for ever-receding truth. And he was clearly

  of a divided mind when it came to entering into the common mind, the

  “rustic” brain. How strange that the same person could have written to

  Symonds in , the very same year as “The Prophet of Culture”: “my

  best never comes out except when I am played upon & stirred by affection

  and subtle sympathy combined: when I do not get this, I become lethargic.

  Among the ‘dim’ common populations I seem to change and become com-

  mon.” (CWC) And in that early, Apostolic paper on “Prayer,” he had

  explained that “religion will always be beneficial and often of vital necessity

  on the one hand to natures where the emotional and passionate elements

  preponderate over the rational and active: and again to those whom con-

  stitution or fortune have depressed and saddened,” adding breezily that

  he is not going to “speak of the sensual herd of whom Religion will ever be

  the only real elevator.” Even his dear friend Noel, an aristocrat after all,

  though one with a decidedly radical bent, could during the sixties tease

  Sidgwick for tending toward a “Pseudo-Philosophy . . . that opposes itself

  to the vulgar opinion out of a kind of esoteric pride, which perchance we

  of ‘the Brotherhood’ may be peculiarly liable to.” Among other things,

  Sidgwick had wondered about the advisability of marriage, which, though

  valuable for the “inferior man,” was perhaps a drag on the “superior man”

  in his effort to identify with the “universal heart of humanity.” The just-

  married Noel’s advice ran:

  Let the mere student be content to be a mere student, all well. But let him not

  hope to
acquire a fuller sympathy with the ‘universal heart of humanity’ than the

  practical man, by the process of placing himself above or outside of humanity and

  contemplating it, (or rather contemplating his idea of it formed a priori and from

  books.) A curious sympathy will result.

  Such remarks were telling indeed, as was Noel’s advice that, if it is “not

  always by any means our duty to take ‘our largest cut’ of pleasure,” still

  “this pleasant course may be duty sometimes.”

  As later chapters will elaborate, this form of elitism was something

  that Sidgwick would strain to moderate in the years to follow, not always

  successfully. But it is instructive in suggesting the nature of his point

  of departure and the tensions that would define his struggles. And after

  P: IJD/GCV/lzx-inl

  P: FhN

  cb.xml

  CY/Schultz

  

  January , 

  :

  Unity

  

  all, Macaulay rather notoriously had no love at all for the literature of

  Hinduism; his “love” for the common people of India demanded that

  they be taught English and the love of Western literature. To invoke him

  as Sidgwick did raises the spectre of England’s “civilizing” mission in

  India and other parts of the globe.

  In any event, these various points, even when qualified in recognition

  of Sidgwick’s imperial context, do also suggest the significance of Ryan’s

  plea for the ongoing relevance of the Victorian debates. That the general

  cultural atmosphere is vital to the educational and democratic potential

  of society, that this culture must value critical inquiry in a way capacious

  enough to recognize the worth of both science and religion, philosophy

  and literature, in addition to the Hellenistic legacy – these were not revela-

  tions that awaited the twentieth century. And some might even be a little

  nostalgic for the eloquence and passion shown by a Mill or a Sidgwick

  on the subject of encouraging the mingling of classes and stimulating the

  educational potential of all citizens, even if they did grotesquely under-

  estimate what they stood to learn from other classes and other cultures,

  tending to think of intellectual stimulation as proceeding from themselves

 

‹ Prev