Book Read Free

The Omnibus Homo Sacer

Page 71

by Giorgio Agamben


  which is called material, has been instituted. Rather, this is in order to secure

  the correct implementation of the execution [ propter beneficium execucionis]. For the spiritual sword could not execute spiritual tasks or devote itself to spiritual

  matters so well or so beneficially if it did not have the aid of the material sword

  [ . . . ] (Ibid., pp. 110–111)

  Beyond the dispute about the primacy of one sword over the other, to which

  scholars have exclusively devoted their attention, it turns out that what is pri-

  marily at stake in the division between the two powers is guaranteeing the pos-

  sibility of the government of men. This possibility requires the supposition of

  a plenitudo potestatis that, however, must immediately distinguish itself from

  its actual exercise (its executio), which then constitutes the secular sword. From a theoretical point of view, the debate is not so much between the supporters

  of the primacy of priesthood or the empire, but between the “governmental-

  ists” [“governamentalisti ”] (who conceive power as always already articulated ac-

  cording to a double structure: authority [ potestà] and execution; Kingdom and

  Government) and the promoters of a sovereignty in which it is not possible to

  separate power from act, ordinatio from executio. Gelasius I’s well-known dictum according to which “duo quippe sunt [ . . . ] quibus principaliter mundus hic

  regitur: auctoritas sacra pontificum, et regalis potestas” ( Epistolae et decreta, 8, in PL, 59, 42a)—which he addressed to the emperor Anastasius in 494, that

  is, well before the beginning of the conflict between the two swords—must be

  translated—after all, in an absolutely literal way—as: the world is governed

  through the coordination of two principles, the auctoritas (that is, a power with-

  out actual execution) and the potestas (that is, a power that can be exercised); the Kingdom and the Government.

  א In this perspective, it is possible to clarify the position of those who, like John

  Quidort, refuse to accept the theory of the pontiff ’s plenitudo potestatis, since it implies an unnatural separation of power [ potenza] from act, and power [ potere] from execution. Referring most likely to Giles of Rome, John writes in his De potestate regia et papali that

  some claim that the secular power belongs to the pope immediately and accord-

  ing to his primary authority, but that the pope does not have the immediate

  execution of it, which he delegates to the prince [ . . . ] It can certainly happen

  464

  HOMO SACER II, 4

  that somebody has the power to do something, but not the act, because of some

  hindrance, like, for example, if one has the power to build, but not the act, since

  he lacks the matter, or because of a corporal defect, as in the case of a dumb per-

  son who cannot speak. These are hindrances that befall the conferring of power.

  But only a foolish person would bestow the priesthood upon somebody if he

  knew that he was hindered in this way. Therefore, it is meaningless to say that

  the pope receives immediately from God the power of the secular sword, whose

  exercise, however, is not usually his responsibility. If this were the case, God

  would act against nature, as the latter never gives to anybody a virtue separated

  from the act, since those who have the power also have the act [ cuius potentia,

  eius est actus]. (Quidort, p. 120)

  Here, the conflict does not concern only and especially the primacy of one power [ potere]

  over the other, but the separation of titularity from exercise, of the Kingdom from the

  Government.

  א Peters followed the progeny of the figure of the medieval rex inutilis in the notion of roi fainéant between the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. The term appears in the fourteenth century in the Grandes chroniques de France to translate the rex nihil faciens of medieval chronicles, and is later applied, according to its double meaning of sluggish

  (“qui fit nule chose”) and dissolute (“adonné à la paillardise, oisiveté et vices”), to the last of the Carolingian monarchs. In his 1643 Histoire de France, Mezeray contemptuously applies it to the last of the Merovingian kings, “tous fainéants, hébetez, et plongés dans les ordures du vice” (Peters, p. 543). We can then find it applied to Louis VI, Charles VI, and Henry III of France, as well as, among other English kings, to Henry III, Henry VI,

  and even the figure of King Arthur in some courtly novels (Peters, p. 547).

  4.14. The theological model of the separation of power from its exercise

  is found in the distinction between absolute and ordered power [ potenza] in

  God—that is, in the doctrine of divine impotence, of what God, in spite of

  his omnipotence, cannot do (or cannot not do). According to this doctrinal

  complex (which was founded on a passage from De natura et gratia—1, 7, 8—in

  which Augustine answers the question as to whether Christ could have pre-

  vented Judas’s betrayal by saying that he certainly could have done it, but he

  had not wanted it: “Potuit ergo, sed noluit”), God, with regard to his power

  considered as such ( de potentia absoluta), could do anything that did not entail a contradiction (for instance, embodying himself as a woman, instead of as Jesus,

  to save men; or damning Peter and saving Judas; or even just destroying all of his

  creation). But de potentia ordinata, that is, with regard to his will and wisdom, he can only do what he has decided to do. In other words, the will constitutes the

  apparatus that, dividing power into absolute and ordered power, allows to con-

  THE KINGDOM AND THE GLORY

  465

  tain the unacceptable consequences of divine omnipotence (and, more generally,

  of any doctrine of power), but without negating it as such. Thomas writes that

  nothing can be within divine power which is not held in the wisdom and justice

  of his mind and will. All the same, since his will is not bound of necessity to this

  or that particular objective [ . . . ] there is no reason why something should not

  be within divine power which God does not will, and which is no part of the

  present order he has established. We conceive of understanding and wisdom as

  directing, will as commanding, and power as executing; as for what lies within

  power as such, God is said to be able to do it by his absolute power [ . . . ] As

  for what lies within his power as carrying out the command of his just will, he

  is said to be able to do it by his ordinate power. Accordingly, we should state

  that by absolute power God can do things other than those he foresaw that he

  would do and pre-ordained to do. Nevertheless nothing can come to pass that

  he has not foreseen and pre-ordained. (Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, 1,

  q. 25, a. 5, ad 1)

  What is interesting about this theological apparatus is that, contrary to those

  who rejected any distinction between absolute and ordered power, it made it

  possible to reconcile God’s omnipotence with the idea of an ordered, nonarbi-

  trary, and nonchaotic government of the world. But this de facto amounted to

  making the distinction in God between his absolute power and its effective ex-

  ercise, between a formal sovereignty and its execution. Limiting absolute power,

  ordered power constitutes it as the foundation of the divine government of the

  world. The nexus between this theological problem and the juridical-political

  problem of the separation between sovereignty and its exerc
ise is evident, and

  was soon noticed by canonists. With regard to a decretal by Innocent IV that

  denied an abbot the power to suspend a monk’s vow of poverty, the distinc-

  tion between absolute and ordered power was thus applied by Hostiensis and

  other canonists to the problem of the papal plenitudo potestatis, to show that, de potentia ordinata, the pontiff must abide by the law, although de potentia absoluta he is not bound by it (Courtenay, pp. 107–108).

  Once again, the plenitudo potestatis is shown to have an inner articulation

  that structurally divides it, and the doctrine of what God cannot do becomes the

  paradigm of the distinction between power [ potere] and its exercise, the King-

  dom and the Government.

  In Matthew of Acquasparta’s questions on providence, God’s impotence

  clearly displays its governmental meaning. Giving a negative answer to the ques-

  tion of whether God could have created a rational creature who could not sin,

  Matthew explains that this is impossible not because of an impotence on the

  466

  HOMO SACER II, 4

  part of God, but because it would have made the providential government of the

  world pointless. As a matter of fact, creating a rational creature completely unable

  to sin would mean, on the one hand, denying him free will and, on the other,

  making the grace by means of which God preserves and governs creatures useless.

  Every rational creature, insofar as it is a creature, must be preserved by God and

  needs the creator’s continuous maintenance [ manutenentia], for if he ceased to

  govern the things that he had created, these things would go to ruin [ . . . ] The

  general influence of divine maintenance is not sufficient for the preservation

  of the moral good of creatures: the latter also needs that of grace. For this, just

  as God cannot make it so that a creature preserves itself, so he cannot make it

  so that by nature and by itself it cannot sin. (Matthew of Acquasparta, p. 292)

  God’s impotence functions to make possible a righteous government of the

  world.

  Threshold

  WE can now better understand the Arthurian mythologeme of the roi

  mehaignié. It is the reflection in the literary field of a transformation and

  splitting of the concept of sovereignty that must have deeply troubled contem-

  porary minds. Although, as we have seen, it had some precedents in the Gnostic

  doctrine of the idle god and some parallelisms in the tradition of Roman law,

  this transformation is essentially carried out, from a technical point of view, in

  a canonistic field. The theological model of this separation is the doctrine of

  divine impotence, that is, the distinction between potentia absoluta and potentia ordinata. Hugh of Pisa and the Grandi decretal—with which Innocent IV, in the case of the rex inutilis Sancho II, separated regality from its exercise—gave to this distinction a juridical form of whose general meaning and political implications they were perhaps not fully aware. However, it is certain that, as has

  been observed, “Grandi, indeed, contained the results of the most articulate legal

  tradition which Europe had seen since the age of Justinian, but few territorial

  monarchies were capable, in 1245, of profiting fully from that tradition” (Peters,

  p. 304). The conflict that was here in question is not, however, so much between

  “legal authority” (which, due to the decretal, rested with the Earl of Boulogne)

  and “personal loyalty” (which was still owed to the sovereign Sancho II), as be-

  tween a sovereignty inseparable from its exercise and a regality that is structurally

  divided and separable from government (or, in Foucault’s terms, between terri-

  torial sovereignty and governmental power).

  It is in this perspective that we can interpret the debate that, in the first few

  decades of the fourteenth century, opposes John XXII to Ockham. According

  to John, the laws that God has established are identical with his essence and,

  consequently, are eternal and unchangeable. Therefore, he cannot act otherwise

  than how he has chosen to act. Absolute and ordered powers are the same thing,

  and their distinction is purely nominal.

  It is impossible for God to save according to absolute power a man devoid of

  the sacrament of baptism, because this was decided from eternity according to

  467

  468

  HOMO SACER II, 4

  ordered power, which is to be identified with God and cannot be changed [ . . . ]

  Some claim that God can do many things according to the absolute power which

  he cannot do according to the ordered power, but this is false and wrong, for

  the absolute power and the ordered power in God are the same thing and can

  be distinguished only by name, like Simon and Peter, which name the same

  person. Just as it is impossible that somebody hits Simon without hitting Peter,

  or that Peter does something that Simon does not, insofar as they are the same

  man, so it is impossible for God to do according to the absolute power things

  that are different from those he does according to ordered power, for they are

  the same thing and differ and can be distinguished only by name. (Quoted in

  Courtenay, p. 162)

  What Ockham proposes against this thesis is the irreducibility of absolute power

  to ordered power: these are not two powers, but two different ways in which

  we say that God can or cannot do something, or two internal articulations of a

  single divine power in respect to the act.

  If one looks closely at this issue, saying that God can do things according to

  the absolute power which he cannot do according to the ordered power means

  nothing else than God can do things that he had not decided to do [ quae tamen

  minime ordinaret se facturum]. But if he were to do these things, he would do

  them according to the ordered power, for if he did them, he would have decided

  to do them. (Quoted in Courtenay, p. 164)

  For Ockham, as a more modern thinker, it is essential to preserve the contin-

  gency of decision against an understanding of acting, professed by Muslims and

  “old women” ( vetulae), that reduces it to pure necessity (“from this would follow

  that no creature could do anything that he does not actually do, so that all would

  happen according to necessity and nothing in a contingent way, like the infidels

  claim, and the ancient heretics, and also the occult heretics, the lays and the old

  women”: quoted in ibid.).

  What is at stake in this conflict is, in the final analysis, the functioning of

  the governmental apparatus. While, for the pontiff, the difference between the

  two levels or moments of the apparatus is purely nominal, so that the act of

  real government always already determines the power, and the Kingdom is fully

  identified with the Government, for Ockham, the Kingdom (absolute power)

  exceeds and always in some way precedes the Government (the ordered power),

  which reaches and determines it only at the moment of the executio, yet without

  ever exhausting it completely. In other words, two different conceptions of the

  government of men confront each other: the first is still dominated by the old

  model of territorial sovereignty, which reduces the double articulation of the gov-

  THE KINGDOM AND THE GLORY

  469

 
ernmental machine to a purely formal moment; the second is closer to the new

  economico-providential paradigm, in which the two elements maintain their

  identity, in spite of their correlation, and the contingency of the acts of govern-

  ment corresponds to the freedom of the sovereign decision. And yet, because of

  a peculiar inversion, this very paradigm that is, so to speak, more “democratic” is

  also close to the position of those canonists and theologians (like Duns Scotus)

  who, in the same years, elaborate the doctrine of the potentia absoluta as a model for exceptional powers [ poteri eccezionali]. Insofar as it structurally exceeds ordered power [ potenza ordinata], absolute power [ potenza assoluta] is—not only in God, but in every agent (and, in particular, in the pontiff )—that which allows one to act legitimately “beyond the law and against it”:

  Potest agere conformiter illi legi rectae, et tunc secundum potentiam ordinatam

  (ordinata enim est in quantum est principium exsequendi aliqua conformiter legi

  rectae) et potest agere praeter illam legem vel contra eam, et in hoc est potentia

  absoluta, excedens potentiam ordinatam. (Duns Scotus, quoted in Courtenay,

  p. 112)

  5

  The Providential Machine

  5.1. Michel Foucault’s 1977–1978 course at the Collège de France, entitled

  Sécurité, territoire, population, is devoted to a genealogy of modern

  “governmentality.” Foucault begins by distinguishing three different modalities

  in the history of power relations: the legal system that corresponds to the institu-

  tional model of the territorial State of sovereignty and that defines itself through

  a normative code that opposes what is allowed to what is prohibited, and con-

  sequently establishes a system of punishments; the disciplinary devices that

  correspond to the modern societies of discipline and put into practice, alongside

  the law, a series of police, medical, and penitentiary techniques to order, correct,

  and modulate the bodies of subjects; finally, the apparatuses of security that

  correspond to the contemporary state of population and the new practice that

  defines it, which Foucault names “the government of men.” Foucault is careful

  to specify that these three modalities do not succeed one another chronologi-

 

‹ Prev