The Structure of Evolutionary Theory

Home > Other > The Structure of Evolutionary Theory > Page 229
The Structure of Evolutionary Theory Page 229

by Stephen Jay Gould


  * In retrospect, I suppose that I made an adaptive choice, at least by the usual standard of subsequent discussion and brouhaha in the scientific literature — a legacy that has surely helped to clarify this important issue, and to focus attention upon alternatives to adaptationist explanation in evolutionary biology. But I must also confess that Lewontin and I never anticipated so many exaptive spinoffs from this introductory image — including an entire book by linguistic scholars on our (mostly unconscious) literary tactics (Selzer, 1993); a wise commentary by a noted scholar of medieval buildings (Mark, 1996), and, wonder of wonders in our faintly philistine (and avowedly secular) professional commu­nity, a burgeoning interest in at least two humanistic subjects generally shunned by scien­tists for reasons of passive ignorance, or even active distaste: church architecture (Dennett, 1995; Houston, 1997) and literary parody of the puerile, “ain't-I-clever,” sort embodied in two titles, “The Scandals of San Marco” and “The Spaniels of St. Marx.” Ouch! (Borgia, 1994; Queller, 1995).

  * Because exaptations are coopted utilities, and because the attributes in this pool of po­tential remain as yet uncoopted, some people might object to my designation of this ground of evolvability as “the exaptive pool.” Shouldn't this fund be called the “preadaptive pool” (not that ugly and misleading word again!), or the “potaptive pool” (but why invent a neol­ogism if a current term will suffice)? However, in a purely linguistic and etymological sense, “exaptive pool” represents proper usage, and does not convey any confusing implication of names applied before actions that justify the names. The suffix “ive” refers to “something that performs or tends towards or serves to accomplish an action” (per Webster's) — a fine description of attributes that bring organisms towards evolvability and serve to help them accomplish this happy state. Directives are meant to be followed, but perhaps not just yet. Active sockets will work when you plug in an appliance. Sedative pills will calm you down after you ingest them. Exaptive pools will supply their bearers with a leg up in the longterm sweepstakes of evolution.

  * In some way, and through a very dark glass, I had some inkling of this problem as an undergraduate. In an initial embarrassing episode of juvenilia, my first undergraduate term paper in an evolutionary course, I treated this very subject, but could proceed no further than suggesting the more appropriate description of “ultraspecialization,” having at least recognized that the process commits no active “wrong.” In some psychological sense that I feel strongly but cannot clearly define, I view the genesis of this entire book as personal ex­piation for the puerility of this initial effort!

  * I'm usually quite unshockable, and nothing from the fourth estate (even so high a deni­zen thereof as the New York Times) ever surprises me. But I was amazed that America's most distinguished newspaper would editorialize against a theory so clearly subject to empirical test and so eminently interesting as well. I ended up by sounding off in a popular commentary for Discover Magazine (October, 1985) with a title parody on the Times's venerable motto: “All the News That's Fit to Print and Some Opinions that Aren't.” I commented (Gould, 1985b) that the absurdity of their overreach might best be grasped by com­parison with a hypothetical editorial that might have appeared in the Osservatore Romano (the official Vatican newspaper) for June 22, 1633: “Now that Signor Galileo, albeit under slight inducement, has renounced his heretical belief in the earth's motion, perhaps students of physics will return to the practical problems of armaments and navigation, and leave the solution of cosmological problems to those learned in the infallible sacred texts.” I also suggested that, as a quid pro quo of ultimate fairness, the Times might award to the Paleontological Society the right to determine the date and amount of their next price increase.

  * Since I have far more often been wrong than right in my intuitions about iconoclastic ideas, perhaps I may be excused for taking some pride, in retrospect, in calling this affair, even for the right reasons. I can take no credit whatsoever for the theory's success, since I work in other areas of paleontology and never (unlike Raup and others) did any primary research on the subject. At most, I did write many private letters to participants, and sev­eral popular essays, trying to explain both to my colleagues and to general readers, why they should take impact seriously, and why the Alvarez hypothesis differed so dramatically from previous speculations. In a climate of such negativity, these efforts may have done some good — and Glen (1994, p. 49) was kind enough to write: “By contrast, the paleontol­ogist Stephen Jay Gould, perhaps earth's science's most widely read spokesman, was intel­lectually predisposed to welcome the impact hypothesis straightaway, in part because his unorthodox theory of punctuated equilibrium . . . articulated well with impact theory. Gould thus provided welcome and vital encouragement through sustained communication with the Alvarez group early on, when only the iridium evidence was at hand and paleontologic backlash against the theory was strong.” Moreover, I cannot assert any general claim for anything inellectually admirable in myself or the very few initial paleontological supporters of impact — as we all had purely personal reasons for favorable predispositions (me for the punctuational themes that Glen notes above, Raup for his work on random processes, vertebrate paleontologist Dale Russell for his prior, if speculative, writing on a potential role for impacts). Always look to reasons of personal interest, rather than general wisdom, in such cases — and remember the wise words of W. S. Gilbert's most honorable, if unlikable, man: King Gama of Princess Ida: “A charitable action I can skillfully dissect; And interested motives I'm delighted to detect.”

  * May I, for one last time, repeat the rationale, from the internal logic of this book, that leads me to the otherwise odd strategy of treating the refutation of the third, or extrapola­tionist, leg of central Darwinian logic at reduced length (in Chapter 6 in the historical half and the present Chapter 12 in the modern half) relative to the other two legs of hierarchy and levels of selection (Chapter 3 in the first half, and 8-9 in the second half) and struc­turalist thinking and constraint vs. strict selectionism (Chapters 4–5 in the first half and 10–11 in the second half). My reasons rest upon four arguments, the first three intertwined and intellectual, the fourth separate and personal. First, this book treats the biological structure of evolutionary, particularly Darwinian, theory. Of the three central components designated as legs on a tripod of conceptual definition for Darwinism — (1) levels of selec­tion (Darwinian organismal vs. modern notions of a full hierarchy); (2) functional vs. structural approaches (externalist selection as virtually the sole creative force in evolution­ary change vs. the importance of internal constraint from several sources, not all selec­tionist); and (3) uniformitarian extrapolation of microevolutionary styles of natural selec­tion to explain the full panoply of life's changes through geological time — the biological aspects of the critique for the third theme of extrapolationism lie mainly within expansions and revisions of Darwinism on the first two legs. Second, I therefore decided to confine my explicit discussion of the third leg (since the biological critiques had already been treated under the first two legs) to the surrogate theme of geological requirements to potentiate the biological mechanism (the kind of stage needed to display the proposed play). The surro­gate theme of a different profession does not require such detailed treatment as the central biological critiques. Third, and almost as a historical footnote (but a truly intriguing point missed in most discussions of Darwinism and the 19th century debates about evolution), Darwin himself became uncomfortable with his need to call upon such surrogate themes from other disciplines, and he tried (in later years) to avoid such ancillaries, and to devise a theory that would render his conclusions about life's history entirely by biological princi­ples. Most importantly, he abandoned his early satisfaction with allopatric modes of speciation (that called upon geographic surrogacy to ensure a world with sufficient opportu­nity for isolation of populations), and moved towards the sympatric theory embodied in his “principle of divergence” (see
Chapter 4 of the Origin, including the book's sole figure), and considered by him (in the famous “eureka” statement of his carriage ride in 1854, see p. 224) as second in importance only to his formulation of natural selection itself in devis­ing his full theory. Because this sympatric theory, relying upon the generality of selective benefits for extreme forms in any environment, proved ultimately quite unsatisfactory, and even illogical, we can grasp, with even greater clarity, the importance of this issue in Dar­win's mind — as he so rarely allowed himself to place such weight upon a patently dubious argument (and I do mean patent, for he fretted overtly about the inherent problems, see pp. 236-248), unless its conclusion played a central role in his full system, and he could devise no other path toward a desired outcome. Hence, and in any case, in thus de-emphasizing the themes of geological surrogacy, I am only paying homage to Darwin's own preferences in the structuring of his theory. Fourth, disconnectedly, finally, and entirely per­sonally, I have done no technical paleontological research on these geological themes (be­yond some early, and largely philosophical, analysis of the concept of uniformitarianism, including my first published paper of Gould, 1965), whereas I have devoted my career to paleontological studies of the first two biological legs of hierarchy and constraint. Thus, I lack the competence and the “feel” of personal expertise (or the folly of personal engulfment) to treat this theme at comparable length, for which all readers should rejoice (as even this footnote has hypertrophied quite enough already)!

  Index

  ABC Model, 82, 1063-1064, 1093-1094

  Abel, 1086

  abrupt appearance of species. See also punctuated equilibrium theory; punctuations

  gradualist view of, 749-755, 758-759, 840

  inference of cladogenesis and, 840-850

  migrational incursion and, 748, 840, 841, 852

  acceleration, principle of, 367-368, 371

  Adams, R. McC., 573-574, 956

  adaptation. See also adaptationism; nonadaptive origin as evolutionary term, 117n, 263n, 662, 671, 1051, 1229-1231

  Nietzsche and, 1217-1218

  “adaptation at the edge of chaos,” 1213-1214, 1273-1274

  adaptationism. See also Darwinism; Modern Synthesis, hardening of; structuralist-functionalist dichotomy

  adaptation as term and, 117n, 263n, 662, 671, 1051, 1229-1231

  Bateson and, 406-107, 412-415

  co-adaptation and, 218

  Darwinian efficacy and, 61, 155-159

  de Vries and, 450-451

  English tradition and, 252-253

  Geoffroy and, 300-301

  Goethe and, 288-289

  Gould’s personal odyssey and, 42-44, 397n

  Lamarck and, 176-179, 181-186, 479

  Owen and, 324-326

  Paley and, 117, 118-121, 268-271

  primacy of, for Darwin, 254-260

  problem of too much, 213

  textbooks and, 577-579

  Weismann and, 201-203, 217-219

  adaptive radiations, test of, 815-816

  AEPPS. See Principles of Animal Ecology

  African lake mollusks, 769-771, 796, 845, 853, 867

  Agassiz, Louis, 51, 271, 382, 383, 687, 1021-1022

  Essay on Classification, 271-278

  agency, as Darwinian principle, 14. See also hierarchy theory; levels of selection; organismal selection; punctuated equilibrium theory; species selection

  coral model and, 20, 21

  Darwin’s theoretical argument and, 59, 60

  hardening of Modern Synthesis and, 71, 544-556, 585

  historical alternatives to Darwinism and, 586-587, 588

  meaning of individuality and, 597-613

  modern critiques and, 589, 590

  proposed revisions and, 21, 49

  punctuated equilibrium and, 26, 39, 49

  as theme in Origin, 125-137

  age of the earth, 492-502. See also geological time

  Ager, D. V., 753-754, 773, 845

  Akam, M., 1144, 1145-1146, 1163, 1165, 1166

  AL. See Artificial Life Albanesi, G. L., 852

  Alberch, P., 1037

  Alexander, G., 579

  Allen, J. C., 883

  Allmacht of selection, 358-359, 505, 567. See also Weismann, August

  theory of germinal selection and, 63, 197-201, 215, 219, 223-224, 596

  [Page 1393]

  [Page 1394]

  allometry, 42

  channeled directionality by constraint and, 80-81, 1037-1051

  properties of levels of selection and, 683-714

  scaling in nature and, 677, 680, 704

  allopatric analysis, 706, 707-709

  Almada, V.C., 1240

  alternatives to natural selection. See also Lamarckism; mutation theory; orthogenesis; saltationism

  cultural biases and, 588

  Kellogg’s classification and, 353-354, 383, 439, 506, 507, 589

  logical failure and, 588-590

  persistence of critiques and, 586-587

  Alvarez, L. W., 482, 948, 1303, 1306-1308

  Amalda species, 786, 787

  Ambystoma species, 360

  American Civil War, 1338, 1341-1342

  ammonites, 1315

  Amphioxus, 1170

  Amphipholis squamata, 1162

  anagenesis, 190, 357n

  cladogenesis and, 436, 813-822

  macroevolutionary analogy and, 723-724

  punctuated, 795, 840-841

  trends and, 78, 777

  analogy, as term, 282n, 1077

  Anasazi people, 956

  ancestral survival criterion, 76, 794-796, 840-850

  antelope studies, 78, 866

  Antennapedia mutant, 1100

  anti-Darwinian theory. See creationism; natural theology; orthogenesis; saltationism

  antinomies in Lamarckism, 189-192

  Antonovics, J., 1035

  Appel, T. A., 291-293

  “aptation,” as term, 1051, 1233, 1234

  aptive triangle

  functional vertex, 81, 1052, 1053 (see also natural selection)

  historical vertex, 81, 1052-1053, 1055-1057 (see also deep homology; historical constraint)

  model of, 1051-1053

  premises of traditional Darwinism and, 1173-1174

  structural vertex, 81, 1053-1055 (see also spandrels)

  Arabidopsis, 82, 1063-1064, 1092-1095

  Archegozetes mite, 1163

  archetypal theories. See also historical constraint

  Darwin and, 337-339

  dismissal of, 1091-1092

  evo-devo results and, 82-83, 1092-1095, 1106-1122

  Geoffroy’s dorso-ventral inversion and, 83, 1117-1122

  Geoffroy’s vertebral archetype and, 82-83, 299-306, 320, 321, 1091, 1092, 1101, 1106-1117

  Goethe’s leaf archetype and, 284-286, 1064, 1091, 1092-1095

  Owen’s vertebral archetype and, 316-326, 1091

  architectural metaphor, 2-6. See also Pharaonic bricks vs. Corinthian columns analogy; spandrels

  Arendt, 1151-1152

  “area effects,” 542

  Aristotle, 85, 234n, 626, 1186-1187, 1207-1208

  Arkansas equal time law, 989-990

  Arnold, 901

  Arnold, A. J., 611n, 656, 661, 663, 672, 733

  Arnold, E. N., 1234-1238, 1240, 1244

  art history, 978, 1342

  arthropod and vertebrate developmental homologies. See also bilaterian history; Hox genes

  arthropod hox gene expression and, 1148-1149, 1163-1170

  channeling in bilaterian history and, 1161-1173

  common ancestor and, 1148-1155, 1170-1171

  deep segmental homologies and, 1106-1117

  dorso-ventral inversion and, 83, 1117

  early discoveries of, 1101-1106

  Geoffroy’s vertebral archetype and, 1101, 1106-1117

  “Hoxology” and, 82-83, 1095-1117

  Pharaonic bricks vs. Corinthian columns analogy and, 1138-1142

  setting
of historical constraint and, 1155-1161

  throughout developing somites, 1109-1112

  vertebrate Hox gene expression and, 1170-1173

  vertebrate rhombomeres and, 1107-1109, 1112

  Arthur, W., 1174-1175

  Artificial Life (AL), 924-925

  [Page 1395]

  asexual forms, gradualism in, 807-810. See also Foraminifera

  Asimov, I., 974

  atavisms, 1164-1165

  Ausich, W. I., 891

  Australopithecus, 834, 909

  available things. See insinuations; manumissions; miltons; spandrels

  avatars, 705, 706, 708-709

  Averof, M., 1133-1134, 1165, 1166, 1168

  Avers, C. J., 997

  Avise, J. C., 812

  Awake! (journal), 988

  Axelrod, D. I., 558-559

  Ayala, F. J., 167, 1023, 1155, 1156

  Babyrussa skull, 264-265

  Bacon, Francis, 887-888, 969, 1187-1188

  bacteria

  cause of, 898-900

  episodic change and, 931-936

 

‹ Prev