Sixth Century BCE to Seventeenth Century

Home > Other > Sixth Century BCE to Seventeenth Century > Page 40
Sixth Century BCE to Seventeenth Century Page 40

by Ying-shih Yü


  tem also required it. It is true, as we have already noted, that he was much more

  concerned with knowledge of the human world than that of the natu ral world.

  Nevertheless, his objective curiosity about and keen observation of natu ral phe-

  nomena were clearly without match among the Neo- Confucians.90 This sustained

  interest in the natu ral world came partly from his intellectual temper; his earli-

  est won der, which occurred at the age of fi ve or six (Chinese counting), was

  about heavenly bodies.91 But it was undoubtedly also closely related to his fi rm

  belief that princi ples are inherent in things in the external world, including “a

  blade of grass or a tree.” He once told his students: “Princi ples are universally

  inherent in all things in the world. But it is the mind that takes charge of them.

  Being in charge, the mind therefore makes use of them. It may be said that the

  substance of princi ples is in things themselves while their functions depend on

  the mind.” Yet the next morning he added the following: “I stated the case in

  this way because I was taking myself as the [knowing] subject and things as

  objects [of knowledge]. However, the impor tant truth is that there is really no

  198 z h u x i ’ s ph ilosoph ic a l s y s t e m

  diff erence between saying that princi ples exist in things and that they exist in

  us [i.e., the mind].”92 Both the original statement and the afterthought are

  highly illuminating. The original statement shows that he fully recognized the

  objectivity of princi ples. In terms of substance, they exist in things and are in-

  de pen dent of the mind. By saying that “the mind takes charge of princi ples,” he

  obviously refers to the fact that the mind can discover, order, and apply them.

  The afterthought shows, on the other hand, that he became aware of the possi-

  bility that the original statement might mislead his students to question the

  validity of his postulation about a priori forms in the mind that correspond to

  princi ples inherent in things of the external world. To say “ there is really no

  diff erence between saying that princi ples exist in things and that they exist in

  us” is to stress the point that in the actual practice of “investigation of things”

  and “extension of knowledge,” the subjectivity of a priori forms and the objec-

  tivity of princi ples are ultimately to become unifi ed.93

  In a letter to Zhang Shi, Zhu Xi wrote:

  Confucian learning on the whole begins with a thorough study of princi-

  ples. Each individual thing has its own princi ple. Only when a person

  has a clear knowledge of princi ples can he get hold of an exact standard

  ( zhunze

  ), as of weight and mea sure ment, for his mind to follow in its

  functioning. If he does not extend his knowledge in this [realm of princi-

  ples] thereby being left, generally, without an exact standard, and is rather

  content with the sole claim that he has obtained such and such a knowl-

  edge and understanding of the mind, then how would it be pos si ble for

  what is preserved in and issued from his mind to conform unerringly to

  princi ples?94

  Nowhere is the necessity of “the investigation of things” and “the extension of

  knowledge” in Zhu Xi’s philosophical system more clearly explained than this

  letter. Because his trust of the material and fallible human mind was always

  less than total, he therefore wanted to fi nd an objective standard for the mind to

  follow so that it may not mistake selfi sh desires for moral princi ples. This exact

  standard, in his view, can only be established on the basis of a thorough knowl-

  edge of princi ples that exist objectively in things and events in the external

  world. Thus, we see that at least in theory, knowledge of the natu ral world and

  knowledge of the human world are equally impor tant as far as the objectivity of

  princi ples is concerned. As he emphatically pointed out, “princi ples of things

  are identical with moral princi ples. The world does not possess two kinds of

  princi ples.”95 This is a logical conclusion easily derivable from his fundamental

  presupposition that all the individual princi ples in the world are but diff erentia-

  tions from a single unitary one that is none other than what he calls the Great

  Ultimate ( Taiji

  ) . Hence, in the fi nal analy sis, the cosmic order and the

  moral order follow the same pattern; law for things and moral law are of the

  z h u x i ’ s ph ilosoph ic a l s y s t e m 199

  same kind.96 Through “inquiry and study,” an objective standard can be discov-

  ered in either world, which, from his point of view, would guarantee the objec-

  tivity as well as the stability of moral truth.

  It was also his distrust of the ordinary human mind and his search for an

  exact standard that led him to see the necessity of book learning. He said:

  As I see it, the reason that we have to study is because our minds are not

  yet as [purifi ed as] the sages’ minds. Since our minds are not yet as puri-

  fi ed, we therefore cannot see princi ples clearly and do not have an exact

  standard to conform to. As a result, we often follow our personal inclina-

  tions, which generally fail to meet the standard by either going beyond or

  falling below it. But we are usually unaware of our excesses or defi cien-

  cies. If our minds are from the very beginning not at all diff er ent from

  the sages’ minds or the cosmic mind, then what do we need study for?

  For this reason, it is necessary that we as learners fi rst seek to understand

  the ideas or intentions of the sages through early commentaries and then

  search for universal princi ples in the light of the ideas or intentions of the

  sages. Our search proceeds from the superfi cial to the profound as well as

  from what is at hand to what is far- reaching. We do this by following a

  step- by- step order, not by jumping to the conclusion with burning impa-

  tience. Once we have reached the ultimate limit, our minds will become

  naturally rectifi ed. By then, even the sages’ minds or the cosmic mind can-

  not be very diff er ent from ours. But I do not mean to suggest that we be

  satisfi ed with what is superfi cial and at hand [book learning] and forget

  about what is profound and far- reaching [moral princi ples]. Nor do I mean

  that we simply go after the minds of the sages at the expense of our own

  minds and follow uncritically the interpretations of early commentators

  at the expense of our own interpretations.97

  This letter speaks remarkably well for itself. I only want to call attention to a few

  impor tant points. First, the “exact standard” he was seeking to establish is ulti-

  mately to be found in the objectivity of princi ples of things and events of the

  external world, not in the subjectivity of the sages’ minds, for the search must

  eventually go beyond “the ideas or intentions of the sages.” This is entirely con-

  sistent with his hermeneutical princi ple that in the end our understanding

  must be able to transcend the classical text. Second, it was never his idea that

  we must follow the sages blindly. As a matter of fact, his critical spirit of “doubt”

  led him to the contrary. As he explic itly stated elsewh
ere: “We should always

  read a text with open mind and fair spirit in order to scrutinize the princi ples

  enunciated in it. If there is a valid point, we do not cast it aside simply because it

  is made by a common man. On the other hand, if there is a doubtful point, we

  must examine it carefully even though it is attributed to a sage or worthy.”98 Third,

  it is true that book learning is central to his teaching at the methodological level.

  200 z h u x i ’ s ph ilosoph ic a l s y s t e m

  However, his insistence on learning from the sages and the worthies of the past

  can by no means be construed as arising out of an uncritical and idolatrous at-

  titude on his part. Nor is it a result of sheer antiquarianism. It is rather based

  on his belief that the past sages had bequeathed to us numerous objective

  princi ples that they had discovered through “investigation of things.” They can

  serve as our models because their minds had been extremely well cultivated

  (or purifi ed) through “inquiry and study.” As learners, we must also cultivate

  our minds in the same way. We do this not only by following their examples

  but, more impor tant, by also standing on their shoulders. This is precisely

  why he says in his “emendation” to the Great Learning that the learner, in re-

  gard to all things in the world, must “proceed from what knowledge he has of

  their princi ples, and investigate further until he reaches the limit.” The

  knowledge of princi ples of things and events now at our disposal is the rich-

  est and the most valuable legacy we have inherited from the past sages and

  worthies. It must of necessity serve as the starting point of our new investiga-

  tions. He said:

  It is of course true that in high antiquity, before the writing system had

  been in ven ted, the learners had no books to read. Moreover, it is also true

  that people with above- average intelligence sometimes can attain the

  Way through self- realization and without book learning. However, ever

  since the sages and worthies began their creative work, a good deal of the

  Way has been preserved in the classics. Therefore, even a sage like Con-

  fucius could not have possibly pursued learning apart from them.99

  There cannot be the slightest doubt, as Professor Qian Mu

  points out, that

  he must have written this passage with the question posed by Lu Xiangshan

  during their Goose Lake Temple meeting in mind: “Before the time of Yao

  and Shun , what books were there for people to read?”100 From his point of

  view, this is asking the wrong question, one that borders on sophistry. The his-

  torical situation between now and “the time before Yao and Shun” has been

  fundamentally changed. The simple truth is that we now do have the Confu-

  cian classics, which defi ne the Way in its main outlines as well as in its minute

  details. If we are in quest of the very same Way, as Lu Xiangshan apparently

  was, then what pos si ble justifi cation do we have for our refusal to start the

  search with the classics? Zhu Xi’s keen historical consciousness naturally led

  him to emphasize the importance of the tradition of Confucian scholarship.

  For him, knowledge of princi ples of things and events is always an accumula-

  tive enterprise.

  Lastly, Zhu Xi’s statement in the above passage, “Nor do I mean that we

  simply go after the minds of the sages at the expense of our own minds,” is an

  outright rejection of the idea of “transmission of mind,” then in wide currency.

  z h u x i ’ s ph ilosoph ic a l s y s t e m 201

  In his view, what can be transmitted is not the mind but the Way, which con-

  sists of the princi ples objectively discovered by the sages’ minds in things and

  events.101 Since the mind is essentially a knowing mind, the best a person can

  hope to accomplish is to raise his mind to the level of purifi cation as high as the

  sages’ minds. There is no way he can take the sage’s mind as his own, however.

  He is convinced that only the sage’s words exhibit the sage’s mind, which is

  nothing but the embodiment of the princi ples in the world. Only by studying

  carefully and step by step the sage’s words can one expect to grasp these princi-

  ples. But Lu Xiangshan believes, according to Zhu Xi, that a person can obtain

  the princi ples by relying only on his own mind without the help of the sages’

  words. It is indeed excellent, says Zhu Xi, if a person is able to obtain, all by

  himself, the right kind of princi ples. But what if the princi ples he gets turn out

  to be of the wrong kind?102 Here again Zhu Xi displays his deep distrust of the

  subjectivity of mind on the one hand and his basic concern with the objective

  validity of moral princi ples on the other. Seen in this light, the roots of his dif-

  ferences with Lu Xiangshan on the pedagogic level indeed strike deep in their

  diff er ent conceptions of such key Neo- Confucian ideas as “princi ple” ( li) and

  “mind” ( xin) .

  Unlike Zhu Xi, Lu Xiangshan’s concern is not with the objectivity of princi-

  ples but rather with the subjectivity of mind. Needless to say, I cannot deal with

  his theory of mind here.103 All I need to say is that his trust of the subjectivity

  of mind is unlimited.104 His well- known proposition, “Mind is Princi ple,” his

  identifi cation of the mind with the (spatio- temporal) cosmos, his emphasis on

  the “recovery of the original mind,” and many other similar formulations all

  point in the same direction. “Mind” conceived in this way cannot possibly be

  identifi ed with that as understood by Zhu Xi, which, as we have seen, is essen-

  tially “formed to know.” It makes sense only if interpreted as the absolute moral

  mind.105 With regard to this mind, there cannot be princi ples external to it; all

  objectivity is absorbed into subjectivity. Zhu Xi’s question of an “objective stan-

  dard,” therefore, will never arise in the context of Lu Xiangshan’s philosophy.

  Moreover, according to Lu Xiangshan, this absolute moral mind that is shared

  by every one does not change with time. History, therefore, makes little diff er-

  ence, and tradition is of no fundamental importance. The “recovery of the origi-

  nal mind” depends entirely on every one’s own eff ort; it cannot count on the words

  or minds of the sages and the worthies for help in an essential way. Lu once

  reminisced that his understanding of Confucian learning was self- attained on

  the occasion of reading the Mencius.106 Obviously, he here placed the emphasis

  more on self- attainment than on the book, which only provided the occasion for

  his enlightenment. It is also very in ter est ing to note that he reached the same

  conclusion as Zhu Xi did with regard to the prob lem of “transmission of mind,”

  but for completely diff er ent reasons. In the Goose Lake Temple meeting, he was

  dissatisfi ed with the second line of his brother Jiuling’s

  poem composed

  202 z h u x i ’ s ph ilosoph ic a l s y s t e m

  specifi cally for the occasion. It reads: “Ancient sages pass on this mind.” In re-

  sponse, the same line of his own poem says: “ ’Tis man’s indestructible mind

  through all ages.”107 Clearly, in his view, recovery of the original mind depen
ds

  primarily on every one’s “self- attainment,” whereas “transmission of mind” im-

  plies a dependence on the minds, and consequently, also the words, of the

  sages.108 It was in this way that Lu Xiangshan’s view of mind led, by its inner

  logic, to an attitude toward book learning diametrically opposed to Zhu Xi’s.

  not e s

  1. This is a reference to the “Zhongyong”

  , which provides the locus classicus of zun

  dexing and dao wenxue. The “Zhongyong” has been traditionally ascribed to Zisi

  (483–402 b.c.e.?), Confucius’s grand son.

  2. Zhu Wengong wenji

  (hereafter Wenji), SBCK, chap. 54, 962, “Reply to Xiang

  Pingfu.”

  3. See Lu Xiangshan’s “nianpu”

  in the Xiangshan xiansheng quanji

  ,

  SBCK, chap. 36, 321, and Yulu

  in SBCK, chap. 34, 261. I have followed Lu’s nianpu

  in dating Zhu’s letter to Xiang Anshi. Wang Maohong

  (1668–1741) is clearly

  wrong in assigning this letter to 1181, for this was the year that Xiang Anshi fi rst came

  to know Lu Xiangshan. See Wang Maohong, Zhuzi nianpu

  , GXJBCS, 100.

  4. See Yu Ji’s

  (1272–1348) “Xingzhuang”

  of Wu Cheng in Daoyuan xuegu lu

  , SBCK, chap. 44, 386–387.

  5. See Wang Yangming’s two letters to Xu Chengzhi

  , written in 1522, in the Yang-

  ming quanshu

  , SBBY, 21:5a–8b.

  6. For example, see Xu Jie’s

  (1503–1583) “Xueze bian”

  , in Xiangshan xiansheng

  quanji, “Fulu”

  , 14–15.

  7. See SYXA, WYWK, chap. 58, 6–8. Huang Zongxi’s view was also followed by his son

  Bojia

  (ibid., 8) and Quan Zuwang

  (1705–1755) in Jieqi ting ji, waipian

  ,

  , SBCK, chap. 44, 656–657.

  8. For the term “polarity,” see B. I. Schwartz, “Some Polarities in Confucian Thought,” in

  Confucianism in Action, ed. David S. Nivison and Arthur F. Wright (Stanford, Calif.:

  Stanford University Press, 1959), 51–52.

  9. For “unit- ideas,” see Arthur O. Lovejoy, The Great Chain of Being (Cambridge, Mass.:

  Harvard University Press, 1936), 3–6.

  10.

  ZYL (Taipei: Zhengzhong, 1973), chap. 64, 2524.

  11. See Zhu Hengdao’s

 

‹ Prev