Book Read Free

The Book of Memory

Page 16

by Mary Carruthers


  forgetting was a familiar phenomenon, indeed a necessary aspect of creat-

  ing memories, but the solution for ensuring a measure of accuracy for one’s

  semantic memories lay in frequent practice and testing oneself (XI. ii. 34).

  The greater challenge was to secure a rich recollection of material through

  one’s inventory schemes.

  Descriptions of the neuropsychology of memory

  79

  Recollection as investigation

  The first part of Aristotle’s De memoria defines the nature of the memorial

  image and how such images are stamped upon the soul, like a signet ring in

  wax. The second part of the treatise deals with the process of recollection. For

  Aristotle, recollection is the active, intellectual process, distinct from the

  passive, receiving nature of memory. Sorabji (p. 35) suggests that Aristotle

  thought of it as distinct from memory in part because the Greek verb for ‘ to

  recollect’ is passive, ‘ to be reminded of,’ and so the recollector must become

  the conscious agent, who associates ideas with one another, ‘‘one thing

  putting you in mind of something else.’ (In this psychology, spontaneous

  recollection, though recognized, is not valued; it is too risky and irrational.)

  When we recollect ‘‘starting in thought from a present incident, we

  follow the trail in order, beginning from something similar, or contrary, or

  closely connected.’’79 The important thing is to have a starting-point

  (arche´), and to have the things to be remembered set in an order that can

  readily be searched: ‘‘whatever has some order, as things in mathematics do,

  is easily remembered.’’80 This is what remembering from places (apo topon)

  also affords, for ‘‘people go quickly from one thing to another, e.g. from

  milk to white, from white to air, and from this to fluid, from which one

  remembers autumn, the season one is seeking.’’ The ‘‘places’’ Aristotle

  appears to be talking about in this passage are instances of individual visual

  or verbal associations. But another system of ‘‘places’’ discussed at greater

  length in De memoria is more consciously systematic.

  Sometimes it is best, Aristotle says, in recollecting a series of things, to

  begin at a medial position because then one can remember either of the

  two things to each side of it. Evidently, as Sorabji comments, Aristotle

  is describing a mnemonic technique ‘‘done through some system of

  images.’’81 The system Sorabji reconstructs is quite specific and elegant,

  in the mathematical sense of that word. Images are ‘‘placed’’ in threes, each

  triad containing (perhaps as its middle term) a numerical symbol (a similar

  technique is recommended in Rhetorica ad Herennium). The images are

  scanned when we need to recollect, but associating them in triads marked

  by an individuating device such as a number allows one to scan more

  quickly, by being able to skip over several sets until one arrives at a suitable

  starting-place; it also allows one to ‘‘visit the images that are next door on

  either side’’ (‘‘neighboring,’’ Sorabji’s translation of suneggus), instead of

  going through a whole series one after another each time. Undoubtedly

  such a procedure would be useful in remembering a composition of one’s

  own (which is the task most ancient writers on rhetoric address, as do their

  80

  The Book of Memory

  modern commentators) but it is equally useful as a technique for recalling

  the work of others, a summarized treatise, for example, or a set of ‘‘com-

  mon places’’ (koinoi topoi) which one had read and stored in one’s memory

  library and which one wished to refer to in composing one’s own work.

  Aristotle highly recommended the systematic cultivation of memory to his

  students in dialectic. According to Diogenes Laertius, he wrote a book on

  mnemonics, and he refers several times (notably in De anima, 427b) to a

  system of memory training, such as the familiar memorizing of places

  (topoi). In the Topics, he says he wants students to memorize arguments,

  definitions, and the topoi of argument as defined in Topics II–VII; further-

  more the topoi should be memorized by number so they can be quickly

  scanned during debate. 82

  It is the spatial, somatic nature of memory-images that allows for secure

  recollective associations to be formed, according to a variety of consciously

  applied techniques, training, and diligent practice. Recollection is like

  reasoning: Thomas Aquinas says that human being not only have memory

  as animals do, as a spontaneous remembrance of things past, but they also

  have it in a particularly human way, as reminiscence, ‘‘a quasi-syllogistic

  search [quasi syllogistice inquirendo] among memories of things past in their

  individuality.’’83 But because it is also a physiological process, recollection

  is subject to training and habituation in the manner of all physical activity.

  The most powerful associational connections are formed by habit, de

  consuetudine, rather than by logic, de necessitate. Logical reconstruction is

  universal to all human beings in all situations: six times seven is always

  forty-two, and seven times seven is seven more, or forty-nine. But, while

  ‘‘white’’ may remind me of ‘‘milk,’’ it may remind you of ‘‘snow’’ and

  someone else of ‘‘lilies,’’ and thus lead all three of us in different, unrelated

  associative chains, none of which is inherently (de necessitate) truer or better

  than another. Such chains are individually habitual, unlike six times seven.

  All ancient mnemonic advice takes this fact into account by counselling

  that any learned technique must be adapted to individual preferences and

  quirks. One cannot use a ‘‘canned’’ system, nor will every system work

  equally well for everyone. 84 The ability to recollect is natural to everyone,

  but the procedure itself is formed by habitus, training, and practice.

  Aristotle demonstrates the associational nature of memory by observing

  that one sometimes can recollect something in one way and sometimes not.

  Sometimes, if we want to remember C, we can get to it via B, but some-

  times B doesn’t work, and we need to remember D in order to set up the

  ‘‘chain’’ that gets us to C. ‘‘The reason why one sometimes remembers and

  sometimes not, starting from the same position, is that it is possible to

  Descriptions of the neuropsychology of memory

  81

  move to more than one point from the same starting point’’ (452a 24), for

  example from ‘‘white’’ to ‘‘milk’’ or ‘‘lilies.’’ A ‘‘chain of succession’’ is set up

  in recollection, ‘‘for the impulses follow each other by custom, one after

  another’’ (451b 22). ‘‘By custom’’ (Sorabji’s ‘‘by habit’’) translates the Greek

  ‘‘gar ethei,’’ literally ‘‘by repetition.’’85

  Thomas Aquinas and the other scholastics elaborated Aristotle’s observa-

  tions on the associational, ‘ habitual,’ nature of recollection. Commenting

  on Augustine’s discussion of the trinitarian nature of the human soul

  (memory, intellect, and will), Thomas Aquinas says that Augu
stine did not

  think of them as distinct powers but ‘ by memory he understands the soul’s

  habit of retention; by intelligence, the act of intellect; and by will, the act of

  the will.’ Memory is a proclivity or disposition (habitus) of the soul rather

  than a power or activity itself. ‘ As Augustine proves, we may be said to

  understand, will, and to love certain things, both when we actually consider

  them, and when we do not think of them. When they are not under our

  actual consideration, they are objects of our memory only, which, in his

  opinion, is nothing else than a habitual retention of knowledge and love.’ 86

  The habit is a mediator between a power and its object, for ‘‘every power

  which may be variously directed to act, needs a habit whereby it is well

  disposed to its act.’’87 All virtues and vices are habits, good or bad (see II–I,

  Q. 55). Defining memory as habitus makes it the key linking term between

  knowledge and action, conceiving of good and doing it. Memory is an

  essential treasure house for both the intellect and virtuous action.

  Memory and the habits of virtue

  In Aquinas’s theology the influence of Cicero is apparent in his discussion

  of the four cardinal virtues, 88 whose names and attributes themselves are

  taken from ‘‘Tullius’s First and Second Rhetoric’’ (i.e. De inventione and

  Ad Herennium) though reference is also always made to Wisdom 8:7: ‘‘for

  [wisdom] teacheth temperance, and prudence, and justice, and fortitude,

  which are such things as men can have nothing more profitable in life.’’89

  Prudence, the first of them, is also called by Cicero sapientia, a word he

  used to translate the Greek sophia of his sources.90 Prudence, says the

  Ad Herennium, ‘‘is intelligence capable, by a certain judicious method, of

  distinguishing good and bad; likewise the knowledge of an art [scientia

  cuiusdam artificie] is called Wisdom; and again, a well-furnished memory

  and experience in diverse matters [rerum multarum memoria et usus con-

  plurium negotiorum] is termed Wisdom.’’91 Cicero himself defines pru-

  dence as:

  82

  The Book of Memory

  the knowledge of what is good, what is bad and what is neither good nor bad. Its

  parts are memory, intelligence, and foresight. Memory is the faculty by which the

  mind recalls what has happened. Intelligence is the faculty by which it ascertains

  what is. Foresight is the faculty by which it is seen that something is going to occur

  before it occurs. 92

  As he adapts these texts in his own thought, Thomas Aquinas addresses

  the three basic meanings of prudence given in Ad Herennium. Classical

  rhetoric had defined as one aspect of prudence knowing the procedures and

  intricacies of an art, or what we now might call craft ‘‘know-how.’’ In his

  general discussion of the nature of virtue, Thomas considers the question of

  whether art (artifice) can be considered as relevant to speculative knowl-

  edge or only to mechanical knowledge. He responds that even purely

  intellectual activities require art; for the construction of a sound syllogism,

  or of an appropriate style, or the work of measuring or numbering all

  involve something of artfulness, of craft. Art is here defined as knowing

  how to make something well. 93 All craft is acquired through habit (repe-

  tition), but it is an intellectual or ‘‘speculative’’ habit, not a moral one:

  Since, therefore, habits of the speculative intellect do not perfect the appetitive part,

  nor prompt it in any way, but affect only the intellective part directly, they may

  indeed be called virtues inasmuch as they make us capable of a good activity . . . yet

  they are not called virtues . . . as though they ensured the right use of a power or

  habit. Because he possesses a habit of a theoretic science, a man is not set thereby to

  make good use of it . . . That he makes use of it comes from a movement of his will.

  Consequently a virtue which perfects the will, as charity or justice [or prudence],

  ensures the right use of these speculative habits [such as any art].’’94

  Next, Thomas Aquinas distinguishes ‘‘know-how’’ from the ethical

  nature of prudence, thus departing from, or rather refining, as we shall

  see, this part of the classical description in order to emphasize and isolate

  clearly the essentially ethical character of prudence. As art is knowing how

  to make things well, prudence is knowing how to do well: ‘‘prudence stands

  in the same relation to . . . human acts, which lie in the effective application

  of powers and habits, as art does to external productions.’’95 While the

  definition of prudence is closely associated with that of art, in itself

  prudence is a moral virtue, channeling the will and appetites, not perfect-

  ing intellectual activities, although like all virtues it is under the control of

  reason. Prudence is

  a virtue of the utmost necessity for human life. To live well means acting well. In

  order to perform an act well, it is not merely what a man does that matters, but also

  how he does it, namely, that he acts from right choice and not merely from

  impulse or passion . . . Man is directed indeed to his due end by a virtue which

  Descriptions of the neuropsychology of memory

  83

  perfects the soul in the appetitive part, the object of which is a good and an end.

  For a man to be rightly adapted to what fits his due end, however, he needs a habit

  in his reason; because counsel and choice, which are about things ordained to

  an end, are acts of reason. Consequently, an intellectual virtue is needed in his

  reason to complement it and make it well adjusted to these things. This virtue

  is prudence. And this, in consequence, is necessary for a good life . . . Art is

  necessary, not that the artist may lead a good life, but so that he may produce a

  good and lasting work of art. Prudence is necessary, not merely that a man may

  become good, but so that he may lead a good life.96

  Prudence involves both reason and will, an ‘‘intellectual virtue’’ which also

  directs and ‘‘perfects’ the emotional, desiring will. It requires knowledge but

  it acts to shape up our ethical life so that we may live well, and not merely be

  good, in the way that a carving or a building can simply ‘‘be good.’’

  Prudence as sapientia, ‘‘wisdom,’’ comprises the suitable use of all knowl-

  edge, practical and speculative – including, let it be noted here, the making

  of poems. It thus includes dialectic, rhetoric, and physics, or knowledge

  arrived at by arguing from probable premises, knowledge arrived at by

  persuading on the basis of conjectured truth, and knowledge arrived at

  through demonstration.97 This classification of all human knowledge as a

  part of prudence is also found in later medieval writers, such as Brunetto

  Latini, who in his Treśor states that prudence (‘‘sapience’’) contains all sense

  and all teaching, and it also knows all times (‘‘tens’’). Echoing De inven-

  tione, although he says his immediate source is Seneca, Brunetto gives the

  definition of prudence we have already noted: ‘‘c’est le tens ale´ par mem-

  oire, de quoi Seneque dis
t, ki ne pense noient des choses aleés a sa vie

  perdue; et du tens present par cognoissance; et du tens a venir por

  porveance.’’98 Prudence comprehends not only all human knowledge but

  also temporality. The definition of it given in De inventione makes this

  clear: its parts are temporally related, memory being of what is past;

  intelligence of what is; foresight of what is to come.

  The temporal nature of prudence is stressed by Thomas Aquinas when

  he comes to defining its exact nature; his first topic under the parts of

  prudence is whether memory is one of them. He concludes that it is, for:

  Tullius [De invent. ii.53] places memory among the parts of prudence . . . Prudence

  regards contingent matters of action, as stated above [II–II, Q. 47, art. 5]. Now in

  such like matters a man can be directed . . . by those [things] which occur in the

  majority of cases . . . But we need experience to discover what is true in the

  majority of cases: wherefore the Philosopher says [Nic. Ethics ii.1] that ‘‘intellectual

  virtue is engendered and fostered by experience and time.’’ Now experience is the

  result of many memories as stated in Metaphysics i.1, and therefore prudence

  requires the memory of many things. Hence memory is a part of prudence.99

  84

  The Book of Memory

  By memory, Thomas clearly means here not just the natural power of the

  sensitive soul described by Aristotle but trained memory, the memory

  which is a treasury of many memories.

  Thomas’s meaning is made apparent when one contrasts his quotation

  of these words from the Metaphysics with that of his teacher, Albertus

  Magnus. Albertus, citing the same Metaphysics passage in De bono, Q. II,

  a.1, writes that the power of experience is perfected by ‘‘multae enim

  memoriae eiusdem rei’’ – many memories of the same thing – which is

  actually what Aristotle himself wrote. 100 When Thomas Aquinas, however,

  cites the same passage, he writes that experience results ‘‘ex pluribus

  memoriis,’’ from several different memories. The memorial experience

  that founds prudence is not iterative but concatenative, ‘‘plural’’ in the

  sense of the motto of the United States, those many memories contained in

  the varied quantity of his sources. E. K. Rand has written eloquently of

 

‹ Prev