Book Read Free

The Book of Memory

Page 30

by Mary Carruthers


  three rows of teeth, which Hugh of St. Cher proceeds to moralize in terms

  of a backbiter’s nasty characteristics.

  Where did the bear come from? Judson Allen, who carefully studied this

  matter, says that Hugh’s comment is found in no other Psalter gloss; it is

  his own. Hugh of St. Cher cites the most famous bear in Scripture, the one

  with all the teeth in Daniel’s dream (Dan. 7:5). This text supplies the details

  of the image: ‘‘tres ordines erant in ore ejus, et in dentibus ejus,’’ ‘‘there were

  162

  The Book of Memory

  three rows in the mouth thereof, and in the teeth thereof’’ (Douay trans-

  lation; the King James Version differs markedly from the Vulgate).

  The bear has a wide, devouring mouth, as does death, as do backbiters –such

  connections are clear in the Daniel text, for the bear is commanded to

  ‘‘Arise, devour much flesh.’’ And the connection of death with biting

  is clear and traditional, made by means of the homophony of Latin mors,

  ‘‘death,’’ and morsus, ‘‘bite.’’ Furthermore, though Latin dectractor has

  no homophonic or etymological connection to mors or morsus, the late

  Latin participle mordentem, from mordere ‘‘to bite’’ and, by a metaphorical

  extension, ‘‘to make a caustic comment,’’ clearly connects to ‘‘detractors’’ in

  meaning, and to ‘‘death,’’ ‘‘biting,’’ and ‘‘teeth’’ in sound. The Old French

  word, mordant, ‘‘bitter speaking,’’ would have been familiar to Hugh, for

  he was French; he may well also have known the word backbiter from

  English students at Paris. Such a mnemonically useful tissue of homo-

  phonies accords with John of Garland’s advice regarding the use of the

  sounds of all kinds of languages to help fix etymologies and interpretations

  in the memory. But none of these words requires a bear.

  I suspect that the reason why a bear entered Hugh of St. Cher’s composi-

  tional memory is because the word ursus, like umbra, starts with a U. Ursus,

  together with its voces – the most vivid of which is its big mouth, according

  to Isidore, who derives ursus from os, ‘‘mouth’’ – and texts relevant to it,

  such as this obvious one from Daniel, would be stored in Hugh’s memory

  under ‘‘U,’’ helping to mark etymologies, distinctions, and interpretations

  of words and texts which also start with ‘‘U.’’ And so, when composing his

  distinctio on umbra, his U-animal comes to mind, and it has characteristics

  (voces) which, happily, can this time be pressed into service of the point he

  wishes to make. In other words, what first led Hugh to a bear was not some

  hermeneutical or iconographic correlation, but the simple fact that ursus

  and umbra have the same initial letter. The word ursus was thought to

  originate in os, oris, hence ‘‘teeth,’’ and a link to the happy homophony

  of mors and morsus. So the bear’s appearance in the written text is a vestige

  of Hugh’s mental organizational scheme. That it also serves his inter-

  pretation is, of course, why that connection is preserved in the final

  composition.

  John of Garland’s memory advice confirms certain features as standard

  in medieval mnemotechnique. In particular, treating the memory as

  though it were an area divided linearly into columns within a grid seems

  distinctly medieval. Hugh of St. Victor describes the elements differently,

  but he too says to treat memory as a linea, a line of cells in a numerically

  addressed grid. The earliest source of such a lay-out is unclear, but linearly

  The arts of memory

  163

  formatted diagram pages, such as Eusebius’s Canon Tables, were widely

  known and used from earliest times. 19 The development of tabular lay-outs

  and the advice to use them mnemonically went hand in hand, since there is

  a clear, persistent theme in all medieval mnemonic advice: to take advant-

  age of the presentation of the physical page as a fixative for memory.

  T H O M A S B R A D W A R D I N E , O N A C Q U I R I N G

  A T R A I N E D M E M O R Y ( C . 1 3 3 5 )

  John of Garland’s presentation of memoria in his Parisiana poetria is too

  informal to be a complete art of memory. A proper art requires general

  principles and a system which one can apply to a variety of circumstances,

  and these are not features of John of Garland’s mnemonic advice. But a

  medieval treatise on memory that does meet the criteria for being an art, yet

  owes as little to Ciceronian sources as does the advice of John of Garland, is

  the ars memorativa attributed to Thomas Bradwardine, mathematician and

  theologian at Merton College from 1325 to 1335. Subsequently, he was

  chancellor of St. Paul’s and prebend of Lincoln, then a chaplain to

  Edward III, and finally he died of the plague in August, 1349, a month

  after his consecration as archbishop of Canterbury. Bradwardine is best

  known for his participation on the orthodox side in the debate regarding

  the roles of predestination, grace, and free will, through his theological

  tract, De causa Dei, ‘‘the case for God.’’ His other work is mathematical in

  nature – a tractatus on proportions, one on the problem of squaring a

  circle, a speculative arithmetic, and a speculative geometry. And then there

  is the tract we are concerned with here, De memoria artificiali adquirenda.

  This treatise belongs to Bradwardine’s Merton years.20 It is of consider-

  able interest that it was not composed by a professional teacher of rhetoric,

  like John of Garland, nor for elementary-level students, but by a theologian

  and professor of natural philosophy lecturing for university students.

  The work exists in three manuscripts: British Library MS. Sloane 3744,

  British Library MS. Harley 4166, and Fitzwilliam Museum (Cambridge)

  MS. McClean 169. All are English in origin, of the late fourteenth century

  and the first part of the fifteenth, the work itself being datable to 1333–1335.

  The McClean version is part of a book, the work of a single scribe,

  containing other scientific material, astrological, herbal, alchemical, and

  mathematical in nature. The Sloane manuscript version in contrast is a

  digest of Bradwardine’s advice; it was written in a single pamphlet, together

  with a treatise on heraldry. It is also incomplete, missing the discussion of

  memory for syllables and memory for words, and containing a different,

  164

  The Book of Memory

  abbreviated conclusion. The McClean manuscript contains a version that

  is nearly three times the length of that in Sloane 3744. The text in Harley

  4166 contains about two-thirds of the material in McClean, with which its

  readings agree closely. Harley 4166 is a book made up of a number of

  isolated fragments bound together; because of this it is no longer possible

  to tell how the original manuscript was copied, and it appears to have been

  unbound for a long time.21

  Bradwardine’s treatise is interesting on two grounds. First, it codifies

  mnemonic advice of the sort that exists piecemeal in a few sentences in

  other medieval documents, and secondly, though some of its precepts

  resemble one
s in the classical architectural mnemonic, Bradwardine obvi-

  ously draws on a different tradition. His ars memorativa has been treated by

  some modern scholars as though it were in the Ad Herennium tradition, but

  it is not.22 It articulates a completely medieval art of images in places, which

  owes very little directly to the Ad Herennium and is not associated by

  Bradwardine with any ancient authority. The incidental similarities

  between Bradwardine’s rules and those of ‘‘Tullius’’ are explained by two

  factors, one being certain enduring requirements of human recollection

  (such as having a rigid, easily reconstructable order to the backgrounds;

  making visually remarkable and emotionally laden associations through

  images; and the rule of Seven Plus-or-Minus Two), and the other being a

  few continuous pedagogical traditions. For, as in the case of the advice

  given by Hugh of St. Victor, there is no reason to believe that Bradwardine

  created a wholly new art of memory. At most, he was drawing together in a

  single handbook advice that had been practically, if not so systematically,

  available for centuries. And, as we will see, these same conventions are to be

  found not in a textual tradition but in manuscript painting traditions from

  the early Middle Ages. This suggests to me that the mnemonic role of book

  decoration was consciously assumed from the beginnings of the book in the

  West; we have seen other evidence of this close link in the specialized

  vocabulary of memory techniques as well.

  It is in a few generalities rather than specifics that Bradwardine’s system

  resembles that described in the Ad Herennium, written 1,500 years earlier.

  Bradwardine distinguishes many of the basic terms of memorial art:

  memory for subject matters and memory for words, natural and artificial

  memory, the archetypal metaphor of memory as a surface onto which

  letters are written, and the very idea of places and images. But both the

  manner and specifics of his presentation are quite different from what is in

  Ad Herennium. He begins by describing six general properties of places or

  locations (loci): the size, shape, and characteristic features of a single

  The arts of memory

  165

  location, and the number, order, and distance away that characterize a set

  of such background locations.

  A locus should be of a size neither greater nor smaller than what the eye

  can take in at a single glance – a small garden or a cloister are ideal in their

  extent. In shape it should be rectangular, like a page or a tablet. This is a

  striking and significant difference between Bradwardine’s rules for the loci

  and those of the Herennian mnemonic. It clearly is related to both John of

  Garland’s and Hugh of St. Victor’s use of the word locus to refer to the

  presentation on the page of the textual matter to be remembered. The locus

  should be a lighted, completely open space, with no distracting detail of its

  own. It must be neither too dark nor too glaringly illuminated. One should

  not imagine a crowded location, such as a church or marketplace. One

  should use real places, which can be visited and re-inspected frequently, in

  preference to wholly imaginary ones, which are trickier and would require

  greater mastery to keep clearly and unchangingly in mind.

  The places in their ordered sets should contrast with one another in

  color as well as content. Bradwardine describes making a first set of five

  locations on the theme of a field: the first might be a waste field, the second

  a green garden, the third the same field at harvest, the fourth the field after

  harvest when only the stubble remains, and the fifth the field blackened by

  burnt stubble. (It is of some interest, I think, that Bradwardine uses the

  common motif of the seasonal changes as a set of memorative locations.)

  One multiplies one’s available locations in such sets of five, Bradwardine

  counsels, working upward from ground-level to the upper storeys, as

  though of a building. After the set of fields, he describes a set of flat raised

  locations: a large couch, an armoire, a table, a tomb, an altar. Then come

  roofs (wood shingles, thatch, slate, tile, and lead) and terraces (floored with

  earth, greenstone, tiles, straw, or carpeting). By multiplying sets of five in

  this manner, one never has to think of more than five closely related

  locations at any one time, but one can also extend the multiplying process

  as much as one chooses, though Bradwardine suggests that no more than

  ten related sets be constructed at one time, lest the fabrication become too

  unwieldy.

  For one must be able to keep track exactly of each location in relation to

  the others in its own and related sets. So the places must have contiguity (or

  ‘‘neighborliness,’’ to use Aristotle’s word) and direction – as the order of

  numbers and alphabets have both of these basic features. Without such a

  rigid schematic order, one cannot find places easily, nor can one move

  about or gather them together. I have stressed before the shuffling require-

  ment which a memory system must address – Bradwardine’s method of

  166

  The Book of Memory

  multiplying sets in fives does this. These locations are the mental bins of

  one’s inventory, each of similar size, shape, and illumination, and each of a

  monochromatic color but the colors contrasting with those of the other

  locations in its set (the carpeted flooring of the fifth member of

  Bradwardine’s fourth set suggests that a simple pattern within the mono-

  chrome was tolerable). One relates these to one another basically in the

  manner in which people construct a grid or matrix, as sets of empty boxes,

  built one on top of the other, and addressed individually by means of a pair

  of coordinates that places them within the matrix.

  One final feature of the locations concerns what Bradwardine calls

  distancia and distancia intercepta. By this term he seems to mean what we

  call perspective, both with respect to the position of the observer and with

  respect to the distance depicted in the location itself, foreground and

  background. The observation point is frontal, and far enough away from

  the scene that everything in it can be seen clearly, fully, and at once. There

  is no suggestion here, as there is in the Ad Herennium, that the mental eye’s

  perspective will change as one imagines a walk through it – in the

  Bradwardinian account, the eye is positioned optimally, so that one takes

  in the whole location at one glance. Additionally, within the location,

  whatever detail (a hill, perhaps, or a tree or a couch) is needed to set the

  image is depicted, but no distant background is shown, for this might

  distract from the clarity of the mnemonically important image. Thus, a

  mnemonic scene in its background may have some shallow suggestions of

  setting, but no deep perspective. Bradwardine says that the ‘‘distance’’ in

  the location should be void – a single color or a simple design. Both of these

  perspectival conditions are common in early medieval painting. Indeed

  the picture-page of the sixth-century Gospels of St. Augustine (figure 29)r />
  provides an excellent illustration of such a locational arrangement, frontal

  perspective, and emptiness of distance. One finds such features still in late

  medieval painted scenes.

  Into the cell-like arrangement of locations in tiers, one places the

  imagines. Bradwardine gives several general rules for the construction of

  memorial images for content (res) and images for words. This organiza-

  tional feature of his treatise is another significant difference from the Ad

  Herennium, for it clarifies the fact that as images, those employed for

  various mnemonic functions do not differ significantly in their character-

  istics. Memorative images should be of moderate size, but that is their only

  moderate feature. Because the memory retains distinctly only what is

  extraordinary, wonderful, and intensely charged with emotion, the images

  should be of extremes – of ugliness or beauty, ridicule or nobility, of

  The arts of memory

  167

  laughter or weeping, of worthiness or salaciousness. Bloody figures, or

  monstrosities, or figures brilliantly but abnormally colored should be

  used, and they should be engaged in activity of a sort that is extremely

  vigorous.

  These figures are to be grouped against the plain background in an active

  scene, their relative positions acting as cues to the order of the material with

  which they are associated. So, the image for the first matter to be recalled is

  placed towards the front of the location, its torso occupying the center.

  Then the second image is placed on its right hand, and it is helpful if the

  central image has limbs or some means of attaching the other images to

  itself physically. The third and fourth images (if they are needed) are

  attached serially to the right of the second. A fifth image is attached to

  the left side of the central image, with the following ones joined serially to

  it. To read this composite, one begins in the center, then looks right as far

  as one can, and then returns to the center and looks left. The figures are

  joined to one another in an active, even violent, manner. The first image is

  to strike or hold the second with its right hand, the third to ride around the

  second, and so on, so that these vigorous activities ‘‘will be, as it were, a

  fastening together of their order in the series.’’ One can have three or five or

 

‹ Prev