The Book of Memory
Page 33
managed to break loose from the lawsuit image to career dangerously around
on its own in the dark?’’ She suggests perhaps the connection had something
to do with the Zodiac, or perhaps was just the result of too many lonely
nights of study. But the explanation is more prosaic. The testicles are in the
ancient source, of course, but the charging ram bearing them was added in
the earliest known commentary/gloss on it, Etsi cum Tullius, which is most
probably the work of William of Champeaux, the teacher of Abelard and
founder of the school of St. Victor in Paris; thus it dates from the early twelfth
century.37 This aggressive ram with large testicles – both a pun on testes,
‘ witnesses,’’ and a sign for the adversarial nature of the legal proceeding –
features as well in the other twelfth-century commentaries, and had become
the standard academic gloss on this passage by the time Albertus wrote.38
Before proceeding to discuss the circumstances within which the
Herennian mnemonic was revived, let me summarize the features which
The arts of memory
179
seem to be distinctively medieval in the memory advice we have examined
in John of Garland, Thomas Bradwardine, and Albertus Magnus. With
respect to the memory locus, these are: (1) a plain-colored or simply
patterned background, with just enough suggestion of depth to be able
to position the images in relation to one another in a scene; (2) the observer
positioned frontally in respect to this scene, at a distance from which the
whole composition can be taken in completely at a glance; (3) a clear and
consistent arrangement of the images, which enables them to be read off in
sequence – this sequence can be from the center to either side, or, in a
circular arrangement, clockwise or counterclockwise (we will see examples
of these in Chapter 7). With respect to the imagines, they are: (1) their
grouping in a scene in which the order among them is expressed through
physical action; (2) the use of vivid, unusual, and extreme images; (3) the
use of images from a variety of sources, including the Bestiary, the
Calendar, and all other sorts of painted or sculpted forms, such as those
found commonly in churches and in books.
The placement of the memory locations is diagrammatic, frequently
within a grid. One of the most popular of late medieval ethical manuals was
an allegorical treatment of the game of chess, composed by the Dominican
friar, Jacopo da Cessola, around 1300. It was one of the works printed by
William Caxton. In an excellent essay on this work, Raymond DiLorenzo
commented that it uses mnemonic technique to integrate the ethical
material which the friar has composed as a set of memorabilia, ‘‘things-
to-be-remembered.’’ The mnemotechnique used is the chessboard, a grid,
into which imagines (the chess pieces, described with vivid and unusual
detail) are fitted. Jacopo prefaces the work, which is basically a florilegium,
by saying that chess was invented by a philosopher who sought to correct a
tyrannical king. As they played the game, the philosopher instructed the
king in the virtues and vices that attached to each piece. Thus the game
itself became for the king a mnemonic of kingly virtue and responsibility, a
Rule for Princes presented in a form that embeds its own mnemonic – the
form of a grid filled with images, familiar to medieval audiences as a basic
format for the page of memory. 39
The earliest medieval artes memorativae belong to the thirteenth century –
or, more precisely, the earliest written medieval artes belong to this period.
In Alcuin’s dialogue with Charlemagne on rhetoric (ninth century), the
king asks his teacher, Alcuin, if there are any specific precepts for memoria
(trained memory), which is the noblest aspect of rhetoric (‘‘nobilissima . . .
rhetoricae parte’ ). There are none, replies Alcuin, except disciplined
exercise in memorizing (‘‘ediscendi exercitationem’’), practice in writing,
180
The Book of Memory
and the discipline of cogitation or mental composition. One should
also avoid drunkenness (which is harmful to any discipline of soul or
body). Memoria is a store-house, custodian of invention and cogitation,
of ‘‘things’’ and ‘‘words,’’ and without it ‘‘even the most eminent of the
speaker’s other talents will come to nothing.’’ Charlemagne’s question
about precepts is another way of asking whether memoria is an art or not.
Alcuin takes for granted that memoria is a study, involving discipline,
training, and practice. But he apparently saw no need (at least for
Charlemagne) for a complex set of related precepts in addition to the
elementary principles of memory training. He thought of memory as a
consciously constructed inventory, a library, a store-house of material in
the form of both ‘‘words’ and ‘‘things.’’ But his advice to the emperor
does not go farther, to suggest a systematic art of memory. 40
This bias, if that is what it is, in favor of teaching rhetoric students a few
mnemonic principles instead of a systematized art of memory can also be
found in Quintilian and in the late Roman rhetoricians of the fourth and
later centuries. In De oratore, Cicero speaks of an architectural mnemonic
art as so well-known that it needs no elaborate description.41 But, 150 years
or so later, Quintilian, while not rejecting totally the notion of making an
art of memory, plays down its utility and that of other such artes. Evidently
a fashion favoring practice and discipline in the elements of memory
training over more elaborate, curious (and Greek) artes had begun to
dominate Roman pedagogy; this bias is consistent with Quintilian’s judg-
ments against using pre-fabricated mnemonic imagines and all other quick
prescriptions for memory training. Of course, the Ad Herennium also
counseled against substituting others’ schemes for one’s own; this is a
traditional pedagogical caution, the basis of Plato’s warning in Phaedrus
against substituting textbooks and recipes for teachers and disciplined
practice. But Quintilian’s bias towards philosophical rhetoric and against
the sophistical excesses he saw in his contemporaries like Seneca is reflected
again here in his remarks about the usefulness of artes memorativae. Instead,
he stresses the elementary aspects of memory training, reserving the various
arts for it to those of advanced ability – and to teachers of dubious
reputation (or so he implies).
The emphasis in the rhetoric schools on the elements rather than on an
advanced techne of memoria is found still in the fourth century. Julius
Victor wrote that ‘‘for impressing memory some teach observations of a
great many places and images, which do not seem effective to me.’’42 Since
he took a great deal from Quintilian, it is not surprising to find this
opinion, and it also indicates that during the centuries after Quintilian
The arts of memory
181
wrote, his judgment continued to predominate, despite the fact that
Cicero himself spoke favorably in De oratore o
f using memory arts based
on images in places. Julius Victor in turn greatly influenced Isidore of
Seville and Alcuin. Yet, as we have seen, Julius Victor does give instructions
in the basic mnemonic preparations: division, memory ‘‘for subjects’’ and
‘‘for words,’’ using memorial notae, meditation, and composition. So it
seems that in later antiquity and the earlier Middle Ages a memorial ars
such as that taught in the Ad Herennium was regarded in standard peda-
gogy as marginally helpful at best, and that the focus of memory training
was on its elements, instilled through practice and discipline, but without
emphasizing a universal body of principles. To use the traditional cate-
gories, memoria was taught as a studium, a collection of empirically proven
guidelines, but it was not a systematic ars, as it apparently had been
regarded in the time of Cicero and would be again by the end of the
thirteenth century. The distinction I am making is between what we would
call a craft, learned by apprenticeship, and a scientific discipline that can be
taught from a textbook.
Although arguments from silence are not worth much without positive,
corroborating evidence, it is interesting that Augustine makes no mention
of an art of memory, though trained as a teacher of rhetoric and though he
is one of the great philosophers of memory. Frances Yates attempted to
make a case for his having been a practitioner of the Herennian art, on the
basis of his descriptions of memory’s power in Book X of Confessions, of
which the following is typical:
See, in the measureless plains and vaults and caves of my memory, immeasurably
full of countless kinds of things which are there either through their images (as
with material things), or by being themselves present (as is the knowledge acquired
through a liberal education), or by registering themselves and making their mark
in some indefinable way (as with emotional states which the memory retains even
when the mind is not actually experiencing them, although whatever is in the
memory must be in the mind too) – in this wide land I am . . . free to run and fly to
and fro, to penetrate as deeply as I can, to collide with no boundary anywhere. So
great is the faculty of memory, so great the power of life.43
The metaphors Augustine uses here are archetypal: one did not need to
practice the Herennian art to believe that memory was locational in nature,
like a vast cave with many inner caverns in which all experience was
inventoried, and that it had immense power which training could enhance.
Indeed, though copied as one of Cicero’s works, the Rhetorica ad
Herennium was not much commented on or quoted until late in the
eleventh century. The earliest ancient references are in scattered sources
182
The Book of Memory
from Jerome (in works from 395 and 402) through Priscian (early sixth
century). None of these are to the memory section, it should be noted. Its
influence is not extensive until after the mid twelfth century, and even
later. 44
When it was first revived, its memory advice was received with skepti-
cism. John of Salisbury (who knew Quintilian’s Institutes better than most
of his contemporaries) alludes to arts of memory: ‘‘Seneca most readily
promised to teach the art for furnishing memories, of which I certainly
wish I were a master; but as far as I know, he did not actually teach it.
Tullius seems to have applied himself to this in [Rhetorica ad Herennium]
but the latter is not of much help to me.’’45 And Geoffrey of Vinsauf,
writing at the turn of the thirteenth century, dismisses the Ad Herennium’s
art completely: ‘‘Tullius relies on unusual images as a technique for training
the memory, but he is teaching himself; and let the subtle teacher, as it were
in solitude, address his subtlety to himself alone.’’46
Instead, Geoffrey counsels the traditional elements of memory training:
division, placing the pieces in a rigid locational order (one, two, three, etc.),
marking material with mental notae for secure recollection from the
storage-bin (cella) of memory, respecting the limits of short-term memory
(brevitas), and not stuffing too much in at one time, for the store-room of
memory responds well only while it is having fun, and so must be treated
well (‘‘Cellula quae meminit est cellula deliciarum’’). The problem with a
method like that described in the Ad Herennium is that it is gimmicky and
ready-made, whereas no single group of markers (notae) will work equally
well for everyone. Everyone should make little markers of his own choosing
and devising, for those are ‘‘safer,’’ tutior, for recollection. One should note
the concern Geoffrey expresses for the safety of a recollective scheme –
Thomas of Waleys has the same concern.47
One other early medieval writer on memory should be considered here,
because he is credited by Frances Yates as being the one who ‘‘handed on
the art [of memory] to the Middle Ages.’’48 This is Martianus Capella, a
fifth-century teacher whose allegorical encyclopedia on the seven liberal
arts, The Marriage of Philology and Mercury, became influential after the
turn of the first millennium. Martianus treats memoria in the traditional
way, as a part of rhetoric. But he is rarely mentioned as a proponent of an
art of memory and never, to my knowledge, linked with the precepts of
Tullius. What Martianus describes under memoria are some of the elemen-
tary rules of ancient mnemotechnique, but nothing that constitutes an art
of memory, let alone repeats what is peculiar to the architectural art of the
Ad Herennium. Indeed, the advice on memory training that is advocated by
The arts of memory
183
Cassiodorus (d. 590), whose Fundamentals of Divine and Secular Letters
became perhaps the most important academic text for the early Middle
Ages, is not that of Martianus Capella but of Consultus Fortunatianus (a
late fourth-century rhetoric master), from whom Martianus Capella cop-
ied a great deal. As we saw in Chapter 3, Fortunatianus’s advice belongs to
the elementary pedagogy of how to memorize a text, which one can find as
well in Quintilian. Like Martianus Capella, Fortunatianus represents the
mnemotechnical pedagogy which Augustine, Marius Victorinus, and other
teachers in late antiquity valued.
Martianus Capella says that while memory is a natural talent, it may
be assisted by training. The craft of memory has only a few rules and
requires much practice; but by it words and things can be grasped quickly
and surely. Memory-for-things is easier and less time-consuming than
memory-for-words, though the latter may be employed to recall hard
words or particular words one has trouble remembering. Simonides
invented the art from his experience when a banqueting hall collapsed,
and he was able to identify the victims because he had attached their names
to the places where they were seated. Order is thus the key to the precepts of
memory training. The order is memorized as a set of distinctive mental
locations into which
one puts images of things to be recalled – for example,
if one wants to remember a wedding, one would place the image of a girl in
a saffron wedding veil; if a murderer, a sword or other weapon. ‘‘For just as
what is written is contained in wax and letters, so what is committed to
memory is written into areas as if on wax and in page-form [in cera
paginaque signatur].’’49 But since much labor is required for remembering,
we should write down what we wish readily to retain. If the material is long,
divide it into shorter sections for ease of memorizing. It is useful to mark
with notae things we want particularly to recall. When memorizing, one
should not read aloud but meditate upon the material in a low murmur. It
is best to exercise the memory at night, when silence aids concentration.50
The ultimate sources for all of this lore are De oratore and Quintilian’s
Institutes, not the Ad Herennium. Martianus himself provides the particular
examples. A particular order – this order – is memorized (‘‘is [ordo] . . .
meditandus est’’) as a set of distinctive, well-known (and well-lighted)
locations (‘‘in locis illustribus’’). Into these locations the likenesses of
objects (‘‘species rerum’’) and images of subject matters (‘‘sententiarumque
imagines’’) are gathered (‘‘collocandae sunt’’). Rather than a procedure
like that for forming places advised in the architectural mnemonic, what
Martianus counsels is a prototype of advice like that of Hugh of St. Victor
(and others, as we shall see) – to make a diagram, linea, in one’s mind that
184
The Book of Memory
acts as a schematic ordering device for material that is then put into it. This
is the commonest type of medieval description for what one does in
forming memory places, and it is not the same kind of procedure as that
described in the Ad Herennium. Bradwardine’s sets of places in fives, one
on top of another as in a matrix, is more like constructing a diagram than it
is like walking through a house one knows familiarly. The schematic
quality is distinctively medieval.
From the time of Quintilian then, memoria seems to have been com-
monly taught as an elementary practice, consisting of a few basic rules and
some common-sense advice, eclectic, empirical, pragmatic, but not a