Book Read Free

The Book of Memory

Page 66

by Mary Carruthers


  Part of the evidence for placing the manuscript’s making in Rome lies in the

  four legs on the closed chest: similar iconography occured in fifth-century

  mural paintings in the basilica of San Paolo fuor le mure in Rome (Verkerk,

  165). Her arguments have not everywhere been accepted, and other scholars

  continue to believe, because of different affinities both textual and pictorial,

  that the manuscript is probably Spanish, perhaps with a North African

  connection. The date of late sixth to early seventh century has more general

  acceptance. Showing Noah’s Ark as a boat became standard only later: see

  Unger, The Art of Medieval Technology, 39–40.

  117. Smalley, Study of the Bible, 5, quotes Philo. A full analysis of architectural

  metaphors in Biblical exegesis is in de Lubac, Exe´gèse me´die´vale, 4. 41–60.

  Authority for this idea may be found in texts like Proverbs 24:3–4: ‘‘Through

  wisdom is an house builded; and by understanding it is established: And by

  knowledge shall the chambers be filled with all precious and pleasant riches.’’

  I discuss the architecture model, fundamental in monastic meditation prac-

  tice, at length in The Craft of Thought.

  118. Gregory the Great, Moralia in Job, epistula ad Leandrum 3. 109–114: ‘‘Nam

  primum quidem fundamenta historiae ponimus; deinde per significationem

  Notes to pp. 53–55

  385

  typicam in arcem fidei fabricam mentis erigimus; ad extremum quoque per

  moralitatis gratiam, quasi superducto aedificium colore uestimus.’’

  119. Du Cange, s.v. mens. Hugh says in De archa Noe that the mens holds time

  (Bk. II. i. 8–12). Dante’s use of mente can sometimes be synonymous with

  memoria (for example Inferno 2, 7–9). Chaucer says of the dying Arcite: ‘‘For

  he was yet in memorie and alyve,’’ in a context where we would use the word

  ‘‘conscious’ (Canterbury Tales, I. 2698).

  120. The various titles given to this work are listed in Goy, Die U

  ¨ berlieferung der

  Werke Hugos von St. Viktor, 212: these are only a few of the variants. In his

  edition for the CCSL, Sicard calls it simply De archa Noe, and the work

  formerly titled ‘‘De Arca Noe mystica’’ he has retitled Libellus de formatione

  arche. Sicard also commented extensively on the textual relationships of the

  two works, concluding that they indeed belong together; see also his

  Diagrammes me´die´vaux. The treatise De archa Noe was translated into

  English (from the edition in PL 176) by ‘‘a Religious of C.S.M.V.,’’ Hugh

  of St. Victor: Selected Spiritual Writings. I will discuss Libellus in Chapter 7.

  121. Jerome, Commentarii in Hiezechielem, esp. Books 12–14.

  122. Hugh of St. Victor, De archa Noe, I . iii. 35–37 (CCCM 176, 10): ‘‘Huius uero

  spiritualis edificii exemplar tibi dabo archam Noe, quam foris uidebit oculus

  tuus, ut ad eius similitudinem intus fabricetur animus tuus.’’

  123. Hugh of St. Victor, De archa Noe, I . iii. 236–238 (CCCM 176, 17): ‘‘quam

  cotidie sapientia edificat in cordibus nostris ex iugi legis Dei meditatione.’’

  124. Jerome, Commentarii in Hiezechielem xii, on Ez. 40:4; CCSL 75 (554. 178).

  125. Jerome, Commentarii in Hiezechielem i, on Ez. 3:5; CCSL 75 (32. 850–854):

  ‘‘Principia lectionis et simplicis historiae, esus uoluminis est; quando uero

  assidua meditatione in memoriae thesauro librum Domini condiderimus,

  impletur spiritaliter uenter noster et saturantur uiscera ut habeamus, cum

  apostolo Paulo, uiscera misericordiae.’’

  126. Hugh of St. Victor, De archa Noe, I I . i. 10–15 (CCCM 176, 33): ‘‘ita etiam in

  mente nostra preterita, presentia, et futura per cogitationem simul subsis-

  tunt. Si ergo per studium meditationis assidue cor nostrum inhabitare

  ceperimus, iam quodammodo temporales esse desistimus et quasi mortui

  mundo facti intus cum Deo uiuimus.’’

  127. Hugh of St. Victor, De archa Noe, I I . i. 42–43 (CCCM 176, 34): ‘‘Hec est

  archa, quam edificare debes.’’

  128. Hugh of St. Victor, De archa Noe, I V . ix. 132–140 (CCCM 176, 115–116): ‘‘Hec

  archa similis est apothece omnium deliciarum uarietate referte. Nichil in ea

  quesieris quod non inuenias. Et cum unum inueneris, multa tibi patefacta

  uidebis. Ibi uniuersa opera restaurationis nostre a principio mundi usque ad

  finem plenissime continentur, et status uniuersalis Ecclesie figuratur. Ibi

  historia rerum gestarum texitur, ibi mysteria sacramentorum inueniuntur,

  ibi dispositi sunt gradus affectuum, cogitationum, meditationum, contem-

  plationum, bonorum operum, uirtutum et premiorum.’’

  129. Du Cange, s.v. apotheca, apothecarii. At least by the thirteenth century, the

  word seems sometimes to have meant specifically drugs and medicines

  386

  Notes to pp. 56–59

  (s.v. apothecaria). In great houses in France, the ‘‘dessert chef’’ seems to have

  been called apothecarius (s.v. apothecarii, 4). It is worth recalling that sugars

  were relatively scarce and often considered to have healing properties.

  C HA P T E R 2

  1. G. R. Evans, ‘‘Two Aspects of Memoria,’’ 263. I discuss this matter at greater

  length in Chapter 4.

  2. Wolfson’s essay is both philosophical and philological in nature, tracing the

  usage of the Latin terms and how they translate Greek and Arabic (and

  Hebrew, where appropriate). Wolfson’s essay should be read in conjunction

  with Bundy, Theory of Imagination, whose pioneering and deservedly influential

  study it corrects in some important aspects. A useful overview of Arabic-

  medieval medical doctrine is Harvey, The Inward Wits. Minnis briefly surveyed

  the function of vis imaginativa in ‘‘Langland’s Ymaginatyf and Late Medieval

  Theories of the Imagination’’ – his essay begins to provide a corrective to overly

  stringent interpretations of medieval faculty psychology, though like many

  characterizations of what medieval people thought about imagination, it suffers

  from being too narrowly focused both in topic and in sources considered. See

  also the translated commentaries on Aristotle’s De memoria et reminiscentia by

  Albertus Magnus and by Thomas Aquinas in Carruthers and Ziolkowski, eds.,

  The Medieval Craft of Memory.

  3. Wolfson, 115.

  4. These doctrines are well reviewed in the Dictionnaire de Spiritualite´, s.v. sens

  inteŕieur, and see also Rahner, ‘‘The Doctrine of the Spiritual Senses’’ and ‘‘The

  ‘Spiritual Senses’ according to Origen.’’

  5. See Richard Rorty’s comments in Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, esp. 3–13.

  6. See Matson, ‘‘Why Isn’t the Mind–Body Problem Ancient?’’ 93.

  7. Aristotle, De memoria, 451b 10ff. Though the actual role of the brain in sensory

  experience and memory was accepted generally, an additional role for the heart

  as the organ both of memory and of sensation remained. An excellent account

  of ancient teaching on the psychology of memory is in Coleman, Ancient and

  Medieval Memories. On the later medieval emphasis on the heart in literature,

  see especially Jager, The Book of the Heart. References to Aristotle’s De memoria

  et reminiscentia are by Bekker number (I will use the
short title De memoria

  from here on). Except where otherwise noted, I have used Sorabji’s translation

  throughout.

  8. Aristotle talks about the heart as the seat of perception in Parts of Animals, 666a

  14ff., and Generation of Animals, 781a 20ff. What he says in De memoria about

  the processing of memory-images, however, might be interpreted as qualifying

  these other statements. On Aristotle’s psychology, see the essays in A. O. Rorty,

  ed., Aristotle’s De anima.

  9. Wolfson, ‘‘The Internal Senses,’’ esp. 69–74; see also Harvey, Inward Wits, 4–8.

  Early medicine and the contributions of the Alexandrine anatomists (third

  century BC) are discussed in standard histories; a place to begin is Vegetti,

  Notes to pp. 59–61

  387

  ‘‘Hellenistic Medicine.’’ On medieval medicine and medical practice more

  generally, see Siraisi, Medieval and Early Renaissance Medicine. Several early

  drawings of the brain, including the one from CUL MS. Gg 1.1 reproduced

  herein as figure 3, can be found in Clarke and Dewhurst, Illustrated History of

  Brain Function.

  10. Varro, De lingua latina, V I , 46 (LCL, vol. 1, 214–215).

  11. Bosworth-Toller, An Anglo-Saxon Dictionary, s.v. heorte.

  12. See Chapter 1 above, note 124.

  13. Rorty discusses how the ‘ mind–body problem’’ was created in the Renaissance:

  Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, esp. 39–69. See also the first chapters of

  Chalmers, The Conscious Mind. The classic exploration of the problem by

  Nagle, ‘‘What is it Like to be a Bat?,’’ is an exceptionally succinct and well-

  crafted contribution that deserves more attention from literary historians and

  critics concerned with issues of subjectivity.

  14. Aristotle, De anima, I I , 1; cited by Matson, ‘‘Mind–Body Problem,’’ 97.

  15. Both quotations from Matson, ‘‘Mind–Body Problem,’’ 96–97; the whole

  essay analyzes the intellectual matrix of ancient discussions of soul and body.

  An analysis strongly linking ancient psychology, sensation and memory,

  ethical behavior, and political life is that of Tracy, Physiological Theory and

  the Doctrine of the Mean, who concludes that for Aristotle, and also Plato, the

  essential model for understanding is physiological, based upon notions of

  health in the organism. Tracy’s analysis has been corrected and nuanced by

  Martha Nussbaum, especially with respect to Aristotle’s understanding of the

  so-called ‘‘practical syllogism’ in ethical judgment; see her De motu animal-

  ium, 165–220, and The Therapy of Desire, 48–101. See also Cooper, Reason and

  Emotion, who particularly analyzes Aristotle’s ethical and political ideas in

  terms of his views on judgment, persuasion, and ‘‘civic friendship.’’

  16. Sorabji, Aristotle on Memory, 16. ‘‘Affection’’ and ‘‘emotion’’ are both words

  that must be understood physiologically – they affect and move the body.

  Nussbaum discusses the fact that for Aristotle emotion and judgment both can

  also be described in physiological terms, though they are not limited to such

  terms; Nussbaum, De motu animalium, 146–158.

  17. Either the weight itself on perceptual organs or the excessive fluidity which

  Aristotle associated with dwarfism, or both, hinders the persistence of images

  and makes it difficult for the motion set up by a sensory impression in a

  human receiver to stop and be ‘‘fixed’’ as a memory-image; see Sorabji,

  Aristotle on Memory, 114.

  18. Sarton, I I -I I , 893–900, gives Arnaldus’s bibliography and the printed editions

  of his work; Arnaldus is discussed by Thorndike, History of Magic and

  Experimental Science, vol. 2, 841–861. More recently, see the edition by

  Garcia-Ballester, McVaugh et al. of Arnaldus’s complete medical works, still

  in progress.

  19. Arnaldus, Opera omnia, (Basle, 1585), in which see esp. Aphorismorum, cols.

  243–244, and ‘‘De bonitate memorie,’’ cols. 837–838; the latter appears to be a

  recension of the advice in Aphorismorum, together with some recipes for

  388

  Notes to pp. 61–63

  memory enhancement ‘‘praised by the authorities,’’ ‘‘laudata ab autoribus.’’

  The Aphorismi de gradibus, which appeared as vol. 2 (1975) of the complete

  edition of Arnaldus’s medical works, is an important work on mixture,

  complexion, and ‘‘degrees,’’ but has little to say about memory.

  20. ‘‘Supervitet coitum superfluum et carnes facilis digestionis,’’ ‘‘One especially

  should avoid unnecessary intercourse and easily digested meats’’; Matheolus

  Perusinus, De augenda memoriae (Rome, [1494] iv.r.; I used the copy in the

  Newberry Library, Chicago). Advice against drunkenness is also given by

  Alcuin in his dialogue on rhetoric (ninth century); undoubtedly, some of

  these prescriptions were passed along orally, and some are based on continuing

  observation. It is well to remind ourselves that Avicenna’s work is compen-

  dious; he is an originator in the pre-modern sense, not in our own.

  21. That is, ‘‘gaudium temperatum et honesta delectio’’ (Aphorismorum, col.

  244D); the likening of feeding memory to feeding the stomach is most fully

  expressed by Geoffrey of Vinsauf, but the memory–stomach metaphor is

  pervasive; it lies behind the standard monastic (and patristic) metaphor of

  meditatio as ‘‘rumination’’; see Chapter 5, below.

  22. Guy de Chauliac, 617, 620, and 627. Pepper is also of fourth-degree hotness,

  and so would presumably not be good for memory, although it is rarely

  mentioned as a specific prohibition.

  23. Matheolus, De augenda memoriae, 4.v.: ‘‘Corpus teneatur mundum a super-

  fluitatibus vnde quottidie ventris beneficium et si non naturale fiat artificiale.’’

  24. Arnaldus, Aphorismorum, col. 244E.

  25. Arnaldus, Aphorismorum, col. 244: ‘‘Solicitudo et visorum seu auditorum

  frequens recordatio, memoriam corroborat et confirmat.’’

  26. See Wolfson, ‘‘The Internal Senses,’’ 120–122.

  27. Aristotle, De memoria, 450a 10–15; Sorabji, Aristotle on Memory, 49; Wolfson,

  ‘‘The Internal Senses,’’ 74–76.

  28. Aristotle, De memoria, 449b 30. Nussbaum comments that it is not clear what

  sort of image Aristotle thought one utilized for concepts like ‘‘goodness’’ or

  ‘‘truth’’: De motu animalium, 266–267. Thomas Aquinas says that intellect

  itself retains ‘‘knowledge-forms’’ (it is conservativa specierum), concepts, and

  other things composed for thinking; see Kenny, Aquinas on Mind, 41–57, who

  explains what Aquinas meant by species and the relation of this concept to his

  distinctive psychology of an ‘‘agent intellect.’’ Though this is a crucial differ-

  ence in certain contexts (it is a major difference between Aristotle and

  Neoplatonism, and important as well in Christian descriptions of how an

  individual soul can be immortal), for the purpose of my discussion of memory

  in this chapter it would only be confusing to emphasize it.

  29. That is, ‘‘centrum omnium sensuum et a qua derivantur rami et cui reddunt

  sensus, et ipsa est vere quae sentit’’; Avicenna, Liber de anima, IV. 1; p. 5, l
ines

  57–59.

  30. Aristotle, De anima, I I I , ii, 425b 12ff. Aristotle, and indeed the whole classical–-

  medieval tradition, did not distinguish between sound-as-heard and as vibra-

  tion of air; for them, sound was sound and wasn’t pertinent to the human

  Notes to pp. 63–69

  389

  mind unless some abstracting process was involved. As Matson points out,

  this is one reason why they had no mind–body problem.

  31. I realize that the concept of ‘‘raw feels’’ is a spin-off of the mind–body problem,

  and so on the historical grounds I argued earlier I shouldn’t even introduce the

  language here; but I hope I will be forgiven. On ‘‘raw feels,’ see R. Rorty,

  Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, esp. 24, 88–98. See also Nagle, ‘‘What is it

  Like to be a Bat?’’

  32. Harvey summarizes al-Razi’s account (c. 900), 9–13, which in turn depended

  largely upon Galen. Four ventricles are described, a pair in front and two

  behind them, one following the other. Imaginatio is located in the front pair,

  cogitatio in the middle one, and memoria in the last one. The concept of vital

  spirits within the material body – one might think of these as the body’s

  energy – is found throughout ancient and medieval psychology. They

  were carried and channeled by hollow vessels, the nervi, and were active also

  in the various ventricles of the brain, but exactly what they were composed

  of was a matter of dispute. The nature of the vital spirits was a critical

  concern for Descartes, but less fraught in earlier medical thought; see esp.

  Jacquart, ‘‘Medical Scholasticism,’’ and Vegetti, ‘‘Between Knowledge and

  Practice.’’ Sutton, Philosophy and Memory Traces, provides an account of

  Descartes’s ideas about vital spirits that helps clarify his departures from

  previous thought.

  33. Avicenna, Liber de anima, I V , i (ed. Van Riet, 6. 66–68): ‘‘Formam enim

  sensibilem retinet illa quae vocatur formalis et imaginatio, et non discernit

  illam ullo modo.’’

  34. Wolfson, ‘‘The Internal Senses,’’ 92.

  35. Aristotle, De anima, I I I , xi, 434a 9–10.

  36. Wolfson, ‘‘The Internal Senses,’’ 86–95.

  37. Wolfson, ‘‘The Internal Senses,’’ 118–119.

  38. Janet Coleman has some acute remarks on the importance of intentio

 

‹ Prev