Tom Stoppard Plays 3
Page 17
ANDERSON: Don’t be such an ass.
(MCKENDRICK takes this as an intellectual objection.)
MCKENDRICK: You think it’s the adulation, perhaps? (To CRISP) Is it the adulation, Tommy, which has corrupted you?
CRISP: What’s he flaming on about?
CHAMBERLAIN: Well, I think it’s time for my shut-eye.
CRISP: No, I want to know what he’s saying about me. He’s giving me the needle.
ANDERSON: (To MCKENDRICK) May I remind you that you profess to be something of a pragmatist yourself in matters of ethics –
MCKENDRICK: Ah yes – I –see – you think that because I don’t believe in reliable signposts on the yellow brick road to rainbowland, you think I’m a bit of a yob myself – the swift kick in the kneecap on the way up the academic ladder – the Roy Broadbent of Stoke – (To BROADBENT) Stoke’s my team, you know.
BROADBENT: Will you tell this stupid bugger his philosophy is getting up my nostrils.
GRAYSON: You’re not making much sense, old boy.
MCKENDRICK: Ah! Grayson here has a fine logical mind. He has put his finger on the flaw in my argument, namely that the reason footballers are yobs may be nothing to do with being working class, or with financial greed, or with adulation, or even with being footballers. It may be simply that football attracts a certain kind of person, namely yobs –
(This is as far as he gets when BROADBENT smashes him in the face. MCKENDRICK drops.)
CRISP: Good on you, Roy.
(ANDERSON goes to MCKENDRICK, who is flat on the floor.)
ANDERSON: McKendrick …
CHAMBERLAIN: Well, I’m going to bed.
(CHAMBERLAIN goes through the connecting door into his own room and closes the door.)
BROADBENT: He can’t say that sort of thing and get away with it.
GRAYSON: Where’s his room?
ANDERSON: On the third floor.
GRAYSON: Bloody hell.
CRISP: He’s waking up.
BROADBENT: He’s all right.
ANDERSON: Come on, McKendrick.
(They all lift MCKENDRICK to his feet. MCKENDRICK makes no protest. He’s just about able to walk.)
I’ll take him down in the lift. (He sees the typewriter in its case and says to GRAYSON) I’ll come back for the typewriter. (He leads MCKENDRICK towards the door.)
MCKENDRICK: (Mutters) All right. I went too far. Let’s talk about something else.
(But MCKENDRICK keeps walking or staggering. ANDERSON opens GRAYSON’s door.)
BROADBENT: Here. That bloody Jirasek. Just like you said.
ANDERSON: Yes.
BROADBENT: They don’t teach you nothing at that place, then?
ANDERSON: No.
(ANDERSON helps MCKENDRICK out and closes the door.)
11. INT. THE COLLOQUIUM
ANDERSON comes to the lectern. There is a Czech chairman behind him.
CHETWYN is in the audience but MCKENDRICK is not. We arrive as ANDERSON approaches the microphone. ANDERSON lays a sheaf of typewritten paper on the lectern.
ANDERSON: I propose in this paper to take up a problem which many have taken up before me, namely the conflict between the rights of individuals and the rights of the community. I will be making a distinction between rights and rules.
(We note that the CHAIRMAN, listening politely and intently, is suddenly puzzled. He himself has same papers and from these he extracts one, which is in fact the official copy of Anderson’s official paper. He starts looking at it. It doesn’t take him long to satisfy himself that ANDERSON is giving a different paper. These things happen while ANDERSON speaks. At the same time the three INTERPRETERS in their booths, while speaking into their microphones as ANDERSON speaks, are also in some difficulty because they have copies of Anderson’s official paper.) I will seek to show that rules, in so far as they are related to rights, are a secondary and consequential elaboration of primary rights, and I will be associating rules generally with communities and rights generally with individuals. I will seek to show that a conflict between the two is generally a pseudo-conflict arising out of one side or the other pressing a pseudo-right. Although claiming priority for rights over rules – where they are in conflict – I will be defining rights as fictions acting as incentives to the adoption of practical values; and I will further propose that although these rights are fictions, there is an obligation to treat them as if they were truths; and further, that although this obligation can be shown to be based on values which are based on fictions, there is an obligation to treat that obligation as though it were based on truth; and so on ad infinitum.
(At this point the CHAIRMAN interrupts him.)
CHAIRMAN: Pardon me – Professor – this is not your paper –
ANDERSON: In what sense? I am indisputably giving it.
CHAIRMAN: But it is not the paper you were invited to give.
ANDERSON: I wasn’t invited to give a particular paper.
CHAIRMAN: You offered one.
ANDERSON: That’s true.
CHAIRMAN: But this is not it.
ANDERSON: No. I changed my mind.
CHAIRMAN: But it is irregular.
ANDERSON: I didn’t realize it mattered.
CHAIRMAN: It is a discourtesy.
ANDERSON: (Taken aback) Bad manners? I am sorry.
CHAIRMAN: You cannot give this paper. We do not have copies.
ANDERSON: Do you mean that philosophical papers require some sort of clearance?
CHAIRMAN: The interpreters cannot work without copies.
ANDERSON: Don’t worry. It is not a technical paper. I will speak a little slower if you like. (ANDERSON turns back to the microphone.) If we decline to define rights as fictions, albeit with the force of truths, there are only two senses in which humans could be said to have rights. Firstly, humans might be said to have certain rights if they had collectively and mutually agreed to give each other these rights. This would merely mean that humanity is a rather large club with club rules, but it is not what is generally meant by human rights. It is not what Locke meant, and it is not what the American Founding Fathers meant when, taking the hint from Locke, they held certain rights to be inalienable – among them, life, liberty and the pursuit of happiness. The early Americans claimed these as the endowment of God – which is the second sense in which humans might be said to have rights. This is a view more encouraged in some communities than in others. I do not wish to dwell on it here except to say that it is a view and not a deduction, and that I do not hold it myself. What strikes us is the consensus about an individual’s right put forward both by those who invoke God’s authority and by those who invoke no authority at all other than their own idea of what is fair and sensible. The first Article of the American Constitution, guaranteeing freedom of religious observance, of expression, of the press, and of assembly, is closely echoed by Articles 28 and 32 of the no less admirable Constitution of Czechoslovakia, our generous hosts on this occasion. Likewise, protection from invasion of privacy, from unreasonable search and from interference with letters and correspondence guaranteed to the American people by Article 4 is likewise guaranteed to the Czech people by Article 31.
(The CHAIRMAN, who has been more and more uncomfortable, leaves the stage at this point. He goes into the ‘wings’. At some distance from ANDERSON, but still just in earshot of ANDERSON, i.e. one can hear Anderson’s words clearly if faintly, is a telephone. Perhaps in a stage manager’s office. We go with the CHAIRMAN but we can still hear ANDERSON.)
Is such a consensus remarkable? Not at all. If there is a God, we his creations would doubtless subscribe to his values. And if there is not a God, he, our creation, would undoubtedly be credited with values which we think to be fair and sensible. But what is fairness? What is sense? What are these values which we take to be self-evident? And why are they values?
12. INT. MCKENDRICK’S ROOM
MCKENDRICK is fully dressed and coming round from a severe hangover. His room is untidier than Anderso
n’s. Clothes are strewn about. His suitcase, half full, is open. His briefcase is also in evidence. MCKENDRICK looks at his watch, but it has stopped. He goes to the telephone and dials.
13. INT. ANDERSON’S ROOM
The phone starts to ring. The camera pulls back from the phone and we see that there are two men in the room, plain-clothes POLICEMEN, searching the room. They look at the phone but only for a moment, and while it rings they continue quietly. They search the room very discreetly. We see one carefully slide open a drawer and we cut away.
14. THE COLLOQUIUM
We have returned to Anderson’s paper. There is no CHAIRMAN on stage.
ANDERSON: Ethics were once regarded as a sort of monument, a ghostly Eiffel Tower constructed of Platonic entities like honesty, loyalty, fairness, and so on, all bolted together and consistent with each other, harmoniously stressed so as to keep the edifice standing up: an ideal against which we measured our behaviour. The tower has long been demolished. In our own time linguistic philosophy proposes that the notion of, say, justice has no existence outside the ways in which we choose to employ the word, and indeed consists only of the way in which we employ it. In other words, that ethics are not the inspiration of our behaviour but merely the creation of our utterances.
(Over the latter part of this we have gone back to the CHAIRMAN who is on the telephone. The CHAIRMAN is doing little talking and some listening.)
And yet common observation shows us that this view demands qualification. A small child who cries ‘that’s not fair’ when punished for something done by his brother or sister is apparently appealing to an idea of justice which is, for want of a better word, natural. And we must see that natural justice, however illusory, does inspire many people’s behaviour much of the time. As an ethical utterance it seems to be an attempt to define a sense of rightness which is not simply derived from some other utterance elsewhere.
(We cut now to a backstage area, but ANDERSON’s voice is continuous, heard through the sort of PA system which one finds backstage at theatres.
The CHAIRMAN hurries along the corridor, seeking and now finding a uniformed ‘FIREMAN’, a backstage official. During this ANDERSON speaks.)
Now a philosopher exploring the difficult terrain of right and wrong should not be over-impressed by the argument ‘a child would know the difference’. But when, let us say, we are being persuaded that it is ethical to put someone in prison for reading or writing the wrong books, it is well to be reminded that you can persuade a man to believe almost anything provided he is clever enough, but it is much more difficult to persuade someone less clever. There is a sense of right and wrong which precedes utterance. It is individually experienced and it concerns one person’s dealings with another person. From this experience we have built a system of ethics which is the sum of individual acts of recognition of individual right.
(During this we have returned to ANDERSON in person. And at this point the CHAIRMAN re-enters the stage and goes and sits in his chair. ANDERSON continues, ignoring him.)
If this is so, the implications are serious for a collective or state ethic which finds itself in conflict with individual rights, and seeks, in the name of the people, to impose its values on the very individuals who comprise the state. The illogic of this manoeuvre is an embarrassment to totalitarian systems. An attempt is sometimes made to answer it by consigning the whole argument to ‘bourgeois logic’, which is a concept no easier to grasp than bourgeois physics or bourgeois astronomy. No, the fallacy must lie elsewhere –
(At this point loud bells, electric bells, ring. The fire alarm. The CHAIRMAN leaps up and shouts.)
CHAIRMAN: (In Czech) Don’t panic! There appears to be a fire Please leave the hall in an orderly manner. (In English) Fire! Please leave quietly!
(The philosophers get to their feet and start heading for the exit. ANDERSON calmly gathers his papers up and leaves the stage.)
15. INT. AIRPORT
People leaving the country have to go through a baggage check. There are at least three separate but adjacent benches at which CUSTOMS MEN and WOMEN search the baggage of travellers. The situation here is as follows:
At the first bench CHETWYN is in mid-search.
At the second bench ANDERSON is in mid-search.
At the third bench a traveller is in mid-search.
There is a short queue of people waiting for each bench. The leading man in the queue waiting for the third bench is MCKENDRICK. The search at this third bench is cursory.
However, ANDERSON is being searched very thoroughly. We begin on ANDERSON. We have not yet noted CHETWYN.
At Anderson’s bench a uniformed CUSTOMS WOMAN is examining the contents of his suitcase, helped by a uniformed CUSTOMS MAN. At the same time a plain-clothes POLICEMAN is very carefully searching everything in Anderson’s briefcase.
We see the CUSTOMS MAN take a cellophane-wrapped box of chocolates from Anderson’s case. He strips off the cellophane and looks at the chocolates and then he digs down to look at the second layer of chocolates. ANDERSON watches this with amazement. The chocolate box is closed and put back in the case. Meanwhile, a nest of wooden dolls, the kind in which one doll fits inside another, is reduced to its components.
The camera moves to find MCKENDRICK arriving at the third desk. There is no plain-clothes POLICEMAN there. The CUSTOMS OFFICER there opens his briefcase and flips, in a rather cursory way, through McKendrick’s papers. He asks MCKENDRICK to open his case. He digs about for a moment in McKendrick’s case.
Back at Anderson’s bench the plain-clothes POLICEMAN is taking Anderson’s wallet from ANDERSON’s hand. He goes through every piece of paper in the wallet.
We go back to McKendrick’s bench to find MCKENDRICK closing his case and being moved on. MCKENDRICK turns round to ANDERSON to speak.
MCKENDRICK: You picked the wrong queue, old man. Russian roulette. And Chetwyn.
(We now discover CHETWYN, who is going through a similar search to Anderson’s. He has a plain-clothes POLICEMAN too. This POLICEMAN is looking down the spine of a book from Chetwyn’s suitcase. We now return to Anderson’s bench. We find that the CUSTOMS MAN has discovered a suspicious bulge in the zipped compartment on the underside of the lid of Anderson’s suitcase. ANDERSON’s face tells us that he has a spasm of anxiety. The bulge suggests something about the size of Hollar’s envelope. The CUSTOMS MAN zips open the compartment and extracts the copy of McKendrick’s girlie magazine. ANDERSON is embarrassed.
We return to CHETWYN, whose briefcase is being searched paper by paper. The CUSTOMS OFFICIAL searching his suitcase finds a laundered shirt, nicely ironed and folded. He opens the shirt up and discovers about half a dozen sheets of writing-paper. Thin paper with typewriting on it. Also a photograph of a man. The plain-clothes POLICEMAN joins the CUSTOMS OFFICIAL and he starts looking at these pieces of paper. He looks up at CHETWYN, whose face has gone white.)
16. INT. AEROPLANE
The plane is taxiing.
MCKENDRICK and ANDERSON are sitting together.
MCKENDRICK looks shocked.
ANDERSON: Silly bugger. Honestly.
ANDERSON: It’s all right – they’ll put him on the next plane.
MCKENDRICK: To Siberia.
ANDERSON: No, no, don’t be ridiculous. It wouldn’t look well for them, would it? All the publicity. I don’t think there’s anything in Czech law about being in possession of letters to Amnesty International and the UN and that sort of thing They couldn’t treat Chetwyn as though he were a Czech national anyway.
MCKENDRICK: Very unpleasant for him though.
ANDERSON: Yes.
MCKENDRICK: He took a big risk.
ANDERSON: Yes.
MCKENDRICK: I wouldn’t do it. Would you?
ANDERSON: No. He should have known he’d be searched.
MCKENDRICK: Why did they search you?
ANDERSON: They thought I might have something.
MCKENDRICK: Did you have anything?
AN
DERSON: I did in a way.
MCKENDRICK: What was it?
ANDERSON: A thesis. Apparently rather slanderous from the state’s point of view.
MCKENDRICK: Where did you hide it?
ANDERSON: In your briefcase.
(Pause.)
MCKENDRICK: You what?
ANDERSON: Last night. I’m afraid I reversed a principle.
(MCKENDRICK opens his briefcase and finds Hollar’s envelope, ANDERSON takes it from him. MCKENDRICK is furious.)
MCKENDRICK: You utter bastard.
ANDERSON: I thought you would approve.
MCKENDRICK: Don’t get clever with me. (He relapses, shaking.) Jesus. It’s not quite playing the game is it? ANDERSON: No, I suppose not. But they were very unlikely to
search you.
MCKENDRICK: That’s not the bloody point.
ANDERSON: I thought it was. But you could be right. Ethics is a very complicated business. That’s why they have these congresses.
(The plane picks up speed on the runway towards take-off.)
SQUARING THE CIRCLE
Poland 1980–81
CHARACTERS
NARRATOR WALESA CHILDREN
LEONID BREZHNEV DANUTA WALESA
EDWARD GIEREK MAZOWIECKI
BREZHNEV’S AIDE MODZELEWSKI
BABIUCH MARIAN JURCZYK
KANIA ANDRZEJ GWIAZDA
SZYDLAK JAN RULEWSKI
WOJCIECH JARUZELSKI BUJAK
BARCIKOWSKI BOGDAN LIS
JAGIELSKI JUDGE
FINANSKY GANG MEMBER
FIRST ELECTRICIAN PRIEST
SECOND ELECTRICIAN PUBLIC PROSECUTOR
MACIEJ SZCZEPANSKI SOVIET AMBASSADOR
JACEK KURON GERMAN SPOKESMAN
GEREMEK MARSHAL KULIKOV
GIEREK’S SECRETARY WORKER
GERMAN BANKER PARTY OFFICIAL
AMERICAN BANKER MIECZYSLAW RAKOWSKI
SWISS BANKER DOCTOR