Positional Option Trading (Wiley Trading)
Page 2
Published by John Wiley & Sons, Inc., Hoboken, New Jersey.
Published simultaneously in Canada.
No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or
transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying,
recording, scanning, or otherwise, except as permitted under Section 107 or 108
of the 1976 United States Copyright Act, without either the prior written
permission of the Publisher, or authorization through payment of the
appropriate per-copy fee to the Copyright Clearance Center, Inc., 222 Rosewood
Drive, Danvers, MA 01923, (978) 750–8400, fax (978) 646–8600, or on the
Web at www.copyright.com. Requests to the Publisher for permission should be addressed to the Permissions Department, John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 111 River
Street, Hoboken, NJ 07030, (201) 748–6011, fax (201) 748–6008, or online at
www.wiley.com/go/permissions.
Limit of Liability/Disclaimer of Warranty: While the publisher and author have
used their best efforts in preparing this book, they make no representations or
warranties with respect to the accuracy or completeness of the contents of this
book and specifically disclaim any implied warranties of merchantability or
fitness for a particular purpose. No warranty may be created or extended by
sales representatives or written sales materials. The advice and strategies
contained herein may not be suitable for your situation. You should consult
with a professional where appropriate. Neither the publisher nor author shall
be liable for any loss of profit or any other commercial damages, including but
not limited to special, incidental, consequential, or other damages.
For general information on our other products and services or for technical
support, please contact our Customer Care Department within the United
States at (800) 762–2974, outside the United States at (317) 572–3993, or fax
(317) 572–4002.
Wiley publishes in a variety of print and electronic formats and by print-on-
demand. Some material included with standard print versions of this book may
not be included in e-books or in print-on-demand. If this book refers to media
such as a CD or DVD that is not included in the version you purchased, you may
download this material at http://booksupport.wiley.com. For more information about Wiley products, visit www.wiley.com.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Names: Sinclair, Euan, 1969- author.
Title: Positional option trading : an advanced guide / Euan Sinclair.
Description: Hoboken, New Jersey : Wiley, [2020] | Series: Wiley trading series
| Includes bibliographical references and index.
Identifiers: LCCN 2020008849 (print) | LCCN 2020008850 (ebook) | ISBN
9781119583516 (hardback) | ISBN 9781119583523 (adobe pdf) | ISBN
9781119583530 (epub)
15
Subjects: LCSH: Options (Finance) | Financial futures.
Classification: LCC HG6024.A3 S56225 2020 (print) | LCC HG6024.A3 (ebook)
| DDC 332.64/53—dc23
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2020008849
LC ebook record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2020008850
Cover Design: Wiley
Cover Image: © blackred/Getty Images
16
INTRODUCTION
You know nothing, Jon Snow.
—Ygritte in A Storm of Swords by George R. R. Martin.
He is not the only one.
We are not in a time where reason is valued. In economics, the
idea that marginal tax cuts pay for themselves is still advanced,
even though all evidence says they don't.
Forty percent of Americans do not believe in evolution. Forty-five
percent believe in ghosts. These beliefs are not based on any
evidence. They are manifestations of another philosophy, whether
it is economic, religious, or sociological. Usually these opinions
reveal more about what people want to be true rather than any
facts that they know. And many people know few facts anyway.
Evidence is seen as irrelevant and arguments are won by those
who shout loudest and have the best media skills.
The idea that opinions are as valid as facts also affects trading and
investing. Many investors rely on methods that are either
unproven or even proven to be ineffective. The few of these
investors who keep records will see that they are failing but rely on
cognitive dissonance to continue to believe in their theories of how
the markets behave. One would think that losing money would
prompt reexamination, but the persistence of losers is remarkable.
And even when some people give up or are forced out, there is
always new money and new participants to replace the old.
The only way to learn about anything is through the scientific
method. This is an iterative procedure where theory is modified by
evidence. Without evidence we are just in the realm of opinion.
Most of what I present here is backed by evidence. There are also
some opinions. My justification for this is that experience is also a
real thing. But I'm no less prone to self-delusion than anyone else,
so feel free to pay less attention to these ideas.
Trading is fundamentally an exercise in managing ignorance. Our
ability to judge whether a situation presents a good opportunity
will always be based on only a simplified view of the world, and it
is impossible to know the effects of the simplification. Our pricing
17
model will be similarly compromised. It will be a simplification
and possibly a very unrealistic simplification. Finally, the
parameters the models need will have estimation errors and we
generally won't know how large these are.
It is impossible to understand the world if you insist on thinking
in absolute terms. The world is not black and white. Everything
has shades of gray. You won't learn much from this book is you
aren't comfortable with this.
This is clear for “risk.” Everyone has a different risk tolerance,
whether this is personal or imposed by management or investors.
But more important, risk is multidimensional. We are comfortable
with this idea in some areas of life. Imagine you have a choice of
going on vacation to either Costa Rica or Paris. Both are nice
places and any given person could reasonably choose either one.
But Paris has no beaches and Costa Rica doesn't have the
Pompidou Centre. There is no one correct choice in this situation.
And that is also the case in most investing decisions.
Many of the ideas I write about can be extrapolated to a ludicrous
level. But if you do, don't blame me or credit me with the resulting
conclusions.
In no particular order here are some facts that are often
misrepresented:
There is usually a variance premium. This does not mean there
is always a variance premium.
There is usually a variance premium. This does not mean you
should always be short volatility.
Short volatility can be risky. This does not mean that short
volatility has to have unlimited risk.
Some theories (e.g., GARCH, BSM, EMH, returns are normally
distributed) have limitations. This
does not mean the theories
are stupid or useless.
The Kelly criterion maximizes expected growth rate. This does
not mean you should always invest according to it.
If what I write is unclear or incorrect, that is a problem of my
making. But if you choose to ignore nuance, that is your issue.
18
Trading as a Process
I have made no attempt here to write a comprehensive option
trading book. I don't cover the definitions and specifications of
various types of options. There are no derivations of option pricing
models. I expect the reader to know about the common option
structures such as straddles, spreads, and strangles. Many books
cover these topics (e.g., Sinclair, 2010). A very brief summary of
the theory of volatility trading is provided in Chapter One, but this
is not a book for beginners.
This is a book for experienced traders who want the benefits of
including options in their strategies and portfolios but who are
unwilling or unable to perform high-frequency, low-cost dynamic
hedging. Again, there are many books on this type of positional
option trading, but none are theoretically rigorous, and most
ignore the most important part of trading anything: having an
edge.
One of the things that distinguishes professionals from amateurs
in any field is that professionals use a consistent process. Trading
should be a process: find a situation with edge, structure a trade,
then control the risk. This book documents these steps.
The book's first section explores how to find trades with positive
expectation.
In Chapter Two, we look at the efficient market hypothesis and
show that the idea leaves plenty of room for the discovery of
profitable strategies. This insight lets us categorize these
“anomalies” as either inefficiencies or risk premia. These will
behave differently and should be traded differently. Next, we
briefly review how behavioral psychology can help us and also its
limitations. We examine two popular methodologies for finding
edges: technical analysis and fundamental analysis.
Chapter Three looks at the general problem of forecasting. No
matter what they say, every successful trader forecasts. The
forecast may not be one that predicts a particular point value, but
probabilistic forecasting is still forecasting. We introduce a
classification of forecasting methods. Forecasts are either model
based, relying on a generally applicable model, or situational,
taking advantage of what happens in specific events. We very
briefly look at predicting volatility with time-series models before
moving on to our focus: finding specific situations that have edge.
19
The most important empirical fact that an option trader needs to know is that implied volatility is usually overpriced. This
phenomenon is called the variance premium (or the volatility
premium). Chapter Four summarizes the variance premium in
indices, stocks, commodities, volatility indices, and bonds. We
also present reasons for its existence.
Having established the primacy of the variance premium, Chapter
Five gives eleven specific phenomena that can be profitably
traded. The observation is summarized, the evidence and reasons
for the effect are given, and a structure for trading the idea is
suggested.
The second section examines the distributional properties of some
option structures that can be used to monetize the edge we have
found. We need to have an idea of what to expect. It is quite
possible to be right with our volatility forecasts and still lose
money. When we hedge, we become exposed to path dependency
of the underlying. It matters if a stock move occurs close to the
strike when we have gamma or away from a strike when we have
none. If we don't hedge, we are exposed to only the terminal stock
price, but we can still successfully forecast volatility and lose
because of an unanticipated drift. Or we can successfully forecast
the return and lose because of unanticipated volatility.
Chapter Six discusses volatility trading structures. We look at the
P/L distributions of straddles, strangles, butterflies, and condors,
and how to choose strikes and expirations.
In Chapter Seven we look at trading options directionally. First,
we extend the BSM model to incorporate our views on both the
volatility and return of the underlying. This enables us to
consistently compare strikes on the basis of a number of risk
measures, including average return, probability of profit, and the
generalized Sharpe ratio. Chapter Eight examines the P/L
distributions of common directional option structures.
The final section is about risk. Good risk control can't make
money. Trading first needs edge. However, bad risk management
will lead to losses.
Chapter Nine discusses trade sizing, specifically the Kelly
criterion. The standard formulation is extended to allow for
parameter estimation uncertainty, skewness of returns, and the
incorporation of a stop level in the account.
20
The most dangerous risks are not related to price movement. The
most dangerous risks are in the realm of the unknowable.
Obviously, it is impossible to predict these, but Chapter Ten
explores some historical examples. We don't know when these will
happen again, but it is certain that they will. There is no excuse for
blowing up due to repeat of a historical event.
It is inevitable that you will be wrong at times. The most
dangerous thing is to forget this.
Summary
Find a robust source of edge that is backed by empirical
evidence and convincing reasons for its existence.
Choose the appropriate option structure to monetize the edge.
Size the position appropriately.
Always be aware of how much you don't know.
21
CHAPTER 1
Options: A Summary
Option Pricing Models
Since all models are wrong the scientist must be alert to what
is importantly wrong. It is inappropriate to be concerned
about mice when there are tigers abroad.
—Box (1976)
Some models are wrong in a trivial way. They clearly don't agree
with real financial markets. For example, an option valuation
model that included the return of the underlying as a pricing input
is trivially wrong. This can be deduced from put-call parity.
Imagine a stock that has a positive return. Naively this will raise
the value of calls and lower the value of puts. But put-call parity
means that if calls increase, so do the values of the puts. Including
drift leads to a contradiction. That idea is trivially wrong.
Every scientific model contains simplifying assumptions. There
actually isn't anything intrinsically wrong with this. There are
many reasons why this is the case, because there are many types of
scientific models. Scientists use simplified models that they know
are wrong for several reasons.
A reason for using a wrong th
eory would be because the simple
(but wrong) theory is all that is needed. Classical mechanics is still
widely used in science even though we now know it is wrong
(quantum mechanics is needed for small things and relativity is
needed for large or fast things). An example from finance is
assuming normally distributed returns. It is doubtful anyone ever
thought returns were normal. Traders have long known about
extreme price moves and Osborne (1959), Mandelbrot (1963), and
others studied the non-normal distribution of returns from the
1950s. (Mandelbrot cites the work of Mitchell [1915], Olivier
[1926], and Mills [1927], although this research was not well known.) The main reason early finance theorists assumed
normality was because it made the equations tractable.
22
Sometimes scientists might reason through a stretched analogy.
For example, Einstein started his theory of the heat capacity of a
crystal by first assuming the crystal was an ideal gas. He knew that
this was obviously not the case. But he thought that the idea might
lead to something useful. He had to start somewhere, even if he
knew it was the wrong place. This model was metaphorical. A
metaphorical model does not attempt to describe reality and need
not rely on plausible assumptions. Instead, it aims to illustrate a
non-trivial mechanism, which lies outside the model.
Other models aim to mathematically describe the main features of
an observation without necessarily understanding its deeper
origin. The GARCH family of volatility models are
phenomenological, and don't tell us why the GARCH effects exist.
Because these models are designed to describe particular features,
there will be many other things they totally ignore. For example, a
GARCH process has nothing to say about the formation of the bid-
ask spread. The GARCH model is limited, but not wrong.
The most ambitious models attempt to describe reality as it truly
is. For example, the physicists who invented the idea that an atom
was a nucleus around which electrons orbited thought this was
actually what atoms were like. But they still had to make
simplifying assumptions. For example, when formulating the
theory, they had to assume that atoms were not subject to gravity.