Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 25

by Jeremy Jennings


  19 Augustin Barruel, Mémoires pour servir à l’histoire du jacobinisme (Chiré en Montreuil, 1973), 217.

  114

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  laziness those who purported to set France free had turned to Rousseau and Du

  Contrat social, ‘the worst book’, Mounier commented, ‘which has ever been written

  about government’. It was from his ‘principles of anarchy’ that these ‘modern

  legislators’ had taken their ideas. In their speeches and proclamations they had

  ‘without cease drawn upon the expressions of J.-J. Rousseau’.20

  How might the matter of Rousseau’s influence in the French Revolution be

  summarized? First, Rousseau was read by all sections of society, from the aristocracy

  downwards.21 Next, he was read in diverse and contradictory ways and those who

  cited Rousseau often did so for no better reason than to give added authority to

  their own views. Robespierre is a good example of this. Thirdly, if Rousseauian

  discourse undoubtedly permeated the revolutionary decade and if those who

  aspired to lead the revolution sought occasionally to put Rousseau’s ideas directly

  into practice, then equally the actions of the revolutionaries frequently contradicted

  anything Rousseau might have said. Bernard Manin, for example, points out that

  Jacobin policies on the economy and taxation owed nothing to Rousseau. He also

  reminds us that Robespierre specifically indicated that the theory of revolutionary

  government underpinning the Terror could not ‘be found in the books of writers

  on politics’.22

  Stated in this way, however, we have no sense of the emotional (and frequently

  tearful) frenzy that Rousseau induced amongst his disciples. The community born

  out of the social contract was to be frugal, hard-working, virtuous, distrustful of

  wealth, free of corruption, trusting to the simple qualities of the people cast as the

  repositories of all that was naturally good. Armed thus, men such as Robespierre

  and Saint-Just had little difficulty affirming their own rhetorical and moral ascen-

  dancy over opponents who bore the mark of evil. What happened when the people,

  corrupted by despotism, were found to be unworthy of the love that had been

  invested in them was the recourse to an ever-extensive dictatorship, with the general

  will supposedly articulated by a twelve-man Committee of Public Safety.

  The revolutionaries, then, were not just millenarians: they were ‘Rousseauist

  millenarians’.23 Moreover, the hypnotic effect of their actions was such as to

  bequeath to France a living tradition and style of politics––what Pierre Rosanvallon

  has termed a ‘political culture of generality’––that was deeply imbued with Rous-

  seauian notions. The bare bones of what virtually amounted to a revolutionary

  catechism can be easily sketched out.24 Sovereignty belonged to the people. There

  were no limits to sovereignty because the field of politics was itself without limits.

  It was the task of the community to ensure that the general will was respected and it

  alone had the right to decide upon the sacrifices that were to be demanded of each

  20 Mounier, Recherches sur les causes (179, 1973), 147–58.

  21 Roger Chartier, Les Origines culturelles de la Révolution française (1990), 105–7.

  22 Bernard Manin, ‘Rousseau’, in François Furet and Mona Ozouf (eds.), Dictionnaire critique de la

  Révolution française: Idées (1992), 457–81.

  23 Norman Hampson, ‘The Heavenly City of the French Revolutionaries’, in Colin Lucas (ed.),

  Rewriting the French Revolution (Oxford, 1991), 53.

  24 See Jacques Julliard, La Faute à Rousseau (1985) and Rosanvallon, Le Modèle politique français: La

  Société civile contre le jacobinisme de 1789 à nos jours (2004).

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  115

  individual. The role of government was limited to the execution of the general will

  as expressed by the people as sovereign. Money and the activities it engendered were

  the source of corruption and moral decline. The goal of politics was that of

  transformation and regeneration. Its political expression was to be the one and

  indivisible Republic. By general agreement, therefore, Rousseau’s greatness lay in

  his advocacy of liberty and in his recognition that this would demand the destruc-

  tion of all past forms of tyranny. For many in France he was the philosopher of

  fraternity.

  I I I

  In the immediate aftermath of the fall of Robespierre there was no shortage of

  commentary upon Rousseau’s work. Almost without exception a connection was

  made between Rousseau and the events of the Revolution and invariably Rousseau’s

  influence was seen in strongly negative terms. Time and time again his influence was

  attributed to his seductive style and to the naivety, if not the malice, of his readers.

  Clearly too there was a sense that his influence persisted and that his ideas still needed

  to be refuted. A work such as that by Pierre Landes, Principes du droit politique, mis en

  opposition avec ceux de J.J. Rousseau sur le Contrat social, for example, consisted of a

  point by point refutation of Rousseau’s ideas, beginning with the contention that, far

  from being born free, man was born weak and therefore in need of authority rather

  than liberty.25 Written slightly later, Gabriel-Jacques Dageville’s De la Propriété

  politique et civile argued, against Rousseau, that the ‘true’ social contract could only

  be that made between property owners to defend their property and thus that

  Rousseau’s contract, as had been demonstrated by the events of the Revolution,

  could only lead to disorder and the disintegration of society.26 Given the persistence

  of these fears, Rousseau’s works virtually vanished from booksellers’ shelves and

  under Napoleon no edition of Du Contrat social was published.

  Nowhere was the hostility and distrust directed towards Rousseau’s ideas more

  evident than among those writers who, like Rousseau, believed that sovereignty was

  one and absolute but who saw the origin of that sovereignty as found not among the

  people but in God. Of these no one put the case more succinctly than Joseph de

  Maistre. Written in exile between 1794 and 1796, his Étude sur la souveraineté

  amounted to a systematic attempt to demolish the very foundations of Rousseau’s

  thought.27

  25 Pierre Landes, Principes du droit politique, mis en opposition avec ceux de J. J. Rousseau sur le

  Contrat social (1801).

  26 Gabriel-Jacques Dageville, De la propriété politique et civile (1813).

  27 Joseph de Maistre, ‘Étude sur la souveraineté’, in Œuvres complètes (Lyons, 1884), i. 309–554.

  A revised version of this text has been publ. under the title of De la Souveraineté du peuple: Un anti-

  contrat social (1992). See also Joseph de Maistre, ‘Examen d’un écrit de J.-J. Rousseau: Sur l’inégalité

  des conditions parmi les hommes’, in Œuvres complètes, vii. 507–66. In English see Maistre, Against

  Rousseau: ‘On the State of Nature’ and ‘On the Sovereignty of the People’ (Montreal and Kingston, 1996).

  116

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  There was no doubt in Maistre’s mind that Rousseau had been one of those

  responsible for both the outbr
eak and the horrors of the Revolution. Robespierre

  and Marat could not have committed their crimes had Rousseau and the other

  philosophes not undermined the bases of France’s pre-1789 Christian order. Rous-

  seau’s particular achievement (and again special mention was made of his seductive

  ‘eloquence’) was everywhere to have spread ‘contempt for authority and the spirit of

  insurrection’. Nor did Maistre have any doubts about Rousseau’s motives. Rous-

  seau, Maistre wrote, could never forgive God for not making him either a duke or a

  peer of the realm. His work was infused with ‘a certain plebeian anger directed

  against all forms of superiority’.28

  However, the core of the theocratic argument directed by Maistre against

  Rousseau lay in the assertion that man was by nature ‘sociable’ and therefore that

  it made no sense to speak of man existing prior to the existence of society. The

  latter, Maistre argued, was ‘the direct result of the will of the Creator who wanted

  that man should be what he always and everywhere had been’. It followed therefore

  that it was ‘a major error’ to conceive of society as a ‘choice’ based upon human

  consent, deliberation, or what Maistre described as ‘a primitive contract’. The

  confusion, he believed, derived in part from a misunderstanding about what was

  meant by the word ‘nature’ and in this context he was sure that such anomalous

  examples as the ‘American savage’ had little to teach us. It was absurd to seek the

  character of a being in its most undeveloped and untypical form. By the same token

  a people could not be said to pre-date the existence of sovereignty. A sovereign, in

  Maistre’s view, was necessary to make a people and therefore society and sovereign-

  ty both appeared at precisely the same time. ‘There was’, Maistre wrote, ‘a people,

  some kind of civilization and a sovereign as soon as men came into contact with

  each other.’

  The same logic also told Maistre that the very power which had decreed

  the existence of the social order and of sovereignty had also willed ‘modifications

  to sovereignty according to the different character of nations’. Nations, Maistre

  believed, quite definitely had different characters and from this were derived

  different forms of government that in each case were suited to the conditions.

  Thus, to ask in the abstract, as Maistre interpreted Rousseau to have done, what

  was the best possible form of government was to pose an insoluble question. ‘From

  these incontestable principles’, Maistre continued, ‘derives a conclusion which is no

  less so: that the social contract is a chimera. Because if there are as many govern-

  ments as there are different peoples, if the various forms of these governments are

  perforce prescribed by the power which has given to each nation its moral, physical,

  geographical and commercial qualities, then it is no longer possible to speak of a

  pact.’29 In short, each people had the type of government that suited it and none of

  them had been either chosen or self-consciously created.

  As such Rousseau, in addition to his many personal faults and the immense

  damage he had caused, was cast as ‘the mortal enemy of experience’.30 If history

  28 Maistre, ‘Étude sur la souveraineté’, 457.

  29 Ibid. 329.

  30 Ibid. 456.

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  117

  taught us (as Maistre believed it did) that monarchy was the most natural and

  universal form of government and that no pure form of democracy had ever existed,

  this had in no way prevented Rousseau from proclaiming that the ‘sole legitimate

  government’ was one he himself acknowledged was made for gods, was suitable

  only for small states, and for a people with a simplicity of morals.31 So also

  Rousseau judged democracy not by how it actually worked––‘Of all the monarchs’,

  Maistre wrote, ‘the hardest, the most despotic, the most intolerable, is the monarch

  people’32––but in terms of its theoretical perfection: hence the general will was

  by definition always right. The whole thing, from the idea of the social contract

  upwards, was nothing more than ‘un rêve de collège’.33

  Just as importantly there lay beneath this critique of Rousseau an alternative

  (and, Maistre believed, more compelling) account of the origin of society and of the

  nature of government. Joseph de Maistre’s ‘general thesis’ was that human beings

  were relatively powerless and therefore were incapable of any significant level of

  creative activity. They were also tainted by original sin and hence were not, as

  Rousseau believed, potentially perfect. From this Maistre found himself in agree-

  ment with Hobbes. Society, he wrote, ‘is in reality a state of war and here is to be

  found the necessity of government: given that man is evil he must be governed;

  wherever several people want the same thing there must be a superior power

  over everyone who can adjudicate and who can prevent them from fighting each

  other . . . a being who is both social and evil must be put under the yoke’.34

  Government was therefore not a vehicle for human liberation but was rather a

  necessary remedy for the consequences of original sin. To limit the power of the

  sovereign was to destroy it. If there was a difficulty, it was not that the sovereign

  should not exercise his will ‘invincibly’ but that he should be prevented from

  exercising it ‘unjustly’.35 This was to be avoided by ensuring that power derived

  from the papacy rather than from Rousseau’s ‘blind multitude’. How then was the

  legitimacy of a government to be assessed? For Maistre, all governments, given their

  divine source, were good governments but the best were those that provided the

  greatest sum of happiness to the greatest number of people over the longest period

  of time. Ultimately this could be measured not by the maxims of ‘human reason’

  but by the simple criterion of their longevity or duration.

  The overall import of Joseph de Maistre’s argument, as all his writings testify,

  was that the Revolution of 1789, directly inspired by Rousseau’s ‘disastrous

  principles’, had been a frontal assault upon what he chose to describe as ‘the eternal

  laws of nature’. By divorcing politics from religion and by mistakenly seeking to

  rebuild society upon the foundation of a man-made contract, chaos and disorder

  had inevitably followed.

  This was to be a refrain taken up by the ideologists of Catholic counter-

  revolution on a regular basis, none more so than Louis de Bonald. The writings

  of Bonald have neither the brilliance nor the trenchancy of those of Maistre, but

  31 Ibid. 482.

  32 Ibid. 502.

  33 Ibid. 489.

  34 Maistre, ‘Examen d’un écrit de J.-J. Rousseau’, 563.

  35 Maistre, ‘Étude sur la souveraineté’, 422.

  118

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  they again demonstrate that central to the counter-revolutionary defence of both

  throne and altar was the perceived need to refute Rousseau’s ideas, in this case by

  demonstrating how Rousseau’s own arguments could be used to subvert the very

  ideas for which he was taken to stand.

  Louis de Bonald
began his magisterial Théorie du pouvoir politique et religieux

  dans la société civile, démontrée par le raisonnement et par l’histoire,36 first published

  in 1796 and written in exile in Heidelberg, with a statement effectively denying the

  possibility of ever reconstructing society from first principles. ‘Man’, he proclaimed,

  ‘has always wanted to set himself up as the legislator of religious society and of civil

  society and to provide a constitution for each of them: I believe it possible to show

  that man can no more give a constitution to religious and political society than he

  can give weight to a body or dimensions to matter.’37 In short, the constitution of

  society was as natural and as immune to human action as the physical constitution

  of man himself. As such all forms of political voluntarism––of which Rousseau’s

  ideas were a prime example––were nothing less than deviations from what Bonald

  regarded as ‘the fundamental axioms of politics or of the science of society’. Indeed,

  he went so far as to suggest that Du Contrat social would have been better published

  under the lugubrious title of Méthode à l’usage des sociétés pour les éloigner de leur

  inclination naturelle, ou de la nature.

  What Bonald took these axioms to be is, to say the least, somewhat complicated.

  His argument, never quick in pace, moved forward by way of deduction and

  analogy, and was built around a series of tripartite divisions. As we saw in our

  earlier discussion of Bonald’s critique of the rights of man, the central claim was

  that a properly constituted society was one in which the elements of will, love, and

  force were in harmony and that certain relationships between men were ‘necessary’

  and must therefore be respected if the lives and property of a society’s members

  were to be preserved. At this point our focus must be on the first of Bonald’s

  categories: la volonté.

  Given that God had created man in his own image, how could society’s descent

  into turmoil be explained? Bonald’s reply was in accord with what he took to be the

  teachings of theology. These, he argued, saw ‘an unrestrained will, an uncontrolled

  love of self, immoral or criminal action as the source of all our disorders and as the

  origin of all our tribulations’.38 From this there had followed war between men and

 

‹ Prev