Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 30

by Jeremy Jennings

laws of nature the use of these objects and the agreeable sensations they produce

  are neither necessary or useful to life or health, nor necessary for the happiness of

  man’.109 If Pluquet was to devote more than 900 pages to developing this theme,

  repeatedly disparaging the ideas of Melon, Bernard Mandeville, David Hume, and

  the other ‘panegyrists of luxury’ in the process, Butel-Dumont was content with a

  more modest 400 pages designed to prove his argument that the most powerful

  102 Ibid. 276.

  103 Berry, Idea of Luxury, 137.

  104 Rousseau, ‘Last Reply’, 84.

  105 Shovlin, The Political Economy of Virtue: Luxury, Patriotism and the Origins of the French

  Revolution (Ithaca, NY, 2006).

  106 (1771), 2 vols.

  107 (1786), 2 vols.

  108 Butel-Dumont, Théorie du luxe, i. 121.

  109 Pluquet, Traité philosophique, i. 79.

  138

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  peoples and states were those that pursued luxury and that it was far better for states

  to reduce their expenditure than to impose ‘inept’ sumptuary laws.

  To these texts can be added Gabriel Sénac de Meilhan’s Considérations sur les

  richesses et le luxe,110 published on the eve of the Revolution and intended as a

  detailed refutation of the ideas put forward by Jacques Necker in his De l’Adminis-

  tration des finances de la France.111 Necker’s argument had been that it was a

  mistake to attribute luxury uniquely to changes in morals, the nature of govern-

  ment, or the acquisition of the New World. Luxury had its origin ‘in the natural

  course of things’, and specifically in ‘the advancement of science’ and, at best,

  government could temper the taste for it. In response, the greater part of the almost

  500 pages of Sénac de Meilhan’s text was devoted to the wholesale castigation of the

  political, social, and moral consequences of luxury. Great states preserved them-

  selves not because of, but despite, their luxury. ‘The immortal author of Téléma-

  que’, he wrote, ‘better understood and made known the problems arising from

  luxury than most of those who have explored the subject.’112

  Published only three years earlier, Antoine-Prosper Lottin’s Discours contre le

  luxe: Il corrompt les moeurs et détruit les Empires,113 began by announcing that

  combating luxury was ‘the most important and patriotic of subjects’, and then

  proceeded, in addition to pillorying ‘the eternal inconstancy of fashions’ and the

  reduction of society to a ‘perpetual ball’, to itemize how luxury destroyed the arts,

  the sciences, letters, industry, agriculture, public morals, and manners, before

  finally destroying empires themselves. Citing Montesquieu and the example of

  the decline of the Spanish Empire, Lottin contended that wealth did not guarantee

  the greatness of a state. Rather this lay in a people devoted to agriculture and the

  ‘useful arts’ and one imbued with a sense of virtue and courage. For these writers, in

  summary, the luxury debate was certainly no frivolous and ephemeral matter of

  taste and fashion but one of the most important and far-reaching questions of the

  age. At issue was nothing less than the fate of the absolute monarchy and the

  aristocratic order.

  It was, of course, a perpetual refrain in the writings of Rousseau that he alone

  had correctly observed the maladies of the age and that he alone was inspired by a

  love of humanity that was so strong that he was obliged to speak out. Everyone

  else, he believed, spoke only of ‘commerce and money’. As we have seen, this was

  not true and Rousseau was by no means alone in his condemnation of luxury.

  But, for once perhaps, Rousseau might be excused his rhetorical excesses, for it

  was indeed the case that writers in France, and elsewhere in Europe, were

  beginning to grapple with issues relating to trade, to finance, and to the market

  in a way that they had not done previously.114 Did the advent of the French

  110 (1787).

  111 Jacques Necker, De l’Administration des Finances de la France (1784). Vol. iii 57–75 is devoted

  to ‘Considérations sur le luxe et sur le progrès’.

  112 Sénac de Meilhan, Considérations sur les richesses, 174.

  113 (1783).

  114 See Henry C. Clark, Compass of Society: Commerce and Absolutism in Old-Regime France

  (Lanham, Md., 2007).

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  139

  Revolution and the fall of the Jacobins, we might therefore ask, elicit a change of

  attitude towards luxury in particular and towards commerce more generally?

  The Abbé Sieyès, principal ideologue and architect of the first stage of the Revolu-

  tion, had been fully aware that the distinctive feature of modern society was that it

  rested upon the division of labour, an insight which he applied to his understanding

  of both politics and economics.115 ‘If ’, he wrote, ‘every individual concerned himself

  with all the objects required for his own consumption, all individuals would be the

  same, and society would not depart from its state of infancy.’116 This, he contended,

  was no longer the case as men now thought about production rather than happiness.

  Where Sieyès therefore diverged from the physiocratic school was in his conclusion

  that there was no fundamental difference in productive potential between agriculture

  and manufacturing and thus that the exclusive focus of the physiocrats upon the

  former was misplaced. From this it followed that the privileged position accorded

  to the aristocracy through the ownership of land had to be removed and that anti-

  commercial prejudices, most obviously associated with extravagance of the court and

  the idleness of the nobility, had to be eradicated.

  Between the summer of 1789 and 1791 it was in this direction that France

  moved and, to that extent, the dominant tendency of the numerous reforms

  introduced in this period was broadly favourable to the further development of

  commerce and free trade. The ambition was not only to pay off France’s enormous

  public debt but also to secure the economic regeneration of the country. To that

  end, the feudal regime, with its restrictions upon the free movement of goods and

  persons, was abolished. Property rather than privilege was established as the basis of

  the new order and came to define a person’s status. The loi Le Chapelier of 1791

  made illegal all forms of restrictive trade corporations. But, as events were to show,

  this did not mean that concerns about the potentially damaging consequences of

  gross inequality and unbridled luxury or about the need to balance wealth and

  virtue had been abandoned. Amidst fears of a complete economic breakdown, the

  radical demands of the Parisian populace and of the enragés saw to that.

  As we already know, the advent of foreign war and internal revolt opened the door

  to a revival of the rhetoric of classical republicanism. With this came not only a return

  to the notion of the virtuous, frugal citizen-farmer of ancient Greece and Rome but

  also a victory for the claims of austerity and simplicity over those of ostentation and

  display. Moreover, in the face of food shortages and famine, the reintroduction of

  economic controls during 1793–4 amounted to
‘the economy of the Terror’.117

  National price ceilings were introduced for grain and flour, and to these were later

  115 See William H. Sewell Jr, A Rhetoric of Bourgeois Revolution: The Abbé Sieyes and What is the

  Third Estate? (Durham, NC, and London, 1994). Sewell writes: ‘Virtually all of Sieyes’s political

  thought had an important economic dimension. . . . Sieyes rejected not only Rousseau’s ideas

  about representation but the entire classical model of Greek and Roman political virtue on which

  it was based; he argued that material well-being, not political virtue, was the proper goal of a

  modern European State.’ Ibid. 67.

  116 Roberto Zapperi (ed.), Emmanuel-Joseph Sieyès: Écrits Politiques (1985), 63.

  117 Judith A. Miller, Mastering the Market: The State and the Grain Trade in Northern France,

  1700–1860 (Cambridge, 1999), 155.

  140

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  added price controls on all ‘goods of first necessity’ including such products as onions,

  soap, and paper. The General Maximum, introduced in September 1793, was,

  according to Colin Jones and Rebecca Spang, a ‘shibboleth of overt consumer

  renunciation’, providing ‘a snapshot of what Revolutionary Government regarded

  as prime necessities’.118 Envisaged was an alternative political economy based upon

  the satisfaction of needs rather than the production of luxuries. Its guiding spirit was

  to be fraternity rather than competition. Yet, by the same token, Jones and Spang

  argue, the General Maximun ‘was a shimmeringly indeterminate document’, reveal-

  ing that ‘[d]espite their best attempts to look and sound like Athenians and Romans,

  the French found it altogether more difficult than their classical forbears to draw a

  hard-and-fast line betweens the realms of necessity and luxury’. Denouncing luxury,

  in other words, was easy but defining it proved well-nigh impossible, and construct-

  ing an economic policy upon the basis of its eradication quickly showed itself to be

  both catastrophic and repressive.

  Thus, with the fall of the Jacobins, the General Maximum was abolished in

  December 1794 and an (often faltering) attempt was made to fashion something

  resembling a commercial republic more in tune with the demands and interests of

  the emerging industrial and mercantile elites. Yet it would be a mistake to believe

  that reflections on the nature of commercial activity were suddenly divested of

  moral and political concerns and thus that the question of luxury was now forgotten

  altogether.119 Indeed, as Martin Staum has argued, ‘concepts of public virtue

  remained indelibly linked to economic theory despite efforts to construct a value-

  neutral science based on private interest’.120

  This can be shown by referring to the ideas of the best-known French economist

  of the time: Jean-Baptiste Say. He has usually been regarded as a classical political

  economist who uncritically embraced and popularized the ideas of Adam Smith.

  Pierre Manent, for example, states that his Traité d’économie politique, first pub-

  lished in 1803, ‘constitutes the first great post-Smithian synthesis of economic

  liberalism’.121 A somewhat different story might be told.

  In 1800 Say published a curious text entitled Olbie.122 It was an account of a

  utopian city recently established upon ‘the ruins of an absolute monarchy’ and was

  intended to answer a question that had previously fascinated the writers of the

  Enlightenment and that had now become especially pertinent in light of the events

  of the previous decade: by what means could morality be established among a

  people? The text itself covered a variety of issues. For example, Say argued that

  118 Colin Jones and Rebecca Spang, ‘Sans-Culottes, Sans Café, Sans Tabac: Shifting Realms of

  Necessity and Luxury in Eighteenth-Century France’, in Maxine Berg and Helen Clifford (eds.),

  Consumers and Luxury: Consumer Culture in Europe, 1650–1850 (Manchester, 1999), 55.

  119 For a discussion of attempts to formulate a new republican political economy during Thermidor

  see James Livesey, Making Democracy in the French Revolution (Cambridge, Mass., 2001).

  120 See Martin S. Staum, Minerva’s Message: Stabilizing the French Revolution (Montreal and Kingston,

  1996), 192. See also Cheryl B. Welch, Liberty and Utility: The French Idéologues and the Transformation of

  Liberalism (New York, 1984), 70–96.

  121 Pierre Manent, Les Libéraux (1986), ii. 182.

  122 Jean-Baptiste Say, Olbie, ou Essai sur les moyens de réformer les Moeurs d’une Nation (1800).

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  141

  lotteries should be banned because they not only encouraged ‘avarice’ and ‘laziness’

  but also reinforced the belief that wealth depended upon chance rather than

  ‘industrie’.123 But, in essence, what Say described was a society characterized

  by ‘modest comfort’ rather than ‘the excesses of wealth and of indigence’. ‘The

  Olbiens’, Say wrote, ‘knew that the love of gain was a snare as dangerous as idleness.

  When this passion is very strong it becomes as exclusive as all the others; it

  extinguishes a mass of noble and disinterested sentiments which must be a part

  of the perfect human soul. It is thus that amongst certain peoples, or even amongst

  the habitants of certain towns, who are too much involved with commerce any idea,

  other than that of enriching oneself, is regarded as folly.’124 Accordingly, in Say’s

  account, the leaders of the Olbiens declared their opposition to displays of luxury,

  themselves adopting a ‘system of simplicity’ and forbidding their servants and

  soldiers from showing a ‘stupid deference for luxurious livery’. As the taste for

  luxury diminished, the Olbiens came to consume nothing beyond what was

  necessary for their utility and comfort. Happiness grew at the same time as morals

  were reformed.125

  In a note to this part of the text, Say clarified what he took to be the import of his

  argument. ‘In criticizing luxury’, he wrote, ‘I would not insist on the foolish

  pretension of returning man to a savage state where there are no utensils but fingers

  and teeth.’ The use of everything that was conducive to well-being in ‘rich and

  industrious nations’ should be allowed but, he continued, ‘I do not hesitate to

  pronounce that luxury is harmful to states, large and small, and that the country

  where there is least would be the richest and the most happy.’126 For that reason

  Say denied two of the main claims made in defence of luxury. The production of

  luxury did not provide jobs. There were, he countered, ‘never fewer unemployed

  hands than in regions where morals are simple and where, by consequence, few

  luxuries are produced’.127 Nor did luxury keep people alive. It was, Say argued,

  ‘only in a country where there is no luxury, or very little, that one sees everyone

  well-dressed, well-housed, well-nourished, and content’.128 It was in line with this

  argument that copious praise was heaped upon Lycurgus and the institutions of

  Sparta, whilst the fates of Carthage, Venice, and the Dutch Republic were cited as

  examples of the dire consequences which followed from the exclusive concentration

  upon the pursuit of wealth.

  Conven
tional wisdom has had it that the transition from Olbie to the Traité

  d’économie politique, published only three years later, represented a shift from a

  republican political economy to a laissez-faire liberalism based on the inviolability of

  private property and minimum state activity. This account has been contested by

  Richard Whatmore.129 While Whatmore has not wished to deny that innovations

  occurred in Say’s thinking––Say, for example, no longer believed that a republican

  123 Ibid. 34–5.

  124 Ibid. 29.

  125 Ibid. 42–4.

  126 Ibid. 123.

  127 Ibid. 125–6.

  128 Ibid. 126.

  129 See Richard Whatmore, Republicanism and the French Revolution: An Intellectual Biography of

  Jean-Baptiste Say (Oxford, 2000). See also Evelyn L. Forget, The Social Economics of Jean-Baptiste Say

  (London, 1999). Forget’s text includes a tr. of Say’s Olbie: see pp. 196–241.

  142

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  constitution was necessary for the inculcation of industrious manners nor did he

  retain his faith in legislation as a form of moral catechism––he nevertheless holds to

  the view that Say remained deeply concerned about the deleterious consequences

  of commerce as described by Adam Smith––not least what he took to be the

  impoverishment of the general population which would follow from the overzeal-

  ous introduction of the division of labour––and for all his emphasis upon the

  importance of productive capital as the source of a nation’s wealth he continued to

  disparage the unbridled pursuit of needless luxury.

  Specifically, we should note that in his lengthy Discours Préliminaire (an aston-

  ishing text which not only proclaimed the autonomy of economic science but also

  reviewed all previous economic doctrines) Say dismissed the maxim that ‘a state is

  enriched by luxury’, further contending that its application in the France of the

  1720s had led to bankruptcy. ‘Moderation and economy’, he commented, ‘became

  terms of ridicule.’130 This anti-luxury theme was then developed in the main body

  of the text. In line with his preference for frugality over excess and avarice, Say

  began by arguing that ‘[t]hose who say that money is only good to be spent and that

  products are only made to be consumed are badly mistaken if by this they mean

 

‹ Prev