Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 31
Revolution and the Republic Page 31

by Jeremy Jennings


  solely expenditure and consumption devoted to securing pleasure’.131 According to

  Say, luxury was a form of ostentation designed primarily to dazzle and impress

  others. Most importantly, it was a form of ‘unproductive consumption’, and as

  such directed resources away from ‘reproductive expenditure’. There was no merit

  in consuming everything one could, Say concluded, only in consuming what was

  reasonable.

  This was no minor matter, as it related to one of the central conclusions reached

  by Say. What later became known as Say’s Law stipulated that total demand in an

  economy could not exceed or fall below total supply in that economy. As he himself

  expressed it, ‘products are paid for by products’, and not by consumption. Into

  what kind of error, he asked therefore, ‘have fallen those who, seeing generally that

  production always equals consumption (because it is necessary that what is con-

  sumed should have been produced), have mistaken the effect for the cause, have

  conjectured that unproductive consumption alone brings about reproduction, that

  saving is directly contrary to public prosperity and that the most useful citizen is the

  one who spends the most.’132 If this truth was demonstrated by economic theory, it

  was likewise proven by history. Poverty, Say wrote, ‘always follows in the wake of

  luxury’. Do not be fooled, he counselled: a country in decline gives for a time ‘the

  image of opulence’, but it can never last and inevitably comes to an end. ‘Those

  people’, Say concluded, ‘who, through their great power or talents, seek to spread

  the taste for luxury, therefore, conspire against the happiness of nations.’133 For

  Say, the challenge was to find a means of reconciling the virtues of frugality and

  industry with commerce.

  That Say’s concerns about luxury were no isolated preoccupation can be easily

  shown by reference to the work of the most important of the political theorists

  130 Traité d’Economie Politique, in Collection des Principaux Economistes (Osnabrück, 1966), ix. 22–3.

  131 Ibid. 454.

  132 Ibid. 459.

  133 Ibid. 462.

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  143

  associated with the French Idéologues, Antoine-Louis-Claude Destutt de Tracy.

  Destutt de Tracy discussed luxury at length in two of his most important texts: his

  Commentaire sur l’Esprit des lois de Montesquieu and the Traité d’économie politique.134

  There were many intriguing elements to his argument. First, Destutt de Tracy

  provided an account of the origin of private property that was the very antithesis of

  that provided by Rousseau. The concepts yours and mine were never invented because

  they derived from the faculty of our will. Second, the will was defined in terms of

  the desire to maximize pleasure and to minimize pain, thus placing us under a duty to

  satisfy our needs ‘without any extraneous consideration’. Nevertheless Destutt de

  Tracy stood back from concluding that all consumption was inherently good, and

  he did so because the force of his argument was to be repeatedly directed against

  those he disparaged as les oisifs. ‘Consumption’, he wrote, ‘varies greatly according to

  the type of consumer as well as according to the nature of the things consumed’.135

  Accordingly, Destutt de Tracy’s fulminations against luxury bore a marked

  resemblance to the criticisms pronounced by Say. Luxury consisted essentially in

  ‘non-productive expenditures’. It was wrong to believe that the increase of luxury

  would enrich a nation. It did not favour commerce and encourage industry by

  quickening the circulation of money. Rather it changed the nature of that circulation

  and ‘made it less useful’. It created only ‘a fleeting pleasure’. Only if the alternative

  was to bury one’s money in the ground did it make sense to spend it in this way.

  ‘I believe myself entitled to conclude’, Destutt de Tracy wrote, ‘that, in economic

  terms, luxury is always an evil, a continuous cause of misery and weakness. Its true

  consequence is continuously to destroy, through the excessive consumption of some,

  the product of the work and industry of others.’136

  If Say’s argument stopped at this point, Destutt de Tracy pressed on, further

  contending that luxury was ‘an even greater evil’ from a moral point of view. It

  thrived on vanity and encouraged frivolity. In women it led to depravity and in men

  to avarice, and in both ‘to a lack of delicacy and probity’. And it produced ‘these sad

  effects, not only amongst those who enjoyed it, but also upon all those who admired

  it and who served to provide it’. Moreover, Destutt de Tracy found himself agreeing

  with Montesquieu’s original contention that luxury was appropriate to monarchies,

  adding that representative governments had no need to pander to ‘the natural

  tendency of man to give himself up to superfluous expenditure’. Did this mean,

  therefore, that governments, in whose interest it was to combat the advance of luxury,

  should resort to sumptuary laws? Not only, Destutt de Tracy replied, were they an

  abuse of authority and an attack on property, but they served no purpose

  when the spirit of vanity is not incessantly excited by all institutions; when the misery

  and ignorance of the lowest class are not so great as to encourage a stupid admiration

  for ostentation; when the opportunities to make fast and excessive fortunes are rare;

  when wealth is dispersed promptly through the equal division of inheritance; when

  134 Commentaire sur l’Esprit des lois de Montesquieu (1819) and Traité d’économie politique (1823),

  232–65.

  135 Ibid. 243.

  136 Destutt de Tracy, Commentaire, 96–7.

  144

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  finally everything leads us in another direction and towards real pleasures; in a word,

  when society is well-ordered.

  There, he concluded, were ‘the true means to combat luxury’.137

  It has been suggested that the concept of luxury ceased to be a central concept

  of economic analysis in the nineteenth century. In his otherwise admirable book,

  Philippe Perrot repeats the earlier claim of Serge Latouche that the concept did

  not figure in any of the four major dictionaries of political economy published in

  France during the nineteenth century.138 This is simply incorrect. There is an

  entry on luxury in Charles Ganilh’s Dictionnaire analytique d’économie politique of

  1826139 and in Sandelin’s Répertoire général d’économie politique ancienne et

  moderne of 1847.140 The same entry by Courcelle-Seneuil figured in both the

  Coquelin and Guillaumin dictionary of 1852 and the dictionary edited by Léon

  Say and Joseph Chailley of 1892. Moreover, only the entry penned by Ganilh

  disclosed an indifference to the social and psychological consequences of luxury.

  Sandelin concluded that luxury went hand in hand with the ‘depravity’ of morals,

  whilst Courcelle-Seneuil wrote that, ‘[w]ith regard to luxury, the teachings of

  political economy fully confirm those of morality’.141 It would be wrong there-

  fore to conclude that, as the French economy took its first significant steps

  towards industrialization, the moral critique of luxury dis
appeared altogether

  from view.

  Unsurprisingly, it was evident in much of the literature of Utopian socialism,

  where there was frequently displayed the hope that the workers would avoid a taste

  for opulence and ostentation and would limit their consumption to the satisfaction

  of ‘real’ needs. This was certainly the view of no less a figure than Pierre-Joseph

  Proudhon (who contended that the errors of socialism, be it ‘epicurean or ascetic’,

  derived from ‘a false conception of value’) as it was also that of Étienne Cabet. It

  was similarly to be found in the work of the most prominent legitimist political

  economist of the day, Alban de Villeneuve-Bargemont, most notably in his Econ-

  omie politique chrétienne, ou Recherches sur la Nature et les Causes du Paupérisme en

  France et en Europe et sur les Moyens de le soulager et de le prévenir.142 Other examples

  could be cited with relative ease.

  Of greater significance was the fact that the moral critique of luxury continued

  to be articulated by nineteenth-century republicans. We can see this quite clearly

  by returning our attention to Renouvier’s Manuel Républicain de l’Homme et du

  137 Destutt de Tracy, Commentaire, 112.

  138 See Perrot, Le Luxe, 38, and Serge Latouche, ‘Luxe et économie’, Revue de MAUSS, 16 (1985),

  71–2.

  139 (1826), 270–80.

  140 (The Hague, 1847), iv. 400–3.

  141 Charles Coquelin and Gilbert-Urbain Guillaumin, Dictionnaire de l’Économie Politique (Paris,

  1852), ii. 109–12, and Léon Say and Joseph Chailley, Nouveaux Dictionnaire de l’Économie Politique

  (Paris, 1892), ii. 191–4. Courcelle-Seneuil was a leading member of the so-called laissez-faire ultras or

  Paris group. The above-cited dictionaries also had entries on sumptuary law and discussions of luxury

  in relation to taxation.

  142 (1834). See also Villeneuve-Bargemont’s Histoire de l’Économie Politique ou Études Historiques,

  Philosophiques et Religieuse sur l’Économie Politique (1841), 2 vols.

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  145

  Citoyen.143 As we have seen, Renouvier sought to define the rights and liberties

  to be enjoyed by the citizen of the Republic. Towards the end of his text, and

  after having discussed the importance of the sentiment of fraternity, he turned

  his thoughts to the desirability or otherwise of luxury.144 You speak, Renouvier

  had his student interlocutor remark, of the ‘levelling of conditions’ but in such

  circumstances, he inquires, what would become of luxury and those who lived

  off its production? Was it not the case, he goes on to ask, that great wealth ‘spent

  ostentatiously serves at least to maintain workers’? Renouvier’s reply was to accept

  that at present the luxury of the rich provided a livelihood for the poor, but he then

  added that the poor would only die of hunger if the abolition of luxury was not

  accompanied by an acknowledgement of the right to work. Accompanied by such a

  reform, the worker would pass from the production of luxury goods to the

  production of something of use and of practical value. In addition, the ‘idler’

  who had previously paid for luxury would now turn his reduced resources to the

  production of something useful. Was luxury to be abolished altogether? There was,

  Renouvier contended (thereby echoing the very arguments deployed in its favour

  at the height of the 1789 Revolution),145 a place for ‘collective luxury’ in the shape

  of libraries, theatres, museums, and so on, all of which could be regarded as

  expressions of fraternity. There was even a place for luxury in the hands of private

  individuals; but such luxury was scandalous when so many people were denied the

  necessities of life. ‘In a Republic’, Renouvier wrote, ‘where the solidarity between

  men is recognized, I find it repugnant that luxury should spread before ease of

  circumstance has been attained and that the caprices of men should be satisfied

  whilst the needs of others cry out before Providence.’146 To this was then added two

  familiar refrains. He trembled, Renouvier declared, when he thought of those

  nations––in particular of England––whose wealth and prosperity consisted in the

  perfect comfort of a few thousand families whose actions condemned millions to live

  on bare necessities. Second, the greater majority of rich people were ‘enervated’ by

  luxury, ‘debased’ by dissolute living, and ‘consumed’ by boredom. However, this was

  ‘just punishment’ for those who had sought ‘the refinement’ of their lives through

  ‘the exploitation of their brothers’. It was only in ‘an age of corruption’, Renouvier

  declared, that such behaviour was not condemned. ‘Nothing is beautiful, nothing is

  noble’, he remarked, ‘that is not also useful.’

  Arguments against luxury, forcibly articulated in the eighteenth century,

  clearly retained much of their vitality and vigour amongst republican opinion.

  Not only this but, as Renouvier’s text testifies, they occupied an important

  position in the ferment of ideas that followed the fall of the July Monarchy and

  the establishment of the Second Republic. To extend this argument further we

  would need to look more closely at the study of political economy as it developed

  in the latter half of the nineteenth century. As fascinating and as tempting as this

  143 (1904).

  144 Ibid. 265–80.

  145 See Perrot, Le Luxe, 80.

  146 Renouvier, Manuel Républicain, 269.

  146

  Sovereignty, Social Contract, and Luxury

  would be, it is unfortunately not possible here. What can be established, however,

  is that the early decades of the Third Republic saw something akin to the

  democratization of consumption––exemplified above all by the opening of the

  first of Paris’s great department stores––and that, in this context, there were some

  who were prepared to reconceptualize luxury as the search for comfort and

  convenience rather than a taste for selfish indulgence and ostentation. In this

  less aristocratic and less harmful form, luxury could be defended as a stimulus to

  manufacturing and the arts and, as the economist Paul Leroy-Beaulieu argued in

  1894, as ‘one of the principal agents of human progress’.147 Nevertheless, it was

  not only conservative traditionalists who continued to worry about the dangers of

  material prosperity.148 Republicans too remained deeply troubled at the thought

  of a market where the rules of social justice did not apply and where conspicuous

  and unregulated consumption was considered to be the norm. The analysis of the

  condition of anomie provided by Émile Durkheim would be a case in point. If

  this anxiety did not necessarily entail an attempted revival and recall of the virtues

  of austerity and self-denial, it did encourage the search for a new moral principle

  capable of placing restraints upon the workings of a market society. The doctrine

  of solidarité, discussed at the end of the previous chapter, performed this function

  admirably.149 By way of conclusion, therefore, we might care to reflect upon the

  enduring quality of Rousseauian arguments against luxury (and by extension,

  of republican hostility to the commercial model embodied by England). That this
>
  was so tells us much about the difficulties faced by those who sought to see France

  embrace the values and practices of a commercial society.

  147 ‘Le Luxe: La fonction de la richesse’, Revue des Deux Mondes, 126 (1894), 72–100, 547–73. In

  its attempt to summarize all the arguments for and against luxury, the article by Leroy-Beaulieu recalls

  the earlier essay of Saint-Lambert.

  148 See Victoria E. Thompson, The Virtuous Marketplace: Women and Men, Money and Politics in

  Paris, 1830–1870 (Baltimore, Md., 2000).

  149 See Rosalind H. Williams, Dream Worlds: Mass Consumption in Late Nineteenth-Century France

  (Berkeley and Los Angeles, Calif., 1982).

  4

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  I

  ‘Voltaire discovered England; Voltaire discovered commerce’: thus writes

  Daniel Roche at the beginning of his analysis of what he terms ‘the kingdom

  of exchange’.1 What this discovery meant for Voltaire was enthusiastically

  expressed in his Lettres philosophiques, published in 1734.2 ‘Commerce’,

  Voltaire wrote, ‘which has enriched the citizens of England, has contributed

  to making them free, and this liberty has extended commerce in its turn’.3

  Not only this but ‘an Englishman, being a free man, goes to heaven by the

  route that he chooses’.4 This was evidenced by the London Stock Exchange.

  ‘There’, he wrote, ‘the Jew, the Mohammedan and the Christian deal with

  each other as if they were of the same religion, and give the name of infidel only

  to those who go bankrupt; the Presbyterian trusts the Anabaptist, and the

  Anglican accepts the promise of the Quaker. Upon departing from these

  peaceful and free exchanges, some go to the synagogue whilst others go for

  a drink.’5 Trade and religious toleration went hand in hand, each mutually

  strengthening the other.

  It was this combination, Voltaire concluded, which had allowed the English to

  become ‘masters of the seas’, but he also wanted us to understand that it was the

  commercial spirit which more broadly explained the character of English society

  and government. If in ancient Rome, Voltaire argued, the consequence of civil war

  had been slavery, in England it was liberty, and this was so because

 

‹ Prev