Revolution and the Republic

Home > Other > Revolution and the Republic > Page 32
Revolution and the Republic Page 32

by Jeremy Jennings


  the English nation is the only one on earth which has succeeded in controlling the power

  of kings by resisting them and which, by dint of continuous effort, finally established

  a form of sound government where the prince, possessing the power necessary to do

  good, has his hands tied when it is a question of doing bad, where the nobility have

  authority without being insolent and without having vassals, where the people participate

  in government without producing confusion.6

  This led Voltaire to reflect upon the comparative merits and utility of the ‘pow-

  dered’ aristocrat ‘who knows precisely at what time the king rises and at what hour

  he goes to bed’ and the trader who ‘enriches his country, sends orders to the island

  1 Daniel Roche, France in the Enlightenment (Cambridge, Mass., 1998), 140.

  2 Voltaire, Lettres philosophiques (1986).

  3 Ibid. 75.

  4 Ibid. 54.

  5 Ibid. 60–1.

  6 Ibid. 66.

  148

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  of Surate and to Cairo from his office, and contributes to the happiness of the

  world’.7 Accordingly, when Voltaire discussed the great figures of English life, he

  focused upon Francis Bacon, John Locke, Isaac Newton, and William Shakespeare,

  reflecting at the same time upon the number of aristocrats in England who were

  well-known writers and who took pride from ‘their works rather than their name’.

  Voltaire offered neither a systematic treatise on England nor on the nature of

  commerce but his brief sketches nevertheless gave prominence to a set of themes

  which were to grow in importance as the eighteenth century developed. In particular,

  by associating commerce with liberty and also with England he not only provided, for

  those who wished to hear it, a telling critique of French society and manners––

  deemed still to be in the grip of religious fanaticism and arbitrary power––but also the

  contours of an alternative vision or model by the side of which France could be both

  judged and reformed.

  The starting point of this debate was an interpretation of the English Revolution

  of 1688. Pierre Jurieu and Bossuet had clashed swords on this, the former strongly

  supporting the cause of William of Orange and the benefits that his reign was

  bringing to the English people.8 Here the Glorious Revolution was accredited with

  two principal achievements. First was the recognition that a particular set of

  institutional arrangements was conducive––indeed indispensable––for the preser-

  vation of political liberty. This set of arrangements was the separation and balance

  of powers. Second was religious toleration. The importance of the last went far

  beyond that of a purely religious controversy. Implicit in the recognition of

  religious diversity was the acceptance that the extent of government action ought

  to be limited, that it should be defined by law, and, consequently, that it did not

  extend over the entire range of an individual’s activities. The corollary was that

  there were a whole range of duties and actions which were best left either to

  individuals or to groups of individuals. Of these activities, one of the most

  important was trade.

  Both Anglophilia and Anglophobia flourished in eighteenth-century France and

  continued to do so until well into the nineteenth century.9 Typical of the spirit and

  tone of the latter was Joseph Fiévée’s, Lettres sur l’Angleterre et Réflexions sur la

  philosophie du XVIIIe siècle, published in 1802, the year Britain and France signed

  the Treaty of Amiens. ‘In England’, he began, ‘the words peace and commerce are what

  the words peace and glory are in France.’10 In England everything––dress, manners, the

  arts––was cheap and vulgar and there was little evidence of good taste. ‘The English’,

  Fiévée remarked, ‘are the least civilized nation in Europe’, and this, he avowed,

  7 Voltaire, Lettres philosophiques (1986), 76.

  8 Pierre Jurieu, ‘Justification du Prince d’Orange et de la Nation Anglaise’, Lettres pastorales XVI–

  XVII–XVIII (Caen, 1991), 409–32.

  9 See Theodore Zeldin, ‘English Ideals in French Politics during the Nineteenth Century’,

  Historical Journal, 1 (1959), 40–58; Frances Acomb, Anglophobia in France 1763–89 (New York,

  1980); and Josephine Grieder, Anglomania in France, 1740–1789: Fact, Fiction and Political Discourse

  (Geneva, 1985).

  10 Fiévée, Lettres sur l’Angleterre (1802), 48.

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  149

  followed from ‘the great regard which they have for money’.11 It also helped to

  explain why the English male did not enjoy the company of women. Similarly, Fiévée

  set little store by England’s much-vaunted religious toleration. If England was

  a country where ‘all religious extravagances are permitted’, to be a Catholic was ‘to

  be much less than a man’. As for the supposed liberty which flowed from the

  English system of government, Fiévée saw only corruption and oppression.

  ‘In England’, he commented, ‘there are three types of election; those that you buy,

  those that you give away, and those that are contested by the use of reputation and

  money.’12 Worse still was the ‘agitation of the rabble’.

  Why did it matter that the beneficial consequences of England’s commerce and

  constitutional settlement should be contested? First, it was Fiévée’s view that the

  philosophes, inspired by a hatred of their own country, had embraced ‘anglomania’,

  and that this had been one of the causes of the Revolution of 1789. Next, he believed

  that it was simply mistaken for one country to try to imitate another, and that this

  was especially so in the case of England and France where their guiding ethos––

  commerce for one, and glory for the other––were so diametrically opposed. ‘The

  English’, Fiévée concluded, ‘like all peoples, are what their position, the centuries,

  and events have decided that they should be. To resemble them would require two

  impossible things: first, to cease to be ourselves, then to become them.’13

  There was some justification in Fiévée’s complaints. Throughout the eighteenth

  century the philosophes frequently cited England, its institutions, and its history,

  to illustrate what, in their opinion, were defects in France and had done so to a

  receptive public. To that extent, the Anglophiles came to be seen as dangerous

  subversives intent on destroying the fabric of French society and culture. There

  was, then, a serious political point to questioning whether England quite lived up

  to the glowing picture of it being purveyed, possibly out of ignorance or malice, by

  its admirers. Clearly, much of this discussion––as Fiévée himself recognized––was

  grounded in the long-standing economic, dynastic, and military rivalry which

  existed between the two countries but, that aside, there was some merit in posing

  the question of whether one country could usefully copy another. This was to be a

  question repeatedly asked, even by England’s most enthusiastic admirers.

  Such was the general awareness of France’s decline relative to Britain that a

  wholesale rejection of the English example was comparatively rare. Once the

 
animosity engendered by the Seven Years War had subsided there was a resurgence

  of Anglophilia in the highest government circles, most notably in the policies

  advocated by Jacques Necker, recalled to ministerial office in 1788.14 As we have

  seen, defenders of moderate reform in 1789 came to see the English model of

  limited monarchy––made known to them principally through Jean Delolme’s

  11 Ibid. 193.

  12 Ibid. 128.

  13 Ibid. 232.

  14 See Jacques Necker, Du pouvoir exécutif dans les grands États (1802). Necker returned to these

  questions in Dernières vues de politique et de finance, offertes à la Nation Française (1802), 266–363,

  specifically exploring the comparison between ‘une Monarchie héréditaire et tempérée’, based upon the

  English ‘model’, and a ‘République une et indivisible’.

  150

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  La Constitution de l’Angleterre of 1771––as a means of providing good government,

  extending the liberties of individuals, and of preserving public order. Their short-

  lived political supremacy handed power back to the Anglophobes, reaching its

  zenith with the ascent of the Jacobins.

  Given their predilection to equate wealth with corruption, there was little to

  indicate that Robespierre and his colleagues would view England with anything

  but profound contempt or as being incapable of displaying the qualities required

  of republican virtue.15 Indeed, in Jacobin discourse England was frequently cast as

  the new Carthage, as a maritime and trading power lacking the capacity for virtue

  displayed by both classical Rome and contemporary France.16 This sentiment only

  intensified as Robespierre’s obsession with internal opposition was extended to

  include ‘the English faction’. France, he believed, was ‘infested with the agents of

  England’. ‘I hate the English as a people’, Robespierre declared, and did so for the

  simple reason that there was nothing more despicable than a nation of slaves

  prepared to live under the rule of tyrants and despots.17 England was no more

  than a ‘contemptible meteor’ which would disappear before the ‘republican star’.

  France, and not an ‘odious’ and ‘proud’ England, was ‘the last hope of the friends of

  humanity’.

  The debate over England continued after the Restoration of the monarchy in

  1814. On both sides of the argument there was agreement on one thing at least:

  England was the country of aristocracy, and thus of inequality. For example, in 1825

  Auguste de Staël, son of Germaine de Staël, published his Lettres sur l’Angleterre and

  there listed the following aristocratic features of English life: ‘The unequal division of

  property, primogeniture, an hereditary peerage, electoral influence, the distinction of

  ranks, honorific prerogatives, bodies possessing privileges’.18 For his part, Benjamin

  Constant described England as ‘a vast, opulent and vigorous aristocracy’.

  The precise character of this aristocracy also received much attention, but the

  view of England’s admirers was that its aristocracy was open to all talents and that

  their privileges were acknowledged by the English people as being indispensable to

  the preservation of English liberty. ‘There has never existed in the world’, wrote

  Charles de Montalembert, ‘a government where the access to power, influence and

  prestige has been as easy and as assured as in England’. Similarly, for Montalembert

  England’s inheritance laws were at once ‘the consequence and guarantee’ of its

  liberty.19 For such enthusiasts, the challenge for France was that of recreating a new

  aristocracy upon similar lines and of appropriating the principal advantages of the

  English system.

  For England’s critics, by contrast, the influence of its aristocracy was something

  to be regretted and the political, economic, and social inequalities flowing from it

  15 See Sophie Wahnich, L’Impossible Citoyen: L’Étranger dans le discours de la Révolution française

  (1997), 243–346.

  16 See Norman Hampson, The Perfidy of Albion: French Perceptions of England during the French

  Revolution (Houndmills, 1998).

  17 Œuvres de Maximilien Robespierre, x. Discours 27 juillet 1793–27 juillet 1794 (1967), 348–50.

  18 Auguste de Staël-Holstein, Lettres sur l’Angleterre (1825), 151–2.

  19 Charles de Montalembert, De l’Avenir politique de l’Angleterre (1857).

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  151

  were at once a crime and a source of weakness. Moreover, with the advent of

  Britain’s industrial revolution, the theme of aristocracy was transposed to this new

  setting. In Flora Tristan’s Promenades de Londres, first published in 1842, we read, for

  example, that ‘the greater proportion of workers lack clothing, a bed, furniture, a fire,

  and sufficient food’.20 The cause of this parlous condition was the English aristocracy.

  ‘Do you understand’, she asked her readers, ‘how a handful of aristocrats, lords,

  baronets, bishops, landed proprietors, and all manner of sinecurists, how this handful

  of privileged people can coerce, torture and starve a nation of twenty six million

  people?’21 In England, she continued, the people suffered under the yoke of the

  ‘pitiless egoism, revolting hypocrisy, and monstrous excess of this English oligarchy’.

  It was ‘the most barbarous and the most frightful of all tyrannies’.22 Tristan was by no

  means alone in travelling across the Channel in order to discover the secrets of

  the new industrial system that was there emerging. Equally representative of this

  strand of thought was Eugène Buret’s De la misère des classes laborieuses en Angleterre

  et en France.23 What Buret saw was a country that combined extreme opulence with

  profound poverty, ‘the liberty of the rich and the strong’ by the side of ‘the servitude

  of the poor and the weak’.24 ‘France’, he wrote, ‘is poor, but England is miserable.’

  France was wrong to envy England’s wealth and power, as it was on a road that would

  lead either to ‘inevitable ruin or to the most radical and perhaps most terrible of

  revolutions’.25 In general the diagnosis was a far from positive one. For many of

  the visitors to Britain’s new industrial cities the arrival of the machine age was

  synonymous with poverty, criminality, and prostitution.

  The surprise is that versions of these very criticisms were to be found in the writings

  of authors who might otherwise have been imagined to be broadly favourable to the

  English model. For example, Jean-Baptiste Say, author of De l’Angleterre et les Anglais

  of 1816, was far from convinced of the supposed merits of English commercial power

  or that this power would endure. As a consequence of the excessive taxation and

  borrowing required to defeat Napoleon Bonaparte, he contended, the cost of British

  industrial and agricultural products was exorbitant, such that even a decent hard-

  working family was frequently obliged to resort to public charity. To survive, all but

  the very rich were condemned to arduous toil and competition with their fellows. In

  such a situation, the rich thought only of getting richer, and so much so that Say feared

  that the country of Bacon, Newton, and Locke was taking rapid steps towa
rds

  barbarism. ‘The greatest disgrace in France’, Say wrote, ‘is to lack courage; in England

  it is to lack guineas.’26 Corrupted by its politicians and debased by its material and

  social inequality, England was no model for France.27

  20 Flora Tristan, Promenades dans Londres, ou L’aristocratie et les prolétaires anglais (1978), 112.

  21 Ibid. 47.

  22 Ibid. 312.

  23 Eugène Buret, De la misère des classes laborieuses en Angleterre et en France (1840), i, p. ii.

  24 Ibid. 19.

  25 Ibid. ii. 475.

  26 Say, De l’Angleterre (1816), 22.

  27 See Jean-Paul Bertaud, Alan Forrest, and Annie Jourdan, Napoléon, le monde et les Anglais (2004),

  90–101.

  152

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  But this increasingly became a difficult position to sustain. In the guise of the

  new doctrine of ‘industrialism’, liberal economists in France became strong advo-

  cates of the wealth-creating power of commerce.28 The key to wealth, they

  perceived, was through capital accumulation and in this a central role was allotted

  to the entrepreneur, to the market, and to free trade. No economy gave better proof

  of this than that of England. Moreover, given that France had again been subject to

  military defeat at the hands of England, that under the Empire she had once more

  found herself in the grip of arbitrary power, and that in 1815, 1830, and 1848

  France was required to find another set of governmental institutions, it was not to

  be unexpected that a good number of French writers should for a further time cast

  an envious and inquiring eye towards the other side of the Channel.

  I I

  To properly understand this disposition we should return to the eighteenth century

  and in particular to Montesquieu. He was not the first to use the term ‘despotism’

  in France.29 It had been widely used by aristocratic as well as Protestant opponents

  of Louis XIV. As a system of government rather than as a description of a form of

  personal rule it had been given wide currency by Pierre Bayle and others such as

  Fénelon and Boulainvilliers, to the point that even before Montesquieu was to place

  the concept of despotism at the heart of De l’Esprit des lois there existed a broad

  understanding of despotism as a form of arbitrary rule by a single sovereign power

 

‹ Prev