Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 33

by Jeremy Jennings


  limited neither by law nor by secondary powers. Despotism was further associated

  with other features of the Sun King’s reign: the centralization of power, religious

  intolerance, the pursuit of military glory, and financial corruption and mismanage-

  ment. To this Montesquieu was to add the description of despotism as rule by fear.

  Montesquieu offered three criteria by which political regimes could be defined:

  who held sovereign power, by what method sovereign power was exercised, and by

  what principle the regime was set in motion. He accordingly stipulated that there

  were three types of government: republican, monarchical, and despotic; and then

  defined the principle determining the working of each in the following way: ‘the

  nature of republican government is that the people as a body, or certain families,

  have the sovereign power; the nature of monarchical government is that the prince

  has the sovereign power, but that he exercises it according to established laws; the

  nature of despotic government is that one alone governs according to his wills and

  caprices’.30 The despot, in short, had no rules by which he was bound and he was

  strong because he gloried in scorning life, being free to take life away as he chose.

  Honour, therefore, was unknown in despotic states, leaving the despot only with

  28 Martin S. Staum, ‘French Lecturers in Political Economy, 1815–1848: Varieties of Liberalism’,

  History of Political Economy, 30 (1998), 95–120.

  29 See Sharon Krause, ‘Despotism in the Spirit of the Laws’, in David D Carrithers, Michael

  A. Mosher, and Paul A. Rahe (eds.), Montesquieu’s Science of Politics: Essays on the Spirit of the Laws

  (Lanham, Md., 2001), 231–72.

  30 The Spirit of the Laws (1989), 21.

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  153

  rule by fear. It was thus in the nature of despotic government that it required

  ‘extreme obedience’ and that the people were to be made ‘timid’ and ‘ignorant’.

  Politics likewise became devoid of substance. There was little public business,

  Montesquieu wrote, and government was reduced to ‘the preservation of the

  prince, or rather the preservation of the palace in which he is enclosed’. Men

  acted only with the comforts of life in view and expected to be rewarded for

  everything they did. As Montesquieu observed, ‘the worst Roman Emperors were

  those who gave the most’.31 However, the goal of despotic government, for all its

  reliance upon caprice and fear, was nothing more than order and tranquillity, the

  reducing of all citizens to a servitude where all showed ‘passive obedience’ and

  where each ‘blindly submits to the absolute will of the sovereign’. Everyone was

  equal, but this was because everyone counted for nothing and lived isolated from

  one another. What is more, the despot’s subjects lived in a state of destitution and

  they did so because the laws of commerce scarcely applied. Embezzlement, Mon-

  tesquieu recounted, was the normal condition under despotic rule.

  Montesquieu summarized this deplorable state of human existence in one

  short observation. ‘When the savages of Louisiana want fruit’, he wrote, ‘they cut

  down the tree and gather the fruit. There you have despotic government.’32 What

  he meant by this was that despotic government was government determined

  by instinctive and irrational appetites and actions. It destroyed the very thing

  sustaining its life. It was government that lacked the all-important ingredient of

  moderation and where power was not counter-balanced. In institutional terms it

  was a situation where the instruments of government were not divided up between

  the executive, legislative, and judicial branches. Among the Turks, Montesquieu

  wrote, ‘where the three powers are united in the person of the sultan, an atrocious

  despotism reigns’.33

  From this Montesquieu concluded that ‘political liberty is found only in

  moderate governments’.34 This in turn begged the question of what was meant

  by political liberty. For Montesquieu it was defined in terms of the absence of

  fear and, its corollary, an individual’s sense of personal security guaranteed by law.

  ‘[I]n a society where there are laws’, Montesquieu wrote, ‘liberty can consist

  only in having the power to do what one should want to do and in no way being

  constrained to do what one should not want to do.’ ‘Liberty’, he continued,

  ‘is the right to do everything that the laws permit.’35 The worst situation was

  one where the enjoyment of liberty depended upon the caprice of the legislator

  or upon the arbitrary power of the despot. Unpromisingly, Montesquieu

  believed that there was something natural about despotism––hence his view

  that it arose more often in warm climates––and that there was no guarantee that

  liberty and moderation would ultimately prevail.

  As Montesquieu famously contended, there was only one nation ‘whose

  political constitution has political liberty for its direct purpose’ and that nation

  was England.36 Much has been written about Montesquieu’s discussion of the

  31 Ibid. 68.

  32 Ibid. 59.

  33 Ibid. 157.

  34 Ibid. 155.

  35 Ibid.

  36 Ibid. 156.

  154

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  English constitution, and in particular on the subject of whether he was providing

  a description of how the English constitution actually worked or an ideal type of

  the ‘constitution of liberty’ with England as its source.37 Montesquieu himself

  appeared to suggest that it did not matter whether the English actually enjoyed

  the liberty he was describing: it was sufficient ‘to say that it is established by their

  laws’. Whatever the truth of the matter, Montesquieu outlined what he took to

  be the tripartite division of the executive, legislative, and judicial branches of

  government and saw England as a system of mixed government in which power

  was shared between monarch, Lords, and Commons. Furthermore he recognized

  that such a system of division and balance was indispensable for the preservation

  of liberty. Thus, the essence of good government was a situation where power

  counter-balanced itself and could not be abused.

  More difficult to assess was what Montesquieu thought of the French monarchy.

  Where Montesquieu cited a regime as an example of arbitrary despotism his

  standard instance was that of the Ottoman Empire. Monarchy itself, along with

  republics, was one of the two types of political regime which he identified as having

  potentially beneficial consequences. Monarchies, he wrote, do not have ‘liberty for

  their direct purpose . . . they aim only for the glory of the citizens, the state, and the

  prince. But this glory results in a spirit of liberty that can, in these states, produce

  equally great things and can perhaps contribute as much to happiness as to liberty

  itself.’38 Nor did he believe anything other than that executive power should be in

  the hands of a monarch. However, monarchies could degenerate into despotism.

  They did so not only when the three branches of government fell into the same

  hands but also when subordinate and intermediate institutions were weakened

  or, in the
worst case, eradicated. As a member of the ‘nobility of the robe’ and of

  the provincial parlement of Bordeaux, Montesquieu’s personal sympathies were

  clear enough. Indeed, as a means of restraining royal power, he was not averse to

  defending the practice of the buying of public offices.

  One possible antidote to the slide towards despotism was religion, but this,

  Montesquieu recognized, could be used to induce passivity. Another was com-

  merce. By commerce, Montesquieu here had in mind not merely the exchange of

  goods but also the creation of new patterns of social intercourse. ‘It is an almost

  general rule’, Montesquieu wrote, ‘that everywhere there are gentle mores, there is

  commerce and that everywhere there is commerce, there are gentle mores’.39 Our

  moral practices and habits, in other words, become less ‘ferocious’ as a result of our

  contacts with other people and through our greater familiarity with their ways. In

  particular, ‘the natural effect’ of commerce is to lead to peace: ‘two nations that

  trade with each other become reciprocally dependent; if one has an interest in

  buying, the other has an interest in selling, and all unions are founded on mutual

  37 See e.g. R. Shackleton, Montesquieu: A Critical Biography (Oxford, 1961), 284–301; M. F. T. H.

  Fletcher, Montesquieu and English Politics (1750–1800) (Philadelphia, 1989), 107–51; M. J. C. Vile,

  Constitutionalism and the Separation of Powers (Oxford, 1967), 76–97; Melvin Richter, The Political

  Theory of Montesquieu (Cambridge, 1977), 84–97; and Paul Rahe, Montesquieu and the Logic of Liberty

  (2009).

  38 Spirit of the Laws, 166.

  39 Ibid. 338.

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  155

  needs’.40 Additionally, there existed a relationship between forms of government

  and commerce. As a general rule, Montesquieu wrote, ‘in a nation that is in

  servitude, one works more to preserve than to acquire; in a free nation, one

  works more to acquire than to preserve’.41 It was here that England again figured

  positively in Montesquieu’s account. Other countries had put political interests

  before commercial interests. In England, it was always the reverse. The English

  were ‘the people in the world who have best known how to take advantage of each

  of these three great things at the same time: religion, commerce, and liberty’.42

  This did not mean that France should rush unreservedly towards an imitation of

  English murs and institutions. One of the most striking conclusions of De l’Esprit

  des lois was an awareness of the limitations attached to the activity of politics. Laws,

  Montesquieu believed, along with climate, religion, morals, manners, and examples

  drawn from the past, were the factors which ‘governed men’ and together they

  formed ‘a general spirit’. The wise legislator was one who followed ‘the spirit of the

  nation’. To that extent, government should be a reflection of society rather than

  a vehicle for securing the transformation of society. Faced therefore with the

  centuries-long deviation of royal power towards despotism, Montesquieu was left

  with little alternative but to conjure up the possibility of a return to a pre-feudal and

  ‘gothic’ past where the monarch made no decisions without first consulting the

  representatives of the people.

  De l‘Esprit des lois was not a book from which one could easily draw hard and fast

  conclusions. Nevertheless, despite the preoccupation with locating all societies

  within their diverse natural and historical conditions, there was no ambiguity in

  Montesquieu’s condemnation of despotism in whatever form it took. Happy then,

  in Montesquieu’s eyes, were all those fortunate enough to experience what was

  delightfully termed ‘la douceur du gouvernement’. The best of situations seemed

  indubitably to be that where ‘moderate’ government was combined with the

  enjoyment of a ‘moderate’ liberty. This led to the conclusion that liberty was

  most readily preserved through the contrived balance of both governmental in-

  stitutions and competing social interests.

  But would this precarious equilibrium be overturned by the activity of com-

  merce, the dynamic effects of which Montesquieu had identified so accurately?43

  Much has been made of Montesquieu’s ‘esprit conservateur’. Within his writings

  the maintenance of stability attained almost as much importance as the dispersal of

  political power. For this reason he opposed the emergence of a ‘noblesse comm-

  merçante’ and believed that governments should regulate who could take part in

  commercial activities. Ultimately, however, such restrictions upon commercial

  activity proved untenable and with the collapse of the feudal order there occurred

  not only a reconfiguration of what Montesquieu would have regarded as the general

  spirit of society but also one potentially undermining the mainsprings of liberty.

  Once this had been perceived to have occurred, those who came increasingly to

  40 Ibid.

  41 Ibid. 341.

  42 Ibid. 343.

  43 Roger Boesche, ‘Fearing Monarchs and Merchants: Montesquieu’s Two Theories of Despotism’,

  Western Political Quarterly, 43 (1990), 741–61.

  156

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  regard themselves as liberals had the task of forging a new doctrine which would

  graft the fundamental insights of Montesquieu concerning the nature of liberty

  and its preservation onto a society dominated by new social classes, new political

  institutions, as well as by the pursuit of affluence. This was to prove to be no easy

  task.

  During the Revolution Montesquieu was read consistently (and correctly) as a

  fierce critic of all forms of despotism. It was also the case that the tripartite division

  of governmental functions outlined by Montesquieu acted as a consistent point of

  reference in the constitutional debates that took place after 1789. Nearly everyone

  agreed that despotism could only be avoided if these three functions were not

  placed in the hands of either a single individual or institution and it was this that

  explained the preoccupation with ensuring that the legislative and executive func-

  tions in particular should remain separate. Not surprisingly, it was the monarchiens

  who were to prove to be the most enthusiastic and faithful advocates of Montes-

  quieu’s constitutional recommendations. As the Revolution progressed, and as

  attention turned away from the goal of constructing a balanced constitution

  towards that of using the State as a moral agent, Montesquieu continued to fade

  from view. Most importantly, the idea figuring at the very heart of Montesquieu’s

  thought––‘the need for power to check power through the arrangements of

  things’––was consistently ignored. Alongside demands for unity of political action,

  the moderation associated with a system of balances and manufactured equilibrium

  had little charm or attraction.

  It was precisely this sentiment that underscored Napoleon Bonaparte’s seizure of

  power on the 18 Brumaire.44 What, more broadly, might be said of the character

  and significance of this new regime? At the heart of what became Bonapartist

  ideology was the aspiration to bring t
he Revolution to a close while preserving what

  were taken to be its achievements.45 This was secured by a series of concessions

  towards those who had been most adversely affected by the Revolution. If this

  largely concerned measures to assuage the Catholic Church and the aristocracy (for

  example, allowing Christians to worship on Sundays and ending the commemora-

  tion of the execution of Louis XVI) it also meant that slavery, having been abolished

  in 1794, was re-established in French colonies in 1802. By the same token, there

  was to be no going back upon the abolition of the privileges associated with the

  ancien régime. Recognizing civil equality, the Revolution was to be stabilized upon a

  conservative basis. What followed were a series of wide-ranging administrative,

  financial, judicial, and educational reforms, many of which still operate in con-

  temporary France. To take but two examples: the legal code was systematically

  overhauled between 1804 and1810, whilst the educational system was reformed

  with a view to providing a new elite equipped to serve the State. So too the préfet,

  symbol of the State’s presence and authority beyond the capital, was brought into

  44 See Patrice Gueniffey, Le Dix-Huit Brumaire (2008).

  45 The term ‘Bonapartism’ was first used in 1816: see Melvin Richter, ‘Towards a Concept of

  Political Illegitimacy: Bonapartist Dictatorship and Democratic Legitimacy’, Political Theory, 10

  (1982), 185–214.

  Commerce, Usurpation, and Democracy

  157

  existence. This was accompanied by a further reinforcement of administrative

  centralization.46

  It was this feature of the Empire that was to become one of the abiding

  obsessions of its later liberal critics. Spreading its tentacles outwards from the

  Ministry of the Interior in Paris, the State’s administrative apparatus came to be

  seen as an all-powerful mechanism of control, intruding into every aspect of local

  life. The reality, according to many of those charged with exercising these func-

  tions, was less interventionist and far more attuned to the needs of local commu-

  nities, but the prefectoral system was seen to be an integral part of what was an

  authoritarian and centralized regime.

  This was not to be the only feature of Napoleon’s rule that was to meet with

  criticism. No sooner had power been seized than attempts to stifle opposition were

 

‹ Prev