Book Read Free

Revolution and the Republic

Page 55

by Jeremy Jennings


  of the nation, men united in the desire to realize the wishes of philosophy.

  Convinced of its rights, it had prevailed heroically over its enemies ‘by the simple

  expression of its will’. In this lay the first and most noble act of the Revolution.

  Never, Thiers contended, ‘had a nation acted with more justice or more danger’.

  However, the fundamental error of the National Assembly was to believe that the

  king would resign himself to his loss of sovereignty and that the people, recently

  awakened, would be content with only a share of it. Herein, Thiers conjectured,

  was to be found a tension and dynamic that would drive the Revolution forward

  towards its final resolution.

  To understand this, Thiers argued, it was sufficient to reflect upon the differ-

  ences between revolutions that had occurred among subject and free peoples. In

  Rome and Athens, the nation and their leaders had argued about who held

  authority. In modern societies, by contrast, the first signs of awakening were

  evident in ‘the most enlightened classes’, only for it progressively to spread

  throughout the entire population. Soon satisfied with the share of power they

  had obtained, the enlightened classes sought to bring the revolution to an end, but

  they could not do so and were ceaselessly harried by those who followed them. For

  the latter, those who had preceded them were the enemy. ‘The simple bourgeois’,

  Thiers explained, ‘is called an aristocrat by the manual worker and is pursued as

  such.’93

  The National Assembly, being the first to challenge an all-powerful authority,

  being wise enough to recognize what was owed to those who had had everything

  and to those who had had nothing, had wished to leave to the former some of its

  power and provide the latter with learning and rights. Yet, from the one they

  encountered resentment, from the other ambition; as a consequence, ‘a war of

  extermination’ was set in motion. The members of the National Assembly were,

  thus, ‘the first men of good will who, shaking off slavery, attempted to found a just

  order . . . but who succumbed through wanting to commit a few to concede

  something and others not to want everything’.94

  The stage was now set for the descent of France into ‘murderous war’. A

  revolution that pitted the base of society against the upper classes was driven by

  envy and violent passions; and, in the case of Robespierre, by a combination of

  purity, vanity, and ‘habitual egoism’. As for Marat, Thiers described a fanatic

  gripped by hatred and obsession, intent on destruction and extermination.95 The

  result, vividly described over several volumes, was a society where the prison and the

  scaffold were a daily reality; where one feared to express an opinion or to see one’s

  friends and family; where merchants were forced to sell goods at ‘fictitious prices’;

  where to display wealth or luxury was dangerous; and where women and the old

  were denied the right to practise their religion. ‘Never’, Thiers wrote, ‘did power

  more violently overturn the habits of a people.’96 Nonetheless, Thiers gave full vent

  92 Thiers, Histoire de la Révolution française, ii. 3–12.

  93 Ibid. 7–8.

  94 Ibid. 8.

  95 Ibid. 217–21.

  96 Ibid. v. 471.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  259

  to the argument that ‘destiny’ had given the Jacobins and their supporters ‘a unique

  and terrible mission’: that of ‘defending the revolution against Europe and the

  Vendée’. ‘Sublime and atrocious’ at one and the same time, of their ‘bloody

  dictatorship’ only ‘the glory of defence’ would remain.97

  The ‘happy catastrophe’ of Robespierre’s fall and execution brought the ‘ascend-

  ing march’ of the Revolution to an end. What followed, in the form of the

  Directory, was a regime which sought to restore order and prosperity and to

  combine this with continued military success. No more glowing account of its

  achievements could have been provided. By the summer of 1796, and following

  one of the ‘most beautiful and extraordinary’ military campaigns in history, France

  was ‘at the height of her power’. She was ‘resplendent in her immortal glory’. The

  storms of the Revolution appeared to have calmed. Commerce and agriculture were

  flourishing. All voices were free to be heard. A government, ‘composed of the

  bourgeoisie, our equals’, ruled the republic with ‘moderation’. Let us not forget,

  Thiers wrote, these ‘immortal days of liberty, greatness, and hope’.98 The decline

  which followed was attributed to continued internal opposition and the plotting of

  the European powers. The repression of the royalists in September 1797, achieved

  through the coup d’état of 18 Fructidor, was viewed by Thiers as ‘a sad but

  inevitable necessity’. Legality was an illusion in times of revolution.99 But, little

  by little, the regime became ‘decayed’ and ‘worn-out’. The government was

  disorganized; factions were ungovernable; everywhere there were signs of social

  collapse and brigandry; military defeat occurred against the Austrians and in Italy.

  In these circumstances, the Republic again seemed in mortal danger. To save the

  situation a ‘force’ was required and that force could only be found in the army. A

  sword was necessary.100 It was to belong to Napoleon Bonaparte. The Revolution,

  therefore, having been in turn monarchical, republican, and democratic in charac-

  ter, finished up by being military and this was so because, ‘in the midst of this

  perpetual struggle with Europe’, it needed to establish itself on a ‘solid and strong’

  foundation.101

  What sense could be made of this turbulent decade? Were the republicans right

  to deplore the immolation of liberty by one of the heroes born of the Revolution?

  According to Thiers, the Revolution, ‘which was to give us liberty, and which

  prepared everything for us to have it one day, was not itself and could not be

  liberty’.102 Rather, it was ‘a great struggle against the old order of things’. Having

  defeated that order in France, it was necessary to defeat it in Europe but such a

  ‘violent struggle’ was not compatible with either the forms or spirit of liberty. Thus,

  if during the period of the National Assembly there had been a brief period of

  liberty, all too quickly it had been replaced by ‘passions and heroism’. With

  97 Ibid. iv. 5. Thiers did not spare his readers the details of the ‘murderous’ repression that took

  place. See his account of the infamous noyades in Nantes: ibid. vi. 399–402.

  98 Ibid. viii. 572–4.

  99 Ibid. ix. 333.

  100 Ibid. x. 409–10.

  101 Ibid. 527.

  102 Ibid.

  260

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  victories won and danger receding, Thiers argued, liberty had returned under the

  Directory, but war with Europe could only be suspended temporarily. The coup

  d’état of 18 Brumaire had therefore been ‘necessary’. Napoleon’s ‘mysterious task’,

  of which he was the ‘involuntary agent’, was not to pursue the cause of liberty—as

  it could not be pursued in the circumstances—but to continue the Revolution

  ‘under monarc
hical forms’. He had done this by mixing his ‘plebeian’ blood with

  the oldest blood of European monarchy. He had blended the peoples of Europe

  together and had carried French laws to Germany, Italy, and Spain. Everywhere he

  had contradicted and shaken what had existed before. In this way, Thiers pro-

  nounced in conclusion, ‘the new society was consolidated under the protection of

  his sword such that liberty would come one day. It has not come, it will come.’103

  In summary, Mignet and Thiers were successful in formulating what might be

  termed a liberal catechism of the Revolution. Seen from this perspective, the

  Revolution was not accidental, but inevitable, with roots deep in French history.

  It was not a conspiracy but had popular support. Its causes were political, rather

  than social and economic. At the outset the Revolution had possessed a purity of

  intention but this had been undermined by the emigration of the aristocracy,

  foreign intervention, and the passions of the people. Circumstances explained the

  resort to terror and the existence of Jacobin dictatorship. Despite its crimes,

  the Revolution established the foundations of a new society upon the ruins of the

  ancien régime and the conditions in which liberty, if not actually realized, could one

  day be attained. To that end, any future liberal revolution had to avoid involvement

  in a foreign war, as it had been war above all that had unleashed the popular

  passions that had ultimately produced despotism.104

  Nevertheless, Mignet and Thiers provided an interpretation of the Revolution

  that was not without ambiguity or even, as Linda Orr has suggested, a ‘basic

  schizophrenia’.105 If the notion of inevitability could serve to vindicate the Revolu-

  tion, it was not at all clear—beyond some vague idea of the movement of civiliza-

  tion—what the determining factors in this history were. Next, while both authors

  were without hesitation in their condemnation of despotism, their critique was

  undoubtedly weakened by an enthusiasm for national glory and an admiration for

  the military achievements of the 1790s and the Empire. It is interesting to note that

  Thiers later felt the need to refute the criticism that, by fostering the image of

  Napoleon’s greatness, he had contributed to the 1851 coup d’état by Louis Napo-

  leon.106 More fundamentally, to the horror of their conservative opponents,

  Mignet and Thiers appeared to be suggesting that the crimes of the Revolution

  could be justified in terms of its positive achievements. Just as importantly, to judge

  that the Revolution would come to an end with the victory of the bourgeois

  representatives of the Third Estate was to imagine and hope that the people

  103 Thiers, Histoire de la Révolution française, 530.

  104 This view was restated by Thiers following the revolution of 1830 when he affirmed that it was

  in the interest of the revolution to want peace: see Thiers, La Monarchie de 1830 (1831), 101.

  105 Linda Orr, Headless History: Nineteenth-Century French Historiography of the Revolution (Ithaca,

  NY, 1990), 19.

  106 See J. P. T. Bury and R. P. Tombs, Thiers 1797–1877: A Political Life (London, 1986), 151.

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  261

  would acquiesce to their exclusion from the political processes of the new order.

  This was to prove recklessly optimistic.

  All the same, it was to the creation of such an order that Mignet and Thiers were

  to devote their political energies over the next decade, the two friends from the

  south of France playing a leading role in the agitation that led to the final departure

  of the Bourbon monarchy in July 1830. The central political objective was now to

  transform the relegitimated ideas of 1789 into a set of stable and regular represen-

  tative institutions. In those circumstances, as Guizot rallied the liberal cause to the

  defence of moderate constitutional government and the new regime turned its back

  on the populist uprisings across Europe, royalist attempts to discredit the Revolu-

  tion appeared to have been largely vanquished. However, as François Furet has

  observed, ‘the opponents of the new Orleanist regime suddenly began to fly the

  banner of 1793: they clamoured for the Republic and the Montagnard Constitu-

  tion, not for the bastard regime offered by the Constituent Assembly’. In short, the

  battle grounds of the historiography of the Revolution were about to be redrawn.

  I I

  Much of this new historiography was socialist in inspiration. The ‘dominant idea’,

  according to Michel Winock, was that ‘after the defeat of the Jacobins, the

  bourgeoisie had profited from the Revolution; and therefore that it was necessary

  to reclaim it for the people, in the name of equality and fraternity’.107 What the

  liberals had both excused and deplored in the Revolution was now to be celebrated

  and praised. No longer was the grand narrative of the Revolution to be the struggle

  between the aristocracy and the Third Estate but that between the bourgeoisie and

  the people. The tyrant Robespierre was to be recast as the very incarnation of the

  Revolution’s emancipatory message of earthly salvation. Rather than bringing the

  Revolution to a close, the goal was to reverse its betrayal and to allow it to be seen as

  a prefiguration of a new social order. Bourgeois sensibilities were to give way before

  proletarian messianism.

  Broadly representative of this new interpretation of the Revolution was the

  monumental forty-volume Histoire parlementaire de la Révolution française, written

  and compiled by Philippe Buchez and his friend Pierre Roux and published in

  instalments between 1834 and 1839.108 Unlike many nineteenth-century histories,

  it is not one that has withstood the test of time, but, in its day, it was both widely

  consulted and deeply influential.109 For the most part, each volume consisted of

  primary documents gleaned from official reports, parliamentary sessions, bro-

  chures, newspapers, and so on, but interspersed among these was a running

  107 Michel Winock, Les Voix de la Liberté: Les Écrivains engagés au XIXe siècle (2001), 287.

  108 Buchez had earlier set out the philosophical and religious basis of his ideas in his Introduction à la

  science de l’histoire (1833). At the end of the 1820s he had broken with the Saint-Simonian movement

  and at this point had abandoned science for religion.

  109 Buchez and Roux imagined that their collection of material might act as a ‘guide for future

  historians’: Histoire parlementaire de la Révolution française, xvii. 186.

  262

  History, Revolution, and Terror

  interpretative commentary. In addition, the early volumes provided a preface

  loosely summarizing the broader philosophical and religious themes underpinning

  the argument. What makes this account especially intriguing was the ambition to

  wed the Revolution to Catholicism, Jacobinism to religion.110 The ‘beginning and

  the end of the Revolution’, Buchez and Roux declared, ‘are contained in these

  words: liberty, equality, fraternity, or, in other words, in this goal: the realization in

  society of Christian morality’.111

  This was made evident in the very first sentence. ‘The French Revolution’, it

  declared, ‘is the most
advanced and final outcome of modern civilization, and the

  whole of modern civilization derives from the Gospels’. This was a fact both

  ‘irrefutable’ and ‘incontestable’.112 The error, Buchez and Roux claimed, was to

  have continued to see the Revolution as an accident, as the product of financial

  insolvency, governmental mistakes, aristocratic insolence, royal scandal, and per-

  sonal ambition. Indeed, they went so far as to suggest that ‘this profound ignorance

  of the goal of humanity’ was not only the cause of all the Revolution’s misfortunes

  but also why, in 1833, it could still be dismissed only as disorder rather than as the

  foundation of right. But, they next argued, to be perceived in this way the

  Revolution had to be located upon a ‘Christian soil’. Then it would be seen that

  the ‘axioms’ of the Revolution were ‘laws long taught, long pursued, and approach-

  ing realization’. To claim, therefore, that the people had given themselves over to

  revolution in order to secure material well-being was to insult those ‘dead martyrs’

  who had ‘sacrificed themselves’ to ‘the great ideas of equality and fraternity’. It was

  also to fail to understand that it had taken fourteen centuries of constant effort to

  produce ‘this proud nation’ which, of itself and without a leader, had risen up as

  one. Thus, Buchez and Roux affirmed in their introduction, ‘the revolutionary idea

  has a history which is that of the world, and where we learn, at the same time, why

  each people occupies the place it does and why our nation is the first among

  modern nations’.113

  Like their predecessors, Buchez and Roux prefaced their history with a précis of

  French history. Resting firmly upon the conviction that France was not the result of

  Frankish conquest, they unhesitatingly asserted that the French nation emerged as a

  consequence of the desire to protect the Gauls and to defend and strengthen

  Catholicism. The whole of European history, they claimed, could be understood

  in just two words: France and the Church. With this historical preface to the

  Revolution completed, Buchez and Roux lost no time in setting out their argu-

  ment. From the summer of 1789, ‘the bourgeoisie sought to confiscate the

  Revolution for its own benefit’.114 To protect its newly acquired dominance it

 

‹ Prev